Insight in Psychiatry PDF
Insight in Psychiatry PDF
Insight in Psychiatry PDF
Insight in Psychiatry
Questions concerning the nature of insight in patients with mental illness have interested clini-
cians for a long time. To what extent can patients understand disorders which affect their men-
tal function? Does insight carry a prognostic value? Is impaired insight determined by the illness
or are other factors important? Despite considerable research examining insight in patients with
psychoses, non-psychotic disorders and chronic organic brain syndromes, results are inconclu-
sive and insight remains a source of some mystification.
IVANA S. MARKOVÁ examines the problems involved in studying insight in patients with men-
tal illness in order to provide a clearer understanding of the factors that determine its clinical
manifestation. She puts forward a new model to illustrate the relationship between different
components of insight in theoretical and clinical terms, and points to directions for future
research.
Dr IVANA S. MARKOVÁ is a Senior lecturer in psychiatry with an interest in insight, descriptive
psychopathology, the epistemology of mental phenomena and neuropsychiatry. She holds fur-
ther qualifications in history and philosophy of science. Her work in insight is widely published,
both in journals and book chapters.
Insight in Psychiatry
IVANA S. MARKOVÁ
cambridge university press
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of urls
for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not
guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
Every effort has been made in preparing this publication to provide accurate and
up-to-date information which is in accord with accepted standards and practice at the
time ofpublication.Although case histories are drawn from actual cases,every effort has
been made to disguise the identities ofthe individuals involved.Nevertheless, the
authors,editors and publishers can make no warranties that the information contained
herein is totally free from error,not least because clinical standards are constantly
changing through research and regulation.The authors,editors and publishers therefore
disclaim all liability for direct or consequential damages resulting from the use
ofmaterial contained in this publication.Readers are strongly advised to pay careful
attention to information provided by the manufacturer ofany drugs or equipment that
they plan to use.
Contents
Preface ix
References 293
Index 327
v
For my mother and babi
DRH
Preface
Throughout history, human beings have been variously occupied with enquiries
into self-knowledge and self-understanding. In Western cultures these themes have
persistently raised vital and profound questions not just for individuals but, par-
ticularly in the last two to three hundred years, for the sciences and humanities.
Psychiatry has been no exception to this. However, although as we shall see in this
book, interest in insight in psychiatry has a relatively long past, it is only in the last
fifteen or twenty years that psychiatry has become engrossed with the empirical
question concerning the presence and nature of insight in patients with mental
disorders. It is a question that encompasses many facets. From one perspective, it
addresses in a practical way the degree of understanding patients have about their
conditions. In turn, this raises important issues relating to clinician-patient com-
munication and carries implications for the management of the individual patient.
From another perspective, however, the question of patients’ insight reaches to the
core of our understanding of mental disorders themselves. It forces us to consider,
for example, how mental functions might act and interact in health and illness.
Can mental disorders have selective effects on mental function? To what extent can
mental dysfunction in one area affect mental function or capacity in another area?
The question of insight from yet a different perspective is wider still and focuses
enquiry on the nature of self in relation to mental illness. Here, questions arise
concerning the sorts of factors that may contribute to self-knowledge and to what
degree these might differ in the ‘healthy’ individual and the person with mental ill-
ness. To what extent can the self be considered independent of the mental illness
that disturbs the very functions which are thought to constitute it? The question of
insight in patients with mental disorders is clearly not simple. Moreover, the nature
of the issues raised demands explorative processes which straddle medical, psy-
chological, philosophical and historical approaches.
A great deal of research has been carried out in order to answer different aspects
of the question of insight in psychiatry. Most such research has involved empirical
studies exploring insight in different clinical populations and examining relation-
ships between patients’ insight and a variety of clinical and individual variables.
ix
x Preface
A range of innovative measures to assess insight have been devised and approaches
to the study of insight have varied from one clinical area to another. Interestingly,
outcomes of such studies both within a particular clinical area and between differ-
ent clinical areas have been striking in their variability. Consequently, it remains
difficult to arrive at consistent answers with respect to insight in psychiatry.
Methodological issues aside, such variable study outcomes highlight the presence
of complexities around the conceptualisation of insight and its ensuing translation
into clinical forms amenable to empirical assessment. It follows that research is
needed at a conceptual level to explore the notion of insight in depth, to identify
and disentangle the complexities that contribute to many of the problems around
the study of insight.
This book is specifically concerned with the complexities surrounding the study
of insight in psychiatry. It sets out to examine the nature of these complexities in
order to help clarify our understanding of insight, to detail the factors important
in determining insight clinically and to specify assumptions underlying the clinical
phenomena elicited. Thus, on the basis of historical, clinical and conceptual analy-
ses, complexities inherent to the concept of insight are defined and localised at var-
ious theoretical and clinical levels. This allows for the formulation of a structure
for insight which delineates constitutive components and their interrelationships.
In addition, this enables the differentiation of phenomena of insight to be deter-
mined in the context of a particular clinical situation. In turn, this provides a basis
on which future empirical research on insight can be systematically developed.
The study of insight itself is a major enterprise for it entails work not only in
diverse areas, both clinical and non-clinical, but also on many levels. As such, this
is beyond the scope of this book. Instead, the book attempts to preserve a fairly
strict focus on unravelling the theoretical and practical difficulties faced by empir-
ical research on insight. Why is insight so difficult to capture clinically? How can it
be measured? Does it make sense to try to measure it in a quantitative form? What
is it about insight that makes it complicated to define or, rather, to define in an
operational way? These are the sorts of questions that are addressed by this book
with the purpose of both furthering clinical understanding of insight and devel-
oping new directions for future empirical work. Whilst approaching these issues
from an epistemological perspective, there is no appropriate room here for a wider
philosophical enquiry that might explore the notion of insight in all its possible
metaphysical dimensions.
The book concentrates on insight in psychiatry but even within this remit has
had to be selective and to set boundaries to the amount and types of material
examined. Thus, both for the maintaining of the book’s focus and for reasons of
space, there are areas that have not been covered and which are important in future
work on the subject. In this regard, for example, insight into medical illness has not
xi Preface
been included within the review section. Emphasis has been given to studies on
insight in general psychiatric disorders and in dementia. Areas which have clearly
contributed to the approaches taken to the exploration of insight in such disorders
have also been included, namely, psychological and neurological approaches.
Within general psychiatry, current studies on insight have focused predominantly
on the psychoses and affective disorders and this material is therefore reviewed and
analysed in the book. Less empirical research has been carried out on insight in
other psychiatric disorders, notably, neurotic, stress-related, dissociative disorders
or anxiety states and this is an area which again would be important to study in the
future. In fact, much of the work that has examined insight in these particular clin-
ical areas has come from the psychoanalytic psychological perspective and this is
covered in Chapter 2. The clinical reviews themselves are not aimed to be fully
comprehensive though the bulk of the work in the various areas has been covered.
For the purposes of the book, however, the clinical reviews are intended primarily
to illustrate and define the essential conceptual issues arising from the empirical
studies of insight within the respective areas. The historical chapter is restricted to
examining the concept of insight in Western cultures. It is further limited, for prac-
tical reasons, to literature in English, French and German languages.
The book is divided into two parts. The first part (Chapters 1–5) reviews and
analyses insight into mental illness from its evolution as an independent concept to
the ways in which insight has been conceptualised and explored in clinical psychi-
atry and related disciplines. Chapter 1 examines the concept of insight in mental
illness from a historical perspective, concentrating predominantly on the views
held by the late nineteenth century French alienists. This focus is the result of,
firstly, the importance and influence of nineteenth century French psychopathol-
ogy on Western psychiatry in general. Secondly, the French debates on this issue
were particularly explicit in showing how ideas on awareness and insight devel-
oped in the context of the changing philosophical and medical-pathological views
at the time. Chapter 2 explores insight from the psychological perspective and
emphasises both the differences in conceptualisation of insight held by the Gestalt,
cognitive and psychodynamic schools and the ways in which these perspectives
have influenced approaches to insight in clinical psychiatry. Chapter 3 reviews the
empirical work on insight in general psychiatry. It shows the wide range of defini-
tions of insight employed by the studies, the different approaches taken to assess
insight empirically and the mixed and inconclusive study outcomes. Chapter 4
examines work on insight and awareness carried out in neurological states and, as
such, forms an introduction to Chapter 5. In comparison with the ‘psychiatric’
notion, impaired insight or unawareness is viewed as a much narrower concept
and approaches taken to its assessment reflect this different conception. The
importance of unawareness or anosognosia in this narrow sense is stressed in the
xii Preface
light of its influence on approaches to the study of insight in dementia and in gen-
eral psychiatry. Chapter 5 reviews the empirical studies on insight in dementia. As
in general psychiatry, outcomes of such studies are variable and inconclusive.
Likewise, a range of methods have been developed to assess insight and these
have, more particularly, been influenced by approaches taken by various clinical
disciplines.
The second part of the book (Chapters 6–9) addresses the conceptual issues
raised from the earlier chapters and proposes a structure for insight that can pro-
vide a useful framework for understanding insight and its determinants. Chapter 6
focuses on the meaning and nature of insight. A distinction is made between the
concept and phenomenon of insight and the problems related to each are specified.
In turn, the implications such problems carry for the empirical study of insight are
explored. Chapter 7 examines the relational aspects of insight. It shows how differ-
ent ‘objects’ of insight assessment determine different clinical phenomena of
insight and emphasises the implications of this for the structure of insight and its
empirical assessment. Chapter 8 argues, on theoretical and empirical grounds, for
a meaningful distinction to be made between awareness and insight. Distinguishing
features between awareness and insight are described in terms of their quantitative
and qualitative aspects. Chapter 9 presents a schematic representation of the struc-
ture of insight that is based on the distinction between awareness and insight. It
shows how the phenomenon of insight can be placed within this structure, deter-
mined by it and also by the ‘object’ of insight assessment as well as the measures
used for its elicitation. The implications for understanding insight and for future
research are then discussed.
The book is based on thoughts that have developed and changed over a number
of years. I have used and built on material presented in my doctoral thesis
(Glasgow University, 1998) and on work already published. I would like to thank
the publishers of the British Journal of Psychiatry, Comprehensive Psychiatry,
Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, Neurology Psychiatry & Brain Research and
Psychopathology for allowing me to use materials from papers of mine which
appeared in their pages. Special thanks are owed to Dr. German E. Berrios from the
Department of Psychiatry, Cambridge University, with whom I have had countless
discussions and explored many of the ideas presented here. His deep scholarly
knowledge has stimulated and inspired my own thinking and much of the concep-
tual work developed here has been the result of a joint struggle. In addition, he has
pointed me towards numerous invaluable bibliographical sources crucial for the
historical section of the book. I would also like to thank members of the AWARE
project group (Awareness in early-stage dementia: understanding, assessment and
implications for early intervention) for useful comments and thoughts in relation
to the work on insight in dementia: Dr. Linda Clare, University of Wales, Bangor;
xiii Preface
Mrs. Geraldine Kenny, North Eastern Health Board, Dublin; Dr. Barbara Romero,
Bad Aibling, Germany; Professor Frans Verhey, University of Maastricht,
Netherlands; Professor Michael Wang, University of Leicester and Professor Bob
Woods, University of Wales, Bangor. In particular, I am grateful to Dr. Linda Clare
for discussions which helped to clarify some of the theoretical aspects of this book.
I am grateful also to the University of Hull for their encouragement of this work.
Finally, I would like to thank my family for their enormous support and also my
friends and colleagues who have shown extreme patience.
Part I
1
1
Historical overview
places its own constraints on the types of patients and the sorts of disorders included
within specific categories at a particular time. This in turn affects the perspective from
which different concepts are held. Consequently, focusing solely on individual discip-
linary historical narratives might obviate the important contribution of the indi-
viduation of clinical disorders themselves towards the conceptualisation of insight.
How then to attempt a general historical account of insight in psychiatry? Berrios
(1994a; 1996) has suggested that one way of approaching the construction of a
valid historical account of symptoms or illness is to make an explicit distinction
between the histories of the terms, the behaviours and the concepts relating to the
object of inquiry. Differentiating between the histories of these aspects of insight
helps to illustrate and clarify how the meanings of insight may change not only in
time but also in relation to different contexts, whether these are social, cultural,
intellectual, etc. This approach shall thus be followed here. However, it has to be
emphasised that such distinctions in relation to the histories of insight do not
entail their independence. For example, when considering insight as a ‘behaviour’,
then clearly this cannot be considered as an a-theoretical object. Instead, interpreting
a behaviour as insightful or insightless is the result of both overt and covert concep-
tualisation. This, in turn, is dependent on a background of related concepts such as
ideas about the self, about the workings of the mind, about illness and mental ill-
ness, etc. These themselves are determined in part by the views and knowledge held
during the particular historical period of the subject. In addition, insight as a
‘behaviour’ does not directly reflect an ontological entity in the way that, for example,
a paretic gait might reflect a specific paresis. This does not mean that there cannot
be a neurobiological basis to insight but simply that at this stage, elicitation of insight
as a behaviour depends much more on conceptualisation and interpretation.
This chapter thus first examines some of the historical contexts forming the
background to insight and related notions. Then a brief overview of the history of
the term ‘insight’ is given, followed by an account of the history of the concept and
behaviour of insight. The histories of the concept and behaviour of insight are dis-
cussed together because of their particular interdependence.
In medicine, the concept of insight into madness seems to have started appearing
in a consistent manner in the early part of the nineteenth century when the clin-
ical descriptions offered by alienists began to include observations concerning
patients’ awareness of their pathological state. In 1820, Georget, commenting on
the received view of madness [folie] as intellectual disorders in which patients were
unaware, remarked how whilst this was true for most patients, there was neverthe-
less a small number of patients ‘who are well able to assess their mental state, who
5 Historical overview
tell you: I have an ill head, a disturbed spirit, I can no longer think, I know that
my thoughts are disordered, I am behaving badly – but I cannot do otherwise …’
(Georget, 1820, p. 94, my translation). And by the middle and late nineteenth century,
specific debates concerning the question of insight and its relationship to different
aspects of mental illness were already taking place (Société Médico-Psychologique,
1869/1870).
In order to try to understand why insight into mental illness became an issue of
interest at this particular time and what factors helped shape its emergence, it is
necessary to look at the historical space in which this was happening. Two particu-
lar contexts will be considered here. Firstly, a brief look is given at the way in which
insight and self-knowledge were conceived in terms of the general thinking around
this time. Secondly, the changing views around the conceptualisation of madness
itself helped to influence the way in which insight into madness was conceived and
debated and, for the purposes of this chapter, more focus will be given to this area.
this way …’ (Descartes, 1648/1991, p. 335). He assumed, as did Locke later, that every
experience of the individual was accompanied by self-awareness (Perkins, 1969).
Indeed, Locke went further to say that the identity of the self was determined by
consciousness (Locke, 1700/1979) though the notion of self throughout this time
was also a changing concept exerting independent as well as interdependent influ-
ences on the conceptualisation of mental illness and psychopathology (Berrios,
1993; Berrios & Marková, 2003). Nevertheless, it can be understood that con-
sciousness or awareness of self in this context was conceived as intrinsic to thinking,
feeling and experiencing rather than as a separate system that could assess such
mental operations independently.
It was later, in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, during the Enlightenment
and the period known as Romanticism, that the self as a whole being became the
real focus of thought. Self-awareness obtained the meaning of self-reflection and
self-consciousness in a much wider sense. In contrast to Descartes who focused
predominantly on the individual’s self, the Romanticists and some of the philoso-
phers at the time argued that self-consciousness develops mutually with the con-
sciousness of others. By being aware of others as reflexive beings, one is able to look
at oneself through the eyes of others. One becomes the object of one’s own obser-
vation (Mead, 1934; 1936). As a result, introspection became a prevailing theme of
that time (Boring, 1953). The importance of the subjectivity of inner experiences
was carried over to the psychiatry of the nineteenth century and legitimised the
elicitation of psychopathology based on patients’ accounts (Berrios, 1996).
Another important psychological concept emerging in the nineteenth century,
and influencing psychiatry and the conceptualisation of insight was that of com-
prehension (Verstehen), as developed in different ways by Brentano (1874/1973),
Dilthey (1976) and eventually, Freud, Husserl and Jaspers, amongst others (Berrios,
1992). This concept encompassed more than ‘understanding’ and more than ‘look-
ing into one’s mind’ (as suggested by introspection). Instead, it aimed to capture
the totality of one’s mental and existential state including non-conscious aspects.
The conceptualisation of insight caught within this frame thus demanded more
than an intellectual awareness of being ill but called on deeper processes involving
emotions and volitions, and that extended to a self that embraced a wider and
richer concept. The way in which such a holistic notion of insight was envisaged
depended on the particular school of thought. For example, Brentano related this
to his concept of intentionality and invoked a ‘third consciousness’: ‘Experience
shows that there exist in us not only a presentation and a judgement, but fre-
quently a third kind of consciousness of the mental act, namely a feeling which
refers to this act, pleasure or displeasure which we feel towards this act’ (Brentano,
1874/1973, p. 143). Dilthey, on the other hand, emphasised a different aspect of the
self as the focus of ‘verstehen’, namely, experience or ‘Erlebnis’. This latter concept
7 Historical overview
… the examples of manic patients with fury but without délire and without any incoherence in
their ideas, are far from being rare in both women and men, and they go to show how much
lesions of the will can be distinct from those of the understanding, even though they frequently
occur together.
Pinel (1809, p. 102, my translation)
Questioning how such cases could be explained if the views held by Locke and
Condillac were followed, he went on to note that patients could appear to have
9 Historical overview
lesions of the affective faculties only, or even isolated lesions involving attention,
memory, thoughts or judgement. Such observations were difficult to reconcile
with the doctrine of indivisibility of human understanding (Pinel, 1801).
More explicit and distinctive still was the concept of partial insanity promoted by
Pinel’s disciple, Esquirol and his own followers, namely that of ‘monomania’. The
monomanias comprised a range of partial insanities where the partial aspect
referred mainly to the content of the ideas/affects/behaviours around which the
madness was observed to be circumscribed. As a result, types of monomanias were
identified and named such as erotic monomania, homicidal monomania, drunk-
enness monomania, etc. (Esquirol, 1838). The concept of monomania became
extremely popular in the early nineteenth century both as a diagnosis made fre-
quently by alienists and as a defence used by lawyers in criminal proceedings
(Goldstein, 1987). In fact, challenges made by lawyers against the concept of total
insanity (as well as the opposing arguments of the prosecutors) had been prom-
inent for several hundred years beforehand (Orange, 1892). It was only when madness
became the focus of more specific medical interest (rather than a social category) and
converged with the legal interest that such debates became significant contributors to
the questions posed around the existence of partial insanities. The term ‘monomania’,
however, lost popularity and by the middle of the century was almost lost while
related concepts were developed and replaced it. What is clear, however, in many
debates about monomanias and partial insanity at that time (Guislain, 1852; Brierre
de Boismont, 1853; Delasiauve, 1853; Falret, 1866), was that discussions seemed to
be hampered by inconsistencies and sometimes contradictions concerning under-
standing of what the ‘partial’ aspect of insanity was referring to. Thus, in the case of
monomania, Esquirol himself defined this variously from a partial délire, i.e. a délire
concentrated on one or a few objects (giving rise to the types of monomanias named
above), to disorders characterised by partial lesions of the intellect or affect or the
will (giving rise to ‘monomanie intellectuelle’, ‘monomanie affective’ and ‘monomanie
instinctive’, respectively) (Esquirol, 1819; 1838). In addition, he distinguished between
lypemania and monomania on the basis of exaltation of ideas, psychological and
physical excitement in the latter (Esquirol, 1819), thereby, invoking yet another cri-
terial form. In other words, clinical observations and their analyses were occurring
at different levels and distinctions between different partial insanities were made
simultaneously on the basis of different categories. Hence, some distinctions were
made empirically, sometimes on the basis of the contents of patients’ madness, and
other times on the basis of the types of emotions or energy affecting the patients.
Yet other distinctions were made theoretically on the basis of postulated lesions of
the mind. A similar point is made by Kageyama (1984) in relation to Pinel’s classi-
fication of madness and it is likely that these inconsistencies also played a part in
the related debates around insight and awareness into illness (see below).
10 Historical and clinical
localisable to specific organs in the brain. However, he rejected the notion that
faculties comprised of understanding, will, memory, etc. and proposed instead the
idea of specific fundamental faculties which enabled differentiation of characteristics
between individuals. In other words, his concept of faculties was that of mental qual-
ities, constitutive of both mind and character, e.g. pride/self-esteem, friendship/
attachment, sense of colours, music, verbal memory, memory for languages, etc.
(Spoerl, 1936). Arousing debates and strong criticisms (Gordon, 1815; Lélut, 1837;
1843), the phrenology movement was nevertheless important. It influenced the
views of alienists in early nineteenth century Britain (Cooter, 1979) and France
where Gall and Spurzheim’s courses were well attended by the alienists of the second
decade e.g. Georget and Leuret (Goldstein, 1987).
Alongside the debates around faculties of the mind, ideas about partial insanity
and the space in which insight into madness could become conceptualised were
also shaped by changing views concerning the causes of insanity. These in turn
related to changes in the notion of disease itself. An anonymous historian stated
in 1840: ‘all explanations of mental illness boil down to three options: they are
localised in the brain … or in the soul … or in both’ (Fabre, 1840, p. 118). Supporters
of the anatomo-clinical view of disease, including madness (Ackerknecht, 1967),
were thus more able to conceive and accept the notion of partial insanity and hence
also the possibility of insight into the diseased mental faculties. In contrast, those
who believed that insanity was exclusively sited in the mind or soul (l’âme) had dif-
ficulty in conceiving partial insanity and insight into illness since the soul was, in
terms of the philosophy of the period, indivisible and could not become partially
diseased.
The shift from the view that madness was as an all-or-none ontological entity to
the possibility that madness could be partial in different ways carried major impli-
cations for the alienists in the nineteenth century. In the context of the factors
described above, important discussions were taking place concerning the nature
and classification of mental disorders. In particular, the different forms of faculty
psychology permeating the thinking of the alienists, allowed for a more modular
conception of the mind with more or less specific cerebral localisation. This in turn
led to debates concerning the organisation and function of mental faculties, and
their role in mental illness (Société Médico-Psychologique, 1866). Delasiauve (1853)
argued that there was a categorical difference between the intellectual faculties and
the instinctive/affective faculties. Whilst the former were interdependent, the latter,
by contrast, could operate and be affected independently. Falret (1866), on the
other hand, maintained that whilst it was useful to distinguish between independ-
ent mental faculties for study purposes, it could not be assumed that mental facul-
ties operated independently in the healthy mind or could be injured independently
in the ill mind. He believed, like Maudsley did some years later, that madness even
12 Historical and clinical
when it affected predominantly one or a few faculties, had its effects on all. Others
disagreed and held that insanity could be specific to different faculties (Delasiauve,
1866; Société Médico-Psychologique, 1866). In a different vein, Fournet (1870)
focused on the importance of studying the relationship between mental events and
events occurring at the cellular level of the brain. He emphasised, however, that
mental activities should not be reduced to brain mechanisms and that psycho-
logical perspectives had to be preserved. It is within the context of such debates, in
the spaces formed by the conceptualisation of partial insanities and the discussions
around the independence/interdependence of mental faculties, that it became pos-
sible to conceive the existence of an insanity which could have awareness of itself.
Thus, insight and insightlessness could become meaningful concepts, variables in
their own right which could be examined in relation to and independent of insanity.
It is interesting that the term ‘insight’ (and its equivalents) only exists in this uni-
tary form in the North and West Germanic families of languages. The Latin lan-
guages (e.g. French, Spanish, Italian, Portuguese, etc.) do not have a corresponding
unitary term and, hence, translation of insight into these languages depends on the
specific meaning of the term intended in a particular context. For example, a well-
known nineteenth century German–French dictionary translates the German
word for ‘insight’ (‘Einsicht’), as: ‘inspection, examen, connaissance de cause, bon
sens, jugement’ (Rose, 1878). Individually, all these terms carry somewhat different
meanings and hence the term chosen in a particular situation will vary according
to the specific need of the speaker. It is of note that, within the countries of the
Germanic languages, there has been more interest shown in the concept of insight
in the general thinking. Whether or not having a unitary term (insight or Einsicht)
carries implications for the conceptualisation of insight as an ontological entity
has not, however, been determined.
For the German term ‘Einsicht’, Grimm and Grimm (1862) propose as equiva-
lents the Latin terms ‘intelligentia’ and ‘judicium’, and suggest that the term gained
wider usage in the work of Goethe and Kant (Pauleikhoff & Mester, 1973).
Adelung, at the beginning of the nineteenth century, defined it as: ‘Das sinneinse-
hen in eine Sache’ [seeing into the meaning or sense of something] (Adelung, 1811,
Vol. 1). Ritter claims that the Middle German term ‘însehen’ was present in
Medieval mystical writings and meant ‘hineinsehen’ [looking into or inside], and
that J.C. Günther at the beginning of the eighteenth century discarded the religious
denotation and used ‘Einsicht’ as equivalent to personal evidence (Ritter, 1972,
Vol. 2). In addition, Ritter suggests that the ‘psychological’ meaning introduced
by Köhler (see Chapter 2) was a deviation in that it simply meant ‘intelligence’
13 Historical overview
and hence was closer to the old Aristotelian meaning of phronêsis (‘thought or
understanding’).
As far as English is concerned, the Oxford English Dictionary (2002) states that the
original notion of insight referred to ‘internal sight’, i.e. with the eyes of the mind
or understanding and provides a set of definitions generally embracing the same
metaphor, e.g. internal sight, mental vision or perception, discernment; the fact of
penetrating with the eyes of the understanding into the inner character or hidden
nature of things, a glimpse or view beneath the surface, the faculty or power of thus
seeing.
In terms of the clinical usages of the term ‘insight’, i.e. its use in relation to
mental illness, some early references to the terms can be seen in Pick (1882) as
‘Krankheitseinsicht’ or insight into illness. Similarly, the term ‘insightlessness’ was
used in Krafft-Ebing: ‘in the later stages of insanity, where delusions have become
organised or mental disintegration has ensued, the patient is completely insightless
[einsichtslos] about his disease state’ (Krafft-Ebing, 1893, p. 102, my translation).
Whilst there are some difficulties in arriving at a meaning that is common to the
word ‘insight’ given the differences in historical roots and terminologies between
the European countries as touched on above, there seems to be a more consistent
conceptualisation of the notion as used in clinical practice. The history of the con-
cept of insight into madness is necessarily embedded in the histories of related
concepts such as reason, consciousness and self-knowledge as well as in the histor-
ies of views around the nature of disease and insanity. Having considered some of
the historical contexts in which the concept of insight emerged, as a phenomenon
that could be examined in relation to, and independent of, madness, this section
will be concerned with the nature of the concept of insight itself and how this was
conceived in the psychiatry of the nineteenth century until the present day.
p. 387, my translation). Hence, lack of awareness into one’s state could not be used
as a criterion of madness in all cases.
A major debate specifically concerning awareness of mental illness (‘la discussion
sur les aliénés avec conscience de leur état’, Société Médico-Psychologique, 1870) was
held by the Société Médico-Psychologique in 1869/1870, and again, to a lesser
extent, in 1875. These discussions were held in the context of medico-legal con-
cerns in relation to determining responsibility of patients/individuals for criminal
and civil acts. In addition, however, the debates on awareness of mental illness
extended into related areas including the nature of madness itself, the faculties of
the mind, the notion of free will, the concept of self, and underlying brain lesions
or processes. Awareness of mental illness was discussed in relation to all these areas
and was, consequently, immersed and shaped by the problems that were being
faced in trying to clarify the latter. It is difficult, therefore, to obtain a clear defin-
ition or conceptualisation of insight in isolation. However, the debates did begin to
identify a possible structure to insight both in terms of clinical importance and in
terms of possible components.
Concerning the question of legal responsibility for criminal acts, most alienists
(Delasiauve, 1866; 1870; Falret, 1866; 1870; Billod, 1870; Girard de Gailleux, 1870;
Maury, 1870; Morel, 1870) argued that patients could have awareness of their
insane state and yet would be powerless against the urges/impulses arising from
their madness that drove them to commit abnormal acts. Hence, they should not
be held legally responsible for such behaviours. Insight or awareness was thus con-
ceived as a form of passive observation made on the part of the sane aspects of the
patient’s mind, of the abnormal urges, feelings and thoughts produced by the
insanity. The passivity of such observation was couched in terms such as ‘spectator’
(Morel, 1870) or ‘witness’ (Billod, 1870). Emphasising the importance of distin-
guishing between reason and awareness of illness, Morel (1870, p. 116) observed
that some mad patients preserved their ability to reason and yet had no awareness of
being insane. Other patients, however, could have a weakened reason which was
unable to prevent them from committing criminal acts and, nevertheless, they had
awareness of their insanity (‘aliénés irréponsables mais non des aliénés inconscients’).
In addition, the awareness of one’s mental state and actions was explicitly distin-
guished from awareness of the right and wrong of one’s actions (Morel, 1870). The
main conclusion, however, was that the ability to observe one’s madness did not
confer the ability to resist its manifestations and consequences. This view was chal-
lenged by Fournet (1870) who claimed that awareness of illness actually implied
the presence of some degree of reason and, hence, the amount of reason available
to the patient would determine the amount of responsibility for his acts. In other
words, he argued that the degree of responsibility for a criminal act was propor-
tionate to the amount of the patient’s reason. Fournet’s position was based on his
16 Historical and clinical
Admissions to asylum
Numbers of patients with
awareness of mental illness Males (n 378) Females (n 350)
Total numbers showing awareness 61 (in 55 of these, 19 (in five of these, madness
madness followed followed alcohol excess)
alcohol excess)
Numbers with complete awareness 49 12
Numbers with incomplete awareness 12 7
views about the central role of the self in the concept of insanity (see below) and
his arguments were not generally upheld.
Discussions on awareness of mental states also raised questions concerning the
nature of mental illness or insanity. Morel (1870) pointed out that patients ranged
from having no awareness of their insanity to having full awareness and suggested
that the extent of awareness held by patients depended on the site of the lesion
causing the insanity. Thus, different insanities, with different aetiologies, not only
showed different patterns of symptoms and manifestations but also were associ-
ated with different amounts of awareness (Girard de Gailleux, 1870; Morel, 1870).
Billod (1870), reporting one of the earliest ‘empirical’ studies on awareness of ill-
ness, found that the number of patients with awareness of their pathological state
was much lower than the number of patients who lacked awareness and that
awareness was much commoner in patients whose insanity was the result of alco-
holism. He presented his own figures (see Table 1.1) and divided patients into
those with complete awareness and those with incomplete awareness of their mor-
bid state.
His distinction between complete and incomplete awareness was interesting and
raised again the issue of whether patients with awareness should be considered as
truly insane. In essence, he first of all divided patients into two categories:
1 Those patients who were not aware of their pathological state, i.e. they were aware
of strange experiences, hallucinations, disordered thoughts, etc. but attributed
those wrongly.
2 Those who were aware of their pathological state, i.e. were aware of being insane.
(i) Patients with incomplete awareness: They were aware of their pathological
state but nevertheless believed in the reality of their delusions/abnormal
17 Historical overview
of totality of a person and being subject, both passively and actively, to the changes
produced by mental disorder. Thus, he remarked, that in a number of mad patients,
this feeling of totality of the person is profoundly changed such that awareness can no
longer perceive the external world in the same way as before. Where these changes are
complete as in some cases of lypemania, hypochondria and various possession states,
then the patient becomes another personality and his awareness, his ability to perceive
and judge come under the auspices of that new personality. In other words, through its
direct connection to the self, Dagonet viewed awareness as being capable of transform-
ation by the same factors producing the madness or changes to the self. Further-
more, because of its active nature, the awareness in this new form ‘contributes to the
strengthening of the false convictions held by the individual’ (Dagonet, 1881, p. 29).
In addition, Dagonet also identified patients who appeared to show different
forms of doubling of personality (‘Doubling of personality’ was a common con-
cept in late nineteenth century psychiatry which was often used to help explain
contradictory mental states and behaviours (Berrios, 1996).) accompanied by
what he termed ‘double awareness’ (‘double conscience’). Such patients might
exhibit impulsive and violent behaviours, and be dominated by fears, hallucin-
ations and delusions but, at the same time, have ‘intimate knowledge of what is
happening to them. They judge correctly … feel that their will is insufficient to
resist against the terrible acts into which they are pushed’ (Dagonet, 1881, p. 21, my
translation). These patients would ask for help or admission to asylums. Dagonet
viewed such double awareness as a state of splitting of the psyche, whereby one state
of awareness was experiencing the bizarre phenomena of the ill personality and the
other state of awareness was judging it, according to the well personality, in a correct
manner. The resultant combination of experiences gave rise to perplexity and confu-
sion. He presented an example of a patient suffering from persecutory delusions,
believing that the whole world was concerned with him, that people were repeating
what he was saying and thinking, and making obscene gestures at him. At the same
time, the patient was analysing and studying his abnormal experiences and making
correct judgements. As Dagonet (1881, p. 21) commented,‘he knows that the impres-
sions he is experiencing are false interpretations’. Following Littré, Dagonet conceived
different forms of double awareness. In one form, the awareness was concomitant
in relation to the two personalities, i.e. both mental states had awareness and mem-
ory of each individual state. In another form, the awareness was successive, i.e. each
mental state had awareness and memory only of their own individual state but not
of the other. In a third form, the awareness was partial, i.e. when a mental state was
aware of itself but not of the new mental state but the latter was aware of both.
Dagonet believed that the awareness of illness shown by some patients could be
explained on the basis of Luy’s hypothesis of pathological asymmetry of the cerebral
hemispheres. Thus, he cited, ‘the coexistence of lucidity and delusional illness
22 Historical and clinical
[délire] can be rationally explained by the integrity of one cerebral hemisphere and
pathological hypertrophy of the other’ (Dagonet, 1881, p. 20, my translation). He
claimed further support for this hypothesis on the grounds of an autopsy result on
one of his mentally ill patients who had manifested clinically two distinct states of
awareness. At postmortem, there was apparently considerable difference between
the two hemispheres which suggested to Dagonet that each corresponded to the
different mental states.
Finally, Dagonet also briefly considered the medico-legal implications of his
observations. He stressed, as had the alienists in the debates some years earlier, that
patients could retain self-awareness but nevertheless be ‘forced’ into unreasonable
acts through the influence of delusional ideas. Specifically, he dissociated the
notion of awareness of illness from that of legal responsibility:
awareness should not be considered [for the physician] as a thermometer measuring degree of
responsibility … more important are the pathological phenomena characterising the mental ill-
ness. The severity of these should be determined in order to ascertain the degree of resistance
necessary for the patient to overcome dominating impulses.
Dagonet (1881, p. 32, my translation)
Seven years later, in a book examining the nature of reason in insanity and
implications for legal responsibility, Victor Parant (1888) analysed the concept of
awareness of self in mental illness (conscience de soi) in more depth. Like Morel and
Falret, he emphasised that awareness should not be confused with reason and
defined the former as a ‘state [in mental illness] in which the patient can take account
of his impressions, his actions, his internal experiences and their resultant effects’. In
other words, awareness, ‘implies not just knowledge of the mental state, but also the
capacity, in varying degrees, to appreciate and judge this’ (Parant, 1888, p. 174, my
translation). Here, therefore, seems to be one of the earliest times when the concept
of insight appears to have a more distinct form and is explicitly referring to two com-
ponent but distinct aspects, namely, awareness or consciousness of mental experi-
ences (as in Despine’s sense) and some form of judgement of these. In contrast to
Despine, Parant disagreed with Spurzheim’s view, translated by Baillarger as ‘madness
is a misfortune which is unaware of itself ’ (Parant, 1888, p. 175) and concurred with
Dagonet that patients could show a range of awareness and judgements with respect
to the mental illness affecting them. Pointing out also that this varied according to the
stage of the illness, i.e. whether early on in the illness, during the acute episode, or after
recovery, Parant (1888, pp. 177–179, 188–218) classified mentally ill patients, dur-
ing an episode of illness, into five groups on the basis of different types of awareness:
1 Those who were aware of their acts and who could judge if these were right or
wrong, but who were unaware of their morbid state.
23 Historical overview
2 Those who were aware that they were in an abnormal state but who did not
understand or would not admit that this state was insanity, e.g. patients recog-
nising the abnormality of their experiences but interpreting them delusionally.
3 Those who were aware that their mental states, acts and ideas were the result
of insanity but who, nevertheless, behaved as if they did not realise this, i.e. not
fully accepting that they had a mental illness, e.g. patients with hallucinations
and persecutory delusions, convinced by the reality of their delusional illness
and yet, at the same time, believing that they were ill.
4 Those who were aware of their morbid states and understood that these were
due to insanity but who were incapable of reacting or activating their will and
hence were powerless to do anything about it.
5 Those who were aware of their morbid states and understood that these
were due to insanity but who committed or were pushed into doing serious,
dangerous acts.
The concept of awareness or insight that Parant held thus incorporated both
awareness of mental phenomena and behaviours together with the judgement of
these as being morbid or the result of mental illness. He maintained that whatever
category of awareness the patients fell into, the presence of awareness implied
a persistence of the faculty of judgement. Interestingly, his classification of aware-
ness was based on both the subjective accounts given by patients as well as their
observable behaviours, noting the range of discrepancies between the two, and
emphasising the dissociation between patients’ judgements and their manifest
behaviours, particularly in relation to categories 3–5. Commenting on how some
patients became extremely distressed the more accurate their understanding of
reality was, he remarked that patients ‘assist like helpless spectators of the collapse
of what is most precious in themselves, that is their moral freedom as well as their
intellectual faculties’ (Parant, 1888, p. 223). Like Dagonet, he thus believed that
preservation of awareness did not entail the preservation of free will and hence did
not entail legal responsibility for criminal acts.
as it did in French psychiatry at that time. Instead, occasional reference to the con-
cept can be found in the clinical observations of alienists in their descriptions of
various forms of insanities (Bucknill & Tuke, 1858). Prichard (1835), for example,
concurring with Georget whom he cited, noted that insane patients were fully con-
vinced of their perfect sanity, ‘yet, as the same author observes [Georget], there are
some patients who are well aware of the disorder of their thoughts or of their affec-
tions, and who are deeply affected at not having sufficient strength of will to
repress it’ (Prichard, 1835, p. 121).
Some years later, Maudsley (1895) expressed considerable scepticism towards
the importance and role placed on consciousness in relation to mental function.
He stated:
it has been very difficult to persuade speculative psychologists who elaborate webs of philosophy
out of their own consciousness that consciousness has nothing to do with the actual work of
mental function; that it is the adjunct not the energy at work; not the agent in the process, but
the light which lightens a small part of it … we may put consciousness aside then when we are
considering the nature of the mechanism and the manner of its work …
Maudsley (1895, p. 8)
such mental states but would have no recollection of, or communication with, the
different states (Azam, 1892). Importantly, however, like Despine (1875) and ante-
dating Lewis (1934) (see below), Maudsley did not believe it was possible for an
insane mind to make a rational judgement concerning its derangement.
The question of the role and state of consciousness in insanity continued troub-
ling writers well into the twentieth century. For example, Claye Shaw (1909), echo-
ing many of Maudsley’s views on consciousness, nevertheless, placed greater
importance on the notion in relation to mental illness, particularly again with
respect to determining legal responsibility. He suggested that the poor recall of
events shown by patients with acute mental illness was due to altered conscious-
ness or awareness at the time. Such changes in consciousness often may be subtle
and difficult to discern, because, he argued, ‘there are in reality as many forms of
consciousness as there are different mental states’ (Shaw, 1909, p. 408). However,
linking consciousness to emotional tone he went on to postulate that one way of
recognising altered consciousness in mental illness was by the dissonance or incon-
gruence between patients’ thoughts and their apparent emotional state: ‘there
is evidence that both in dream states and in insanity the emotional side of the
idea may be wanting, and this must have great effect on both memory and
consciousness … I have over and over again noticed that people with delusions of
a very depressed type do not show the emotional tone which should co-exist with
the delusions’ (Shaw, 1909, pp. 406–407). Once again, the implication behind
Shaw’s views is that the disordered or deranged mind, unable to attend to either
internal or external events, and hence unable to subsequently recall them, is unlikely
to be capable of forming ‘correct’ or sane judgements concerning the nature of
morbid pathology.
The notion of insight in its broader sense as awareness of mental illness rather
than consciousness of mental processes was not, however, debated as widely and
explicitly as in nineteenth century French psychiatry until Aubrey Lewis (1934)
offered his exploration of the concept. Pointing to the confusion due to the differ-
ent meanings given to ‘insight’ within and outwith psychiatry (including Gestalt
and psychoanalytic psychology), he suggested his own definition of insight as
‘a correct attitude to a morbid change in oneself ’. He then proceeded to examine in
turn the meaning of the individual terms within this definition and highlighted
some of the problems inherent to the definition of underlying concepts such as
‘normality’, ‘mental illness’ and ‘attitude’. Consequently, he pointed out, this made
the meaning or understanding of insight itself complicated. Like some of the earl-
ier alienists, notably Parant and Jaspers, in his conceptualisation of insight, Lewis
distinguished between awareness of change and judgement of change, both being
necessary components of insight. Thus, in order to have an ‘attitude’ to the change
in oneself, the patient must first become aware of the change, before secondarily,
26 Historical and clinical
In any mental disorder, whether mild or severe, continued or brief, alien or comprehensible, it
is with his whole disordered mind that the patient contemplates his state or his individual
symptoms and in this disorder there are disturbances which are different from the healthy
function either in degree, combination or kind … always there will be a disturbance which
makes it impossible for the patient to look at his data and judge them as we, the dispassionate,
presumably healthy outsiders do. His judgements and attitude can therefore never be the
same as ours because his data are different, and his machine for judging is different in some
respects.
Lewis (1934, p. 343)
Lewis based his argument on his conceptualisation of insight which by his definition,
in terms of ‘correct’, included the comparison of view with a non-affected indi-
vidual. Thus, there were two reasons why a mentally ill patient could not have
full insight. Firstly, the mental illness itself caused disturbances in the subjective
self which could not possibly be appreciated by an outsider (and therefore a con-
cordance could not be achieved). Secondly, the tools with which the ill patient
could make judgements (‘disordered mind’) were themselves affected by the men-
tal illness and therefore could not make a just assessment. Interestingly, Lewis
made it explicit, including in his explanation of ‘correct attitude’, that the clinical
concept of insight related importantly to the judgement made by an unaffected
observer and hence represented, to some extent, an interaction between the latter
and the patient. The conceptualisation of insight in these terms, extending to
a complex of judgements between individuals, was thus becoming yet more
intricate.
27 Historical overview
progress to developing insight into their illness, other patients, notably those with
hypochondriacal conditions, had marked feelings of being ill and yet had no
insight into their illness (Pick, 1882).
Whilst agreeing with Pick’s distinction between awareness of feeling ill and
insight into illness, Arndt (1905) pointed out that awareness of feeling ill and the
reflective insight into illness were, in fact, interdependent since the ‘feeling’ had to
depend on some knowledge of bodily change. Likewise, the ‘knowledge’ of change
had to depend on some feeling of change. He thus suggested that the distinction
between ‘awareness of feeling ill’ and ‘insight into illness’ did not lie in the differ-
ence between ‘feeling’ in the former and ‘reflection’ in the latter but was based on
the difference in clarity with which the insight is experienced. Patients whose
awareness of illness was based on the feeling of being ill experienced insight into
their illness with much greater clarity and self-involvement. On the other hand,
patients whose awareness of illness was based on rational or reflective insight into
their illness experienced this with less clarity and often clouded by suspicion. In
other words, Arndt emphasised the importance of the experiential aspect of
insight, which, interestingly, shares similarities with later psychoanalytic perspec-
tives (Chapter 2). Arndt went on to analyse what he viewed as the necessary elem-
ents in the development of insight of illness, namely, the feeling of illness,
reasonable judgement and past experience. Each of these elements could be dis-
turbed, in different ways, in patients with mental illness. For example, he pointed
out that in mental disorders the feeling of illness might not be present in the con-
ventional sense. Patients could feel different and sometimes this feeling resonated
with psychological states (e.g. guilt feelings and home sickness) but the feeling
did not have to relate to ‘illness’ in the normal sense. Consequently, experienced
changes could be attributed to other non-illness factors (e.g. external influences)
and hence, almost by definition, patients with mental illness would lack this elem-
ent constituting insight into their illness. Arndt (1905) also speculated on the
underlying processes that might be disturbed in patients with mental illness who
showed impaired insight. In this vein, he suggested a role for attention, memory,
capacity for observation, judgement, conceptual thinking and education.
Following the distinction made and terminology used by Pick concerning
awareness into illness (‘Krankheitsbewußtsein’), Aschaffenburg (1915), concen-
trated from a purely clinical perspective, on examining each suggested component,
namely, the feeling of illness (‘Krankheitsgefühl’) (defined as vague fears and uncer-
tainties) and insight into illness (‘Krankheitseinsicht’) (defined as understanding
the nature and severity of the illness) and the relationship between them. On the
basis of clinical observations, he pointed out, as had Pick and Arndt earlier, that
there was not a direct progression from awareness of feeling ill to insight into being ill
and indeed there was often a discrepancy or mismatch between patients’ subjective
29 Historical overview
feeling of illness and their insight into illness. Thus, patients could have no feeling
of illness and yet have good insight into the fact that they were ill, as in some cases
of syphilis. Likewise, patients could have intense feelings of being ill and yet have
little insight into their illness, e.g. patients with various neuroses or hypochondria-
cal illnesses. He distinguished between the awareness of feeling ill in patients with
physical and with mental illnesses. In the former, this developed into awareness
of illness when patients clarified and formulated such feelings into fears of the
unknown, fears of pain, operations, etc. In the latter, i.e. awareness of feeling ill in
patients with mental illness, this was often the first sign of their illness itself, such
as depressive symptoms. In contrast to the case in physical illness, as such feelings
were ‘clarified’ and judged, then the experience of feeling of illness itself tended to
reduce as this was superseded by the pathological ‘rationalisation’ of the illness
process itself (Aschaffenburg, 1915, pp. 367–369).
By extending his observations of these components of insight into patients with
different mental disorders, he was able to suggest different possible mechanisms
that could affect patients’ judgements of their illness. Like Jaspers (see below), he
emphasised the difficulties in clinically determining patients’ insight and amongst
reasons for this, included his observation that insight as a judgement evolved over
time and that different morbid symptoms and features of the illness required dif-
ferent amounts of time to judge. In addition, he was clear about discrepancies
between insight as expressed by patients and their behaviours which were counter
to their utterances, for example, compulsions in a patient who had insight into his
illness (Aschaffenburg, 1915, pp. 369–371).
The concept of insight in terms of its nature, its diagnostic and predictive sig-
nificance, did not seem to interest Kraepelin (or Bleuler) a great deal. Kraepelin
referred to the notion under ‘judgement’: ‘what always surprises the observer anew
is the quiet complacency with which the most nonsensical ideas can be uttered by
them and the most incomprehensive actions carried out’ (Kraepelin, 1913/1919,
p. 25). He observed that some patients showed awareness of the morbidity of their
state early in the disease, but that this left them as the disease progressed: ‘the
patients often have a distinct feeling of the profound change which has taken place
in them. They complain that they are “dark in the head”, not free, often in confu-
sion, no longer clear, and that they have “cloud thoughts” … understanding of the
disease disappears fairly rapidly as the malady progresses’ (Kraepelin, 1913/1919,
pp. 25–26). Beyond subsequently commenting that ‘a certain insight into their dis-
eased state is frequently present’ in patients with the catatonic form of dementia
praecox (Kraepelin, 1913/1919, p. 150), and that, in contrast to patients with
dementia praecox, patients with manic-depressive psychosis had ‘more tendency
to, and ability for, the observation of self, to painful dissection of their psychic state’
(Kraepelin, 1913/1919, p. 264), Kraepelin did not further elaborate on the concept.
30 Historical and clinical
It was Karl Jaspers who focused specifically on the concept of insight into men-
tal illness and indeed the concept appeared to develop more in depth and detail
with successive editions of his ‘General Psychopathology’ (1913 (1st edition) to 1959
(7th edition)). From a combination of both clinical and psychological/philosophical
perspectives, he explored the concept of insight in several different ways, breaking
this up in terms of awareness of mental processes (consciousness in the narrow
sense), awareness of the sense and activities of the self and attitudes towards men-
tal illness. His conception of insight in these component forms emphasised a close
and bi-directional relationship between the personality judging the mental phe-
nomena affecting him and the manifestation of the psychopathology itself. In
other words, and crucially, it was not only that patients became aware and judged
the mental symptoms and illness that affected them, but the expression of the
mental symptoms themselves was affected by the awareness and judgements made
by the patients. He thus believed that it was essential to study patients’ under-
standing or insight into what was happening to them: ‘Patients’ self-observation,
their attentiveness to their abnormal experience and the processing of their obser-
vations in the form of a psychological judgement that can communicate to us their
inner life, is one of the most important sources of knowledge in regard to morbid
psychic life’ (Jaspers, 1948, p. 350, my translation). On the basis of his clinical
observations, Jaspers described various stages in the manifestation of patients’
awareness. He observed that, in the early stages of their psychotic illness, patients
became bewildered, this being an understandable reaction to the new experiences
they were undergoing. Awareness here, he contended, was related to the multitude of
different sensations they were experiencing and as such was not really a judgement as
a whole (akin to the awareness of immediate data in Lewis above). As the illness pro-
gressed, patients tried to make sense of their experiences, for example, by elaborating
delusional systems. Thereafter, Jaspers described how, when the illness produced
changes in personality, a patient’s attitude to the illness became less understandable to
others as he/she could appear indifferent or passive to the most frightening delusions.
Jaspers distinguished between these stages of changes which referred to aware-
ness of the content of patients’ experiences and insight itself which referred to
judgements made by the patient concerning their illness and hence involved the
relationship between such awareness and the self. Influenced by Pick, though con-
ceptualising the structure of insight slightly differently, he made a distinction, in
the latter judgements, between awareness of illness (‘Krankheitsbewußtsein’) and
insight proper (‘Krankheitseinsicht’). The former referred to the experience of feel-
ing ill and changed but without this awareness reaching all symptoms or the illness
as a whole. The latter, however, included an objectively correct assessment of the
nature and severity of the illness affecting the individual both as a whole and of
each individual symptom (Jaspers, 1948, pp. 349–350). Jaspers did qualify this
31 Historical overview
Conrad described further stages during which destructive processes were followed
by partial resolution as residual schizophrenic effects persisted, and postulated that
schizophrenia was an illness affecting the higher mental functions which differen-
tiate humans from animals. Thus, it affected the whole self-concept and, in particu-
lar, the ability of the individual to effect the normal transition from looking at
oneself from within to looking at oneself from the outside, by the eyes of the world.
1.4 Conclusion
The concept of insight into mental illness emerged around the middle of the nine-
teenth century as an independent phenomenon that could be explored in patients.
This can be understood in the contexts of: (i) general increased interest in individu-
ality and self-reflection at this time, together with the development of concepts
such as introspection, apperception and ‘verstehen’ legitimising subjectivity as
an area of enquiry and (ii) changing views on the nature of mental illness and the
conceptualisation of partial insanities, opening up a space in which it became pos-
sible to conceive insight into madness. The partial insanity debates were, in turn,
influenced by the empirical observations of alienists, the medico-legal challenges
of the courts and the development of faculty psychology including phrenology.
In the early part of the nineteenth century, the concept of insight into mental ill-
ness was not yet clearly formed and patients were simply observed as having or not
having awareness of their illness. Awareness at this point seemed to refer variously
to feelings or judgements. By the middle of the nineteenth century debates specifically
addressed at the concept of insight were taking place, particularly in France. In the
context of these discussions, where insight was explored in relation to mental dis-
orders, to the notion of self, to mental faculties and to the issue of legal responsibil-
ity for criminal acts, the concept of insight began to develop a structure as attempts
were made to define and distinguish between independent mental processes
(Falret, 1866; Billod, 1870; Morel, 1870). Clinically, insight was also becoming
more prominent as a feature to be examined in different clinical groups and men-
tal disorders (Billod, 1870; Morel, 1870), as a criterion distinguishing between clin-
ical disorders (Ritti, 1879) and as a prognostic variable (Billod, 1870).
Towards the end of the nineteenth century, insight into mental illness seemed to
refer to two main concepts. Firstly, there was the narrower concept of awareness or
consciousness of mental operations (Despine, 1875; Maudsley, 1895). Alienists
holding this concept generally believed that whilst patients could have awareness
of particular mental processes, this did not extend to an awareness of such
processes being morbid. Secondly, there was the wider concept of insight which
included both an awareness of mental phenomena together with some awareness
of the self as an individual but, in addition, a judgement made by patients
33 Historical overview
concerning the illness affecting them (Dagonet, 1881; Billod, 1882; Pick, 1882;
Parant, 1888). Alienists conceiving insight in this broad way tended to believe that
patients could have insight and even different degrees of insight into their illness.
Part of the problem in attempting to define the emerging structure of insight, how-
ever, is the difficulty involved in trying to clarify the nature of the constituent
components. Whilst some alienists could conceive clear distinctions between
awareness, feeling and judgement, for others those demarcations were blurred or
did not exist. In turn, such disparities seemed to be based on different understand-
ing of the nature of, and relationship between, mental processes themselves and
their connection or otherwise to brain processes. Nevertheless, a rough structure
can begin to be identified with components based on distinctions between differ-
ent types of awareness (Dagonet, 1881), between different types of judgements
(Billod, 1882), between feelings and reason (Pick, 1882) and between subjective
utterances and observed behaviours (Pick, 1882; Parant, 1888).
After the turn of the century, the broader conceptualisation of insight into men-
tal illness seemed to hold. However, this became more complicated in terms of
determining individual components, e.g. contribution of intelligence, culture, past
experience, capacity for observation, memory, etc. (Arndt, 1905; Jaspers, 1913) as
well as defining the boundaries of such a structure, e.g. extent of knowledge
demanded, level of concordance needed with the unaffected individual (Lewis,
1934), both from a theoretical and the clinical perspective. In addition, qualitative
differences in insight between patients with different types of mental disorders
were beginning to be identified (Arndt, 1905; Aschaffenburg, 1915). This, together
with the unresolved issues concerning the nature of the components of insight,
further compounded the complexity of the insight structure. Nonetheless, insight
conceived as an awareness of change together with some judgement made of this
change has remained the core of the theoretical concept ever since.
2
At the turn of the century, there arose, independently, various challenges to this
form of scientific psychology. Whilst all seemed to argue against the validity of thus
analysing the contents of consciousness, the nature of their objections was very
different. Behaviourism rejected completely the notion that consciousness could be
a valid object of inquiry and turned instead to the study of relationships between
events that could be ‘objectively’ observed and measured. Introspection was con-
ceived as too subjective and hence ‘inaccurate’ and, consequently, consciousness
was placed in a metaphorical black box whilst psychological studies focused on
correlations between its inputs (experimental stimuli) and outputs (behavioural
or physiological responses). Gestalt psychology, on the other hand, challenged the
way in which the ‘facts’ of consciousness were analysed. Specifically, the Gestalt
psychologists argued against the mechanistic structural correspondence that was
conceived between the external world, the contents of consciousness and the brain
itself. Instead, they put forward a functional correspondence that depended on the
mind responding not just to the aggregated constituents of objects but also to the
functional relations between such constituents in the formation of the object as a
whole. In other words, the whole was viewed as different from the sum of its parts.
Brain processes reflected this capacity to integrate functional interrelationships in
order to produce the experience of the whole in the mind of the individual. From
a different perspective again was the objection held by psychoanalytic psycholo-
gists. They claimed that the validity of using the contents of consciousness as
the object of inquiry was compromised because such contents were inherently
unstable and distorted by unconscious mental processes. It thus made more sense,
the psychoanalysts argued, to focus instead, by means of interpretation and other
strategies, on such unconscious mental processes as the objects of psychological
inquiry.
For the purposes here, it is with the latter two schools of psychological thought
that insight is explored. The chapter thus first looks at the notion of insight as
developed by the Gestalt psychologists and by the Gestalt influenced but contem-
porary cognitive psychologists. Then, the notion of insight as conceived within the
psychoanalytical framework is examined together with its perceived role in psy-
chotherapeutic processes. The aim in briefly exploring these psychological per-
spectives on insight is two-fold. Firstly, as already mentioned, both schools of
thought make an important contribution to the conceptualisation and assessment
of insight in clinical psychiatry and neuropsychiatry. Secondly, there are also sig-
nificant differences between the ways in which insight is conceptualised from these
perspectives and from within psychiatry in general. Such differences are important
to highlight in order to help clarify some of the confusion that is present around
the terms and meanings relating to insight in empirical studies. The nature of these
and other differences, evident in the conceptualisation of insight, together with the
36 Historical and clinical
implications these carry for understanding results of empirical work and for deter-
mining a structure for insight will be discussed in the second part of this book.
One of the main principles underlying Gestalt theory was that the whole was
greater than (and different from) the sum of its parts. This idea appeared to be
originally articulated by Ehrenfels (1890), a member of the Würzburg School.
Using the example of a melody (the whole) consisting of separate tones (individ-
ual elements), he argued that even when the tones were played in a different key,
the melody could still be recognised as a particular melody but that when the same
tones were played in a different sequence the melody was no longer recognisable.
Thus, it was not just the sum of the individual elements (tones) that was important
in the perception of the whole (melody) but the relations of such elements to each
other (i.e. their organisation) that was important in the perception of the whole
melody. He coined the term ‘Gestaltsqualitäten’ (qualities of the Gestalt (Gestalt is
variously translated as ‘form’, ‘shape’ or ‘configuration’ and simply refers to a par-
ticular whole)) to specify that wholes had such qualities. These were not perceived
simply in terms of the sum of their elements but it was the way in which the elem-
ents were organised, that gave the qualitative aspect to the whole and which
helped to determine a particular experience or perception of the whole. This
notion was taken up and developed by Max Wertheimer, the Principal Founder of
Gestalt Psychology, and by Wolfgang Köhler and Kurt Koffka, his younger colleagues.
Much of the early work in Gestalt psychology was focused on the area of percep-
tion but subsequently the Gestalt principles were extended to other areas of psych-
ology, particularly to learning, problem-solving and developmental psychology.
Within Gestalt theory, the concept of insight has carried a very specific meaning
which contrasts, both in terms of content and specificity, to the way in which
insight has been conceptualised in general psychiatry (Chapter 3) and in neuro-
logical states (Chapters 4 and 5). Its essence lies in the grasp or understanding an
individual (or animal) obtains of a specific situation in a particular way. Thus, it is
not just understanding of a situation or problem but it is a ‘genuine’ or ‘productive’
understanding that is based on appreciation of the functional inner relatedness of
the parts of the structure of a situation (Wertheimer, 1945/1961). Köhler applied
this concept to the study of intelligent behaviour in chimpanzees. He asked the
question whether chimpanzees were capable of behaving with insight, i.e. whether
they could find solutions to certain problems that were based on insight rather
than on chance or trial-and-error learning. In order to determine this, he devised
various tasks for the apes whose solutions were not straightforward or direct but
depended on the ape taking account of the task as a whole in terms of available
37 The psychological perspective
components and their relationships with each other. For example, one such task
involved placing fruit within sight but just out of reach of the chimpanzee. There
was a small stick in the cage with the animal (at this stage the apes were familiar
with using sticks to help them reach fruit) but this was not long enough to reach
the fruit. Outside the cage there was placed a longer stick which was out of reach
of the animal but could be pulled within reach by means of the smaller stick. In turn
the longer stick could then be used to reach the fruit (Köhler, 1924/1957). These
sorts of tasks thus, argued Köhler, contained components which, if considered
individually, could be seen as meaningless or irrelevant, or even contradictory to
the structure of the solution as a whole. The criterion of insight, he went on to
specify, was ‘the appearance of a complete solution with reference to the whole lay-
out of the field’ (Köhler, 1924/1957, p. 164). It was only by consideration of the
structure of the situation that a solution could be viewed as insightful. He distin-
guished between animal behaviours that led to solutions by chance and behaviours
that resulted in solutions by insight. In the former, the chimpanzee’s actions would
be haphazard and consist of a number of single separate fractions which after some
time might lead to the solution. By contrast, tasks that were solved by insight were
characterised by behaviours which showed a ‘smooth, continuous course, sharply
divided by an abrupt break from the preceding (non-insightful) behaviour … this
process as a whole corresponds to the structure of the situation, to the relation of
its parts to one another’ (Köhler, 1924/1957, pp. 163–164). In psychological terms,
Köhler interpreted such behaviours as indicating ‘the sudden occurrence of per-
fectly clear and definite solutions’ (Köhler, 1924/1957, p. 207), thereby, reflecting
the presence of insight in the animal.
In Gestalt terms, the notion of insight was thus conceived as a reorganisation of
a particular situation through an understanding of the functional relationships
between relevant component parts. (For example, sticks could be perceived as
immaterial or as playthings or as specific tools according to the demands of a par-
ticular situation.) Furthermore, again in line with some of the early Gestalt work,
Köhler understood this reorganisation to involve a perceptual process. Hence:
insight of the chimpanzee shows itself to be principally determined by his optical apprehension
of the situation; at times he even starts solving problems from a too visual point of view, and in
many cases in which the chimpanzee stops acting with insight, it may have been simply that the
structure of the situation was too much for his visual grasp.
Köhler (1924/1957, p. 228 original emphasis)
Koffka (1935/1963) maintained that Köhler was offering insight simply as a descrip-
tion rather than an explanation in itself. However, Köhler did attempt to provide
some explanation based on a modification of associationism. Thus, rather than
relations between things being perceived by means of a mechanical association
38 Historical and clinical
(i.e. links understood when there was frequent following of each other or occurring
together), they could be perceived by means of a functional association, i.e. ‘based
on the properties of these things themselves’ (Köhler, 1924/1957, p. 189).
There have since been numerous criticisms directed at Köhler’s interpretation
of the animals’ behaviours as ‘insight’ (see Koffka, 1925/1980 for a comprehensive
review) and indeed many of the issues raised have been echoed in subsequent debates
in relation to more sophisticated cognitive experiments (see below). Nevertheless,
this definition of insight, as a form of intelligent behaviour or thought charac-
terised by a sudden, rapid, smooth and directed process through which a particu-
lar objective is attained, has remained at the core of the Gestalt and cognitive
psychological conceptualisations of insight.
In an important work, published posthumously, Wertheimer (1945/1961)
applied similar Gestalt principles to the study of learning and problem-solving in
human beings. He attempted to analyse the processes that took place during
insightful or ‘productive’ thinking. Distinguishing between understanding that was
based on such productive thinking and understanding based on blind repetition or
learning by rote, he showed in a number of experiments that only the former could
result in subjects applying their knowledge to a variety of different, albeit related,
problems. Indeed, he criticised the teaching of children by drill which, he argued,
was counterproductive to thinking and induced habits of sheer mechanised action
rather than leading to a true grasp of problems. Like Köhler, he emphasised the
need for the subject to grasp the structure of the whole problem in terms of the
inner relatedness of its parts. In this sense, he described the process of attaining
insight as a top-down rather than bottom-up procedure. Attempting to break
down such operations, Wertheimer focused repeatedly on the demands made by
the structure of the task/problem. He suggested a process which was:
not just a sum of several steps, not an aggregate of several operations, but the growth of one line
of thinking out of the gaps in the situation, out of the structural troubles … it is not a process
that moves from pieces to an aggregate, from below to above, but from above to below, from the
nature of the structural trouble to the concrete steps.
Wertheimer (1945/1961, pp. 49–50)
out the area of a parallelogram) and these also helped to distinguish between solutions
that were insightful and solutions that occurred by chance or trial and error. Thus, he
described subjects expressing the process of ‘seeing the light … (the problem) sud-
denly became transparently clear, meaningful, in the realisation of the inner structure,
the inner requirements of the process’ (Wertheimer, 1945/1961, p. 67). This subjective
sense of clarity and new understanding together with a feeling of satisfaction has
continued to characterise the phenomenon of insight in this area of psychology.
Likewise concentrating on analysing processes underlying problem-solving,
Karl Duncker (1945) further developed Wertheimer’s ideas on restructuring as a
necessary condition for insight. Whilst Gestalt thinking explicitly objected to the
prevailing associationistic explanations underlying thinking and behaviours, the
proposed alternative framed in terms of functional associations, restructuring and
reorganising of perceptual or cognitive fields has been, and continues to be, criti-
cised for its lack of a clear theoretical and explanatory basis (e.g. Osgood, 1964;
Ohlsson, 1984a, b; Isaak & Just, 1995; Mayer, 1995). Nonetheless Duncker (1945),
in his important work on insight and problem-solving, attempted to provide
a clearer and more detailed account of possible processes or stages underlying
insightful problem-solving. He proposed that insight into a problem depended
crucially on restructuring of the problem. In turn, this restructuring could occur in
two main ways. Firstly, the functional goal (i.e. the general purpose) of the prob-
lem could be redefined (he called this process a suggestion from above), and,
secondly, the function of the components of the problem could be reformulated
(suggestion from below) such that the original information presented was defined
in a different way. He also examined possible processes underlying the reasons why
subjects might not achieve a problem solution, i.e. why restructuring might not
occur. He proposed that a subject’s past experience could have a detrimental effect
on such restructuring because this could force a particular mode of thinking and
detract from considering novel approaches. Thus, past experience could become
an actual block to the individual and Duncker termed this functional fixedness.
Duncker’s ideas, his experimental problems and proposed psychological processes
have been extremely influential in the approaches taken by cognitive psychologists
in more recent studies on insight (Sternberg & Davidson, 1995).
It is of interest that the concept of insight as developed by the early Gestalt
psychologists and refined by later cognitive psychologists has been and continues
to be, despite its specificity, an area of much debate and dispute. As is the case with the
ways in which insight is dealt with by the more clinical disciplines (see later), differ-
ences in views concerning the meaning of insight, its nature, its elicitation and its likely
underlying mechanisms/processes are also prevalent in the psychological disciplines.
These differences serve to highlight some of the complexities present around the con-
ceptualisation of insight and it is useful to examine briefly some of these issues in turn.
40 Historical and clinical
different stages (e.g. Hutchinson, 1941; Csikszentmihalyi & Sawyer, 1995; Seifert et al.,
1995, see below). The experiential aspects of insight, i.e. the subjective elements
have also carried various emphases in different definitions. For many, it has not been
particularly relevant (Köhler, 1924/1957; Weisberg, 1995) but others have specified
accompanying subjective experiences such as elation (Hutchinson, 1941), satisfaction
and triumph (Seifert et al., 1995) and delight, humour or chagrin (Gick & Lockhart,
1995). Interestingly, the question of whether the experiential aspects, in terms of
the sense of revelation and satisfaction, could occur independently of correct solu-
tions does not seem to have been explored. In other words, is it possible for sub-
jects to experience the sudden feeling of clarity and sense of enlightenment when
incorrectly solving a problem albeit under the impression it was correct? Clearly
the assumption is that the subjective experience of clarity and understanding has
to correspond intrinsically to a ‘correct’ appraisal of the problem or situation.
The specificity of insight in terms of referring to some form of problem-solving
has also tended to be held with relative consistency. (This level of specificity is
markedly in contrast to the notion of insight as conceived in psychiatric disorders.)
Nevertheless, some variability is found here as well. Seifert et al. (1995) state clearly
that insight is not restricted to problem-solving but includes knowledge about
the world and about oneself. They thus provide a broader theoretical definition
though they do limit this to problem-solving for empirical purposes. Similarly
Finke (1995), in discussions around creative insight, defines this as ‘an essential
process by which we come to make surprising discoveries and realisations, both
about real-world issues and problems, and about ourselves’ (Finke, 1995, p. 255).
This is a much wider conception of insight. Gruber (1995) whilst defining insight
as a moment or flash of enlightenment, at the same time, places this as ‘part of
coherent life’. Some view insight as a state of mind (e.g. Dominowski & Dallob,
1995) while others define it as a process made up of several stages (Davidson &
Sternberg, 1986; Ippolito & Tweney, 1995; Mayer, 1995).
Apart from the issue of specificity in regards to problem-solving, relating insight
to problem-solving itself is a fundamentally different approach to the meaning of
insight compared with its meaning in the clinical disciplines. The crucial difference
lies in the external focus of insight in the Gestalt and cognitive frameworks as
opposed to the internal focus of insight in the clinical disciplines. In other words,
in the case of the former, insight is directed at the solution of an external problem
(i.e. insight is equivalent to awareness of understanding a particular set task outside
of the individual). On the other hand, insight in the clinical conceptions is directed
at the understanding of something happening within the subject (i.e. insight is
equivalent to awareness and understanding of changes, such as illness or symp-
toms or disability, etc. happening within an individual). Later, this will be concep-
tualised and understood in terms of different ‘objects’ of insight assessment
42 Historical and clinical
1986) or that insight is mostly non-special but a few ‘special’ processes are involved
(Seifert et al., 1995). A major proponent of the ‘special’ view of insight, Metcalfe and
her colleagues described a number of experiments which, they argued, provided
empirical support for this view (Metcalfe, 1986a, b; Metcalfe & Wiebe, 1987). The
principles behind this empirical work lay in focusing on subjects’ ‘metacognitions’
(judgements based on self-monitoring of mental states) as predictions of success in
solving so-called insight problems and non-insight problems (memory tasks, alge-
bra sums, etc.). The metacognitions were elicited either as a ‘feeling of knowing’
and/or as a closeness to solution which Metcalfe calls ‘feeling of warmth’, which the
subjects had to rate in conjunction with carrying out the various tasks. In summary,
findings across the different studies indicated that, on the basis of these metacogni-
tions, subjects were able to predict success only in non-insight problems but not in
the insight problems. In other words, there seemed to be no correlation between the
subject’s experience of feeling close to a solution and actual solution in the insight-
dependent tasks whereas in the memory tasks, for example, there was an incremen-
tal growth of feelings of warmth corresponding to subjects’ approaching of the
solutions. In addition, the solution to ‘insight problems’ was marked phenomeno-
logically by a ‘sudden flash of illumination’. This, the authors argued, indicated that
insight involved a qualitative change in mental processing. There was no incremen-
tal process of getting closer to a solution but instead the solution occurred suddenly
and unexpectedly implying a discontinuity in mental processing.
Proponents of the view that insight is not a special process have criticised such
empirical work both on methodological and on tautological grounds. Weisberg
(1992; 1995), for example, argues that the distinction between so-called insight prob-
lems and non-insight problems is false and suggests that it would be more useful to
think of problems in a multidimensional way and conceive a continuum of solutions
some of which depend on incremental steps and others on short and fast steps, etc.
His view in relation to problem-solving was that rather than invoking a special notion
of insight, ‘problem-solving should be considered as a cyclical process, involving
retrieval of information from memory and the attempt to apply this information
to the problem. Failure provides new information, which initiates further memory
search, and so on’ (Weisberg, 1992, p. 427). In other words, solutions to problems are
to be found within memory systems of subjects and depend on appropriate access
and use made of these by the subject rather than on other special mental processes.
In addition, Weisberg criticised the circularity involved in using ‘patterns of warmth’
both as a criterion of an insight problem (a problem is an insight problem because of
the pattern of warmth) and as a support for the validity of the construct (pattern of
warmth, indicating insight, elicited in relation to insight problem). Finally, the ‘Aha’
experience as a criterion of insight has also been disputed, in that subjects can experi-
ence the same phenomenon when solving ‘non-insight’ problems (Weisberg, 1995).
44 Historical and clinical
processes has reflected this shift particularly in the move away from perceptual
models (e.g. Köhler, 1924/1957; Hutchinson, 1941) to more ‘cognitive’ models of
understanding insight (Sternberg & Davidson, 1995). Nevertheless, the perceptual
metaphor is still evident in many of the processes proposed to underlie insight and
this, amongst other things, helps to subdivide views in this area. Some explanatory
mechanisms underlying insight are thus framed in perceptual terms, such as ‘new
perceptual organisation’ (Ellen & Pate, 1986) or ‘locus of explanation in the per-
ceptual world’ (Ippolito & Tweney, 1995).
In general though, insight is conceived as developing following some sort of
restructuring of the problem. The nature of this ‘restructuring’ process, however,
has been a source of difficulty in terms of agreement concerning what precisely
this process involves. Duncker (1945) referred to an analysis of the problem situ-
ation and removal of blocks which impeded such analysis. Similarly, the Russian
Psychologist Rubinštejn (1960) emphasised the importance of reformulation of the
problem and the interactional relationship between reformulation and analysis.
Clearly, some researchers view the restructuring process as perceptual, e.g. a percep-
tual reorganisation (Ellen & Pate, 1986) or pattern recognition (Schooler et al.,
1995). In more information-processing terms, the restructuring has been described
as a change in the representation of the problem, i.e. finding the right problem
representation (Ohlsson, 1984a, b; Kaplan & Simon, 1990; Gick & Lockhart, 1995).
Other suggestions involving methods of restructuring have included: use of ana-
logue, i.e. solving a problem on the basis of its similarity to a different problem
(Gick & Holyoak, 1980; 1983), completing a schema, i.e. the addition of missing
pieces to an incomplete though appropriate mental representation (Mayer, 1995;
Seifert et al., 1995), as a search of memory and working with the information
accrued (Weisberg & Alba, 1982; Weisberg, 1992; 1995), apprehension of relations
and fluency of thought (Ansburg, 2000), and many more (Sternberg & Davidson,
1995). Davidson and Sternberg (1986) suggest three distinct processes consisting of:
(i) selective encoding (i.e. relevant information is sifted out from the irrelevant),
(ii) selective combination (i.e. the assembling of seemingly unrelated facts or ideas
into a coherent whole) and (iii) selective comparison (i.e. relating newly acquired
or proposed concepts to the older concepts, analogies).
One of the more consistent findings in the descriptions of processes underlying
insight has related to the postulated stages involved. Such stages had already been
described in the early Gestalt work (Wallas, 1926 (cited in Mayer, 1995); Hutchinson,
1941) and have persisted, with modifications, within the cognitive literature
(Sternberg & Davidson, 1995). In brief, the stages are described as follows:
2.1.4 Summary
In summary, the concept of insight in Gestalt psychology is viewed in a very spe-
cific sense. Bound up in the theory of perception that is central to Gestalt thinking,
insight results from the reorganisation or restructuring of a particular situation or
problem, based on some form of perceptual shift (‘things falling into place’). With
the development of cognitive approaches, the perceptual analogy has largely been
superseded by information-processing-like models though the behavioural aspect
48 Historical and clinical
of the Gestalt notion remains. Insight has been studied both as an ‘intelligent
behaviour’ through the solving of specific tasks and as a ‘creative process’ through
retrospective and prospective research into scientific methods (Dunbar, 1995).
In contrast to the broader and more general meanings of insight in relation to
mental illness (see next chapter), the specificity of the concept of insight in Gestalt
and cognitive psychology is striking and manifest in several ways. Firstly, the experi-
ence of insight (whether conceived as a state or process) is characterised by certain
features, namely, suddenness, spontaneity, unexpectedness and satisfaction (Seifert
et al., 1995). In other words, there is the sense of ‘enlightenment’ or ‘revelation’ that
can be observed both in behavioural (the sudden smooth solving of a task) and in
subjective (the ‘Aha’ experience) terms. Secondly, insight so conceived is a discrete
event with determinable boundaries. Thirdly, insight is directed specifically at the
solution of a particular task which, in contrast to the clinical perspective, lies exter-
nal to the individual.
Partly as a result of changes in theoretical approaches and partly because of
some circularity involved in studying the phenomenon of insight in so-called
insight problems, opposing views have emerged concerning the validity of both the
insight construct as such and the problems used to determine insight.
unconscious into what is conscious’ (Freud, 1973a, p. 321). Later, as Freud’s views
changed and he developed the structural model of the mind, self-knowledge was
conceived in a similarly deep but more active and integrative way (‘where id was
there ego shall be’ (Freud, 1973b, p. 112)). Likewise, emphasising the depth of self-
knowledge required for therapeutic benefit, Segal points out that insight ‘… must
be deep enough. It must reach to the deep layers of the unconscious and illuminate
those early processes in which the pattern of internal and external relationships is
laid down, and in which the ego is structured’ (Segal, 1962, p. 212).
Interestingly, whilst the concept of insight as a form of deep self-knowledge can
be discerned in the earliest psychoanalytic writings, the term ‘insight’ only began to
be used in this context around the early 1950s. Freud used the term ‘insight’
(‘Einsicht’ or ‘Einblick’) predominantly in the generic sense to denote knowledge or
awareness of being ill. According to Anna Freud (1981), there was only one instance
where Freud used the term ‘insight’ in the deeper sense of revelation as in the much
quoted line from the 1931 preface to the 3rd English edition of The Interpretation
of Dreams: ‘insight such as this comes to one’s lot but once in a lifetime’ (Freud, 1900,
p. xxxii). Nevertheless, the concept of insight in the sense of a self-understanding
that reaches the unconscious levels of the mind has been implied in both the psycho-
analytic aim and in the psychoanalytic treatment (‘that here understanding and
cure almost coincide, that a traversable road leads from one to the other’ (Freud,
1973b, p. 180)). This conceptualisation of insight was subsequently made explicit
by the convergent use of the term ‘insight’ in later psychoanalytic writings (e.g.
Martin, 1952; Zilboorg, 1952; Kris, 1956) and, since then, has continued to be the
source of much debate. In this regard, two main areas will be explored in this sec-
tion. Firstly, the concept of insight itself will be reviewed and, secondly, the role of
insight in psychoanalysis and psychoanalytic therapies will be examined in terms
of its perceived contribution to promoting change or ‘cure’. Whilst a division between
these areas is being made here for the purpose of analysis, it has to be understood
that this is something of an artificial division and the two areas considerably overlap.
Indeed there is, as will be seen, a degree of circularity involved when exploring the
relationship between insight and change in a situation where the conceptualisation
of insight itself incorporates the notion of psychic or personality change within its
definition.
already present in Freud when the latter differentiated between ‘knowing but
not knowing’ – as the intellectual understanding of the repressed (i.e. distant, non-
involvement of the self with the unconscious) – and emotional understanding
which was attained through the direct (experiential) struggle with the repressed in
the transference reaction. In a similar vein, without referring to insight specifically,
Strachey (1934) distinguishes between descriptive interpretations which can lead
to intellectual understanding and ‘mutative’ interpretations which lead to modifi-
cation of the patient’s superego (i.e. to sustained change). The mutative interpret-
ation, he specifies, ‘must be emotionally immediate; the patient must experience it
as something actual’ (Strachey, 1934, p. 150). In general terms, it is this emotional
or experiential aspect of insight that is considered one of the crucial aspects of psy-
choanalytic insight, one that is frequently equated with the definition of psycho-
analytic insight itself, helping to differentiate it from insight as used in other areas
(lay usage, general psychiatric usage, etc.) and often considered as the main factor
in promoting change (Segal, 1962; 1991).
Other more specific approaches have been taken to distinguish between different
types of insight. For example, Reid and Finesinger (1952) differentiated between neu-
tral, emotional and dynamic insight. Objecting to the term ‘intellectual’ insight on the
grounds of claiming that all insight was by definition intellectual (or cognitive), they
proposed distinctions based on the level at which patients could understand the rela-
tionship between antecedents and manifested symptoms or behaviours. They defined
neutral insight as occurring when patients were able to understand and accept super-
ficial links between antecedents (e.g. quarrelling with spouse) and symptoms (e.g.
indigestion). They further specified that at this level, emotions were not involved
either in the act of understanding or as a release resulting from the understanding.
Emotional insight, on the other hand, occurred when patients’ understanding of the
association between antecedents and symptoms included either an emotional com-
ponent in the understanding process itself (e.g. anxiety/hostility underlying the quar-
relling with spouse) or if emotion was experienced as a result of that understanding.
Finally, dynamic insight was defined as the deepest form of insight when patients were
able to understand the relationships between antecedents and symptoms in the
Freudian sense of ‘penetrating the repressive barrier and making the ego aware of
certain hypercathected wishes that were previously unconscious’ (Reid & Finesinger,
1952, p. 731). In other words, here the connection between antecedents and symp-
toms was based on knowledge of unconscious motivations and defences thought to
underlie the emotional component of the antecedent. Of these three kinds of insight,
dynamic insight was conceived as producing the most extensive changes in the per-
sonality of the subject and the most lasting therapeutic benefits.
Whilst agreeing that insight had to involve the patients’ understanding of their
unconscious mental processes in order to achieve therapeutic benefit, Richfield
52 Historical and clinical
(1954), argued that recognition of such unconscious processes on the part of the
patient did not necessarily lead to a change in ‘neurotic’ behaviour. He proposed
that it was not the content of the knowledge that was essential to the therapeutic
effect of insight but the form in which this knowledge was experienced. Thus, on
the basis of Bertrand Russell’s classification of knowledge, Richfield distinguished
between insight gained by description and insight gained by acquaintance. When
patients attained descriptive insight, they became aware of the ‘truths’ about them-
selves by acknowledging the words of the analyst. When, however, they attained
ostensive insight, they became ‘personally acquainted’ with the ‘truths’, for example,
through transference when particular emotions and their significance were
brought directly to patients’ awareness. In other words, it is the method of gaining
knowledge by direct experience that is considered the crucial component of insight
irrespective of the content of such knowledge.
Bibring (1954), in contrast, focuses on the content of knowledge as a distin-
guishing factor between two forms of insight. Specifying also that different tech-
niques are needed to achieve these insights he differentiates between insight
through clarification and insight through interpretation. The former is based on
working with conscious and/or preconscious processes of which the patient is not
sufficiently aware and the latter is based on working exclusively with unconscious
mental processes. Consequently, he argues, the two forms of insight are ‘dynam-
ically’ different. Insight through clarification, because it deals only with conscious
material, does not encounter resistance and patients are able to develop a more
‘objective, realistic perspective’ on problems and thereby achieve greater control
over them. In that sense, the ego becomes ‘detached’. Problems are not resolved but
are viewed from a different perspective. Insight through interpretation, on the
other hand, results in direct involvement of the ego in the process of dealing with
the unconscious material but results in better solutions to underlying pathogenic
conflicts. Somewhat differently, Myerson (1965) differentiates between psychoana-
lytic insight and reality-oriented insight on the basis of what seems to be a deeper
form of understanding in the former. Here again, the focus is on knowledge of
unconscious mental forces and, in particular, of these being directly experienced in
the mental state. In reality-oriented insight a more superficial knowledge is defined
with focus on realistic appraisals of relationships and environment rather than on
underlying instinctual conflicts.
Describing some of the attempts at classifying the various modes of insight as
ad hoc and intuitive rather than systematic or analytical, Lindén (1984; 1985) sets out
a comprehensive but complicated framework for classifying insight using a develop-
mental approach. She stresses the need for an adequate theory of cognition and for
this purpose uses Nilsson’s genetic-hierarchical theory which itself is based on an inte-
gration of Piaget’s developmental theories and Freud’s topographical representation
53 The psychological perspective
of the mind. Insight, she proposes, can be hierarchically (i.e. structurally) localised
in relation to sensorimotor, perceptual or conceptual levels of cognitive activity
and along conscious–unconscious and intellectual–emotional dimensions. In
recognition of the confusion arising from the general use of the term ‘insight’ she
argues for the need to specify (within her proposed framework) the particular
insight manifested within an analytic situation.
Apart from seeking to clarify and define various modes of insight, psychoanalytic
approaches have also explored the possible processes and components involved. In
contrast to the Gestalt notion, there is a much greater emphasis on conceptualisation
of insight as a long gradual process in which insight is gained in slow increments
(Strachey, 1934; Kris, 1956; Hatcher, 1973; Abrams, 1981; Mangham, 1981; Poland,
1988; Segal, 1991). Zilboorg (1952) argues that it has to be an affective process, in
that insight can only develop through successive affective reconstructive experiences
(thus arguing for the emotional/experiential component of insight as the crucial
constitutive factor). Conceived as an ongoing process, there is the additional impli-
cation that insight can never be complete, that it is indefinite, and applies to the
whole life of an individual and, indeed, some have stated this explicitly (Blum, 1979;
1992; Poland, 1988; Segal, 1991). Only a few authors refer to insight as an ‘immedi-
ate’ or sudden illumination as used in the Gestalt sense (Rhee, 1990; Elliott et al.,
1994) though some writers allow for the possibility of sudden flashes of insight
occurring within the ongoing process as a whole (Martin, 1952; Blum, 1979; Olmos-
de Paz, 1990; Wilson, 1998; Joyce & Stoker, 2000). Most views seem to agree that the
process of insight is an active and creative one (Blum, 1979; Freud, 1981; Pollock,
1981; Shengold, 1981; Sternbach, 1989). Thus, it is active in the sense that the indi-
vidual has to be him/herself directly involved in the process. Freud recognised this in
his later work when dealing with the phenomenon of resistance. For this reason also,
some writers have argued specifically against the notion of the analyst ‘giving’ insight
to the subject (Zilboorg, 1952; Poland, 1988). The process is seen as a creative one in
that attaining insight or understanding of unconscious mental processes is viewed as
involving a restructuring or reintegration of aspects of the subject’s ego to form
something new rather than a restoration or clarification of the old (Segal, 1962; 1991;
Freud, 1981; Sternbach, 1989). Abrams (1981, p. 261) puts this very clearly:
Insight-producing activity entails taking things apart and putting them together differently. It is
the highly specialized expression of fundamental differentiating and integrating capacities, the
operation of a relatively intact higher level of mental organisation. The new assemblage of drive
and defence, desexualized and/or restructured, is an entirely different product from what has
preceded it.
part of a meaningful whole’ (Hatcher, 1973, p. 395) or, more explicitly in Myerson
(1965, p. 791) when referring to stages of insight development which, ‘become inte-
grated into a Gestalt through the psychoanalytic process’. Similarly, in Neubauer
(1979, p. 34),‘[a] new Gestalt is established, a reorganised ego structure’. At the same
time, however, the concept of restructuring in the psychoanalytic sense refers in a
much more direct sense to the deeper connotation of psychic or personality change.
Mechanisms and possible components underlying psychoanalytic insight tend to
be difficult to disentangle, reflecting the conception of insight as an ongoing restruc-
turing process. In the main, the experience and interpretation of the transference
situation has generally been considered as the most effective source of gaining insight
(Strachey, 1934; Zilboorg, 1952; Segal, 1962; 1991; Sternbach, 1989). In other words,
whilst interpretations of other aspects of the patient’s mental life are viewed as import-
ant in the development or creation of insight within the individual, it is the inter-
pretations relating to the transference relationship itself that are seen as the most
significant in promoting change. This view probably relates to the conception of
insight in the deeper sense of something that is experienced directly or emotionally.
Thus, in the analysis of the transference relationship, the individual is confronted with
emotions/thoughts which, on resonating with earlier experienced feelings, gain a
direct or immediate quality thereby achieving a deeper personal understanding.
Some authors have emphasised self-observation on the part of the subject as an
important prerequisite or component of the process of insight (e.g. Hatcher, 1973;
Kennedy, 1979; Neubauer, 1979; Abrams, 1981). A few authors have tried to break
up the process of attaining insight into separate components or stages. For example,
on the basis of an analysis of two case reports, Abrams (1981) proposed several
empirical components to ‘insight-producing activity’ that were common to both
cases. These included the following: (1) attention, initially diffuse but becoming
more focused, (2) distinct emotional tone, appropriate to the ideas, (3) recognition
of link between different components (e.g. dreams or memories), (4) free move-
ments within time periods, due to awareness of the meaningful relationship
between past and present, (5) a sense of inner unity within the patient and, (6) at
moment of discovery, a recognition that something new has happened. On the
other hand, Elliot et al. (1994) based their model on a study comparing ‘insight-
events’ in patients undergoing either psychodynamic interpersonal psychotherapy
or cognitive-behavioural therapy. They proposed a five-stage model of insight
comprising of: (1) contextual priming, (2) novel information, (3) initial distanti-
ated processing, (4) ‘insight’ and (5) elaboration. This latter model shares many
similarities with the Gestalt and cognitive models described earlier. This is perhaps
influenced by the fact that these researchers were using a much narrower definition
of insight as a discrete event thus running counter to the general conception of
insight in the psychoanalytic sense. The difficulties in empirically defining and
55 The psychological perspective
assessing insight in such situations, however, is made apparent in this study and
raises questions concerning the validity of extending the model and the methods
used to other areas, particularly, as clearly the content of ‘insight-events’ (as deter-
mined by qualitative analysis) in the two patient groups was very different.
Others have suggested that the ability to empathise was crucial to the development
of insight, viewing the interactive process between subject and analyst as the mech-
anism underlying insight acquisition (Dymond, 1948). In fact, the contribution of
the analyst, in terms of relationship to, and interaction with, the analysand, towards
the attainment of insight, has been the subject of much discussion and of a variety of
disparate views. Part of the problem, however, in trying to clarify some of the differ-
ent perspectives is that there is confusing overlap with different aspects of the rela-
tionship between analyst and insight. These aspects can be broadly divided into three
areas: (i) the meaning of analyst insight, (ii) the role of the analyst in the insight
process and (iii) the role of the analyst in therapeutic change. This last area will be
dealt with in the next section (see below). Concerning the analyst’s insight, whilst
there is general agreement that this has to be differentiated from the patient/subject
insight, it is also apparent that there are opposing views as regards its meaning. Thus,
some authors regard it as the understanding (intellectual and/or emotional) the ana-
lyst has of the patient’s mental life and processes (Richfield, 1954; Blum, 1979; 1992;
Pollock, 1981; Levenson, 1998). Indeed, Pollock (1981), focusing specifically on the
nature of analyst’s insight in relation to understanding elderly patients with cognitive
impairment, proposes a distinction between inductive insight and deductive insight
based on the type of knowledge held by the analyst. Thus, he defines the former as
referring to the understanding of antecedent–consequent linkages as gained from
transference repetition and the latter as referring to the understanding of meaning in
relation to personal phenomena as gained from reconstruction. On the other hand,
others argue that the analyst’s insight cannot refer to the analyst’s understanding of
the patient’s mental life but must refer to self-understanding, i.e. the analyst’s under-
standing of own mental processes (Shengold, 1981; Poland, 1988; Joyce & Stoker,
2000). In other words, there is a polarity between those who do and those who do not
hold that knowledge of the self is crucially different from knowledge of others. Thus,
Anna Freud (1981) differentiated between knowledge of one’s inner world (termed
‘insight’) and knowledge of one’s external world (termed ‘understanding’). Similarly,
Shengold (1981) suggested that the analyst’s insight into the patient’s mind is called
‘outlook’ and should be distinguished from the analyst’s insight into his/her own
mind (‘insight’). Lindén’s (1984; 1985) distinction between insight and outsight is
based on a similar principle.
The role of the analyst in the insight process has likewise been the subject of mixed
views. Here the views range from those who focus on the insight process as some-
thing that is happening predominantly within and by the patient, albeit with
56 Historical and clinical
guidance provided by the analyst (e.g. Bibring, 1954; Segal, 1962; 1991; Blum, 1979;
1992) to those who see the insight process as intrinsically interactive between the
patient and analyst (Loewald, 1960; Shengold, 1981; Poland, 1988; Pulver, 1992;
Etchegoyen, 1993; Levine, 1994; Steiner, 1994; Currin, 2000). Loewald (1960) argues
against the traditional conception of the analyst as neutral and objective, a ‘reflecting
mirror’ whose role is to observe and reflect back to the patient the latter’s conscious
and unconscious processes through verbal communication. Instead, he contends, in
order for the patient to gain insight and attain structural personality changes, signifi-
cant interactions between the patient and analyst must take place in which the ana-
lyst has a specific and active role. The analyst, he maintains, has to function as a
‘co-actor on the analytic stage’ and in order to do that, must be actively empathic and
be able to regress within himself to the level of organisation of the patient. Insight
attainment is thus viewed as an actively interactive process between the patient and
analyst. Some differences emerge, however, between views concerning the nature or
levels of interaction underlying the insight process. For example, Poland (1988)
stresses the deep collaborative aspect of the patient–analyst interaction and the emo-
tional engagement of the analyst in this process, ‘the struggle towards insight is a
shared task, actualised in the transference–countertransference process’ (p. 355). At
the same time, he is clear that within this interaction, the analyst remains ‘an out-
sider’, his mind interacting, but not merging, with that of the patient and, hence, not
becoming part of the patient’s mind. On the other hand, others suggest a more inte-
grative model where there is direct incorporation of the analyst within the patient’s
mind by means of introjection (Strachey, 1934; Olmos-de-Paz, 1990). Some authors
stress the interdependency of insight as self-knowledge and the empathic interactive
relationship with the analyst, pointing out that one could not happen without the
other (Pulver, 1992; Etchegoyen, 1993; Carveth, 1998; Currin, 2000). Others have
focused more on the analyst in the interactive process. For example, Levine (1994)
and Steiner (1994) both emphasise the lack of ‘objectivity’ within the analyst, argu-
ing that the analyst’s interventions were inevitably affected by personal values,
desires, as well as by unconscious influences which were reactivated during the ana-
lytic session. Thus, they stress the need for analysts to have insight into themselves in
order to be effective. Similarly, Currin (2000) emphasises the need to include the
analyst’s insight into him/herself as crucial to the integrative process of insight devel-
opment in the patient. Sternbach (1989) and Sampson (1991) pointed out that it was
possible for patients to develop insights without the necessity of the presence of the
analyst (although based on previous analytic work).
insight within psychoanalytic therapy. The problem is, moreover, beset by the
complexities of identifying goals of psychoanalysis and psychoanalytic psychother-
apies in general (McGlashan & Miller, 1982). Nevertheless, how important is the
attainment of insight for the therapeutic benefit of the patient? Fisher and Greenberg
(1977) suggest that Freud’s own concept of insight in relation to therapy and cure
changed. They point out that while initially Freud maintained the existence of
a direct relationship between the attainment of insight and behavioural change
or cure, he later acknowledged the equal importance of time, working through and
inner resistances. However, Freud’s work can be interpreted rather as a change in
the conceptualisation of insight from a passive (making unconscious conscious) to
an active (confronting forces of resistance) form with both being essential to per-
sonality or therapeutic change (see also Hatcher, 1973). Since Freud’s time, there
have been disparate views on the relationship between insight and change.
As already mentioned, one problem here is differentiating between personality
or psychic or structural change which, in most conceptualisations of psychoana-
lytic insight, is intrinsic to the definition of insight itself and actual therapeutic
change or improvement from symptoms. Often this is not made explicit and is dif-
ficult to infer. Some authors have alluded to this distinction when pointing out that
the development of insight does not entail therapeutic improvement (e.g. Zilboorg,
1952; Neubauer, 1979). More overtly, Lehmkuhl (1989) argues for the need to sep-
arate the concept of emotional insight from the concept of cure and that the for-
mer does not necessarily lead to the latter. Views concerning the role of insight in
contributing to the development of specific therapeutic improvement fall broadly
into three main groups. Firstly, for many, insight remains the crucial factor in
achieving symptomatic relief or cure (Strachey, 1934; Loewenstein, 1956; Segal,
1962; 1991; Blum, 1979; 1992; Schmukler, 1999). Thus, Blum (1979) states that
‘analytic “cure” is primarily effected through insight and not through empathy,
acceptance, tolerance, etc.’ (p. 47) and similarly, a few years later, he reiterates that
insight is the ‘unique critical agent of psychic change in clinical psychoanalysis’
(Blum, 1992, p. 257). His views are echoed strongly by Segal (1962; 1991) who
maintains that insight is central to therapeutic change. Interestingly, she suggests a
number of conditions (e.g. stable analytic environment, right attitude on the part
of the analyst, favourable countertransference, analyst’s correct understanding/
interpretation, correct timing and depth of interpretation) which are also import-
ant in promoting cure but only by providing the right background for the devel-
opment of insight itself. The conditions themselves clearly refer to factors relating
to the analyst. However, these are presented very much as extrinsic to the develop-
ment of insight in contrast to the intrinsic, integrative way such analyst’s factors
are considered when the insight process is conceived as more explicitly inter-
actional (see above). Others qualify the type of insight likely to promote the greatest
58 Historical and clinical
curative effect, e.g. dynamic insight (Reid & Finesinger, 1952), insight through
interpretation (Bibring, 1954) or ostensive insight (Richfield, 1954). On the other
hand, Valenstein (1981) suggests that rather than having a direct curative effect,
insight, through its effect on restoration of ego function, facilitates the conscious
dealing of problems at a secondary process level.
Secondly, many authors in this area express doubts concerning the central role
given to insight in the curative process and suggest that other factors may be more
important in determining therapeutic effect (Kohut, 1977; Carveth, 1998). For
example, Alexander and French (1946) emphasise the role of the ‘corrective emo-
tional experience’, i.e. the curative effect of re-experiencing earlier conflicts within
the transference relationship but in a context of the analyst assuming a different
(and hence therapeutic) attitude from the original person of the past. The analyst
in general has been given a more prominent role in helping to achieve therapeutic
benefit by various means including providing a supportive environment and
through the patient’s relationship with both the analytic/transference personality and
the ‘real’ personality of the analyst (Blum, 1992; De Jonghe et al., 1992; Glucksman,
1993). Some suggest that insight is not the cause but the consequence of thera-
peutic change. For example, Cautela (1965), reporting on three patients undergoing
desensitisation for anxiety problems, found that they showed increased insight with
improvement. He proposed the possibility that some insight-oriented therapies
might be analogous to desensitisation procedures and that as patients relived their
anxieties in the analytic situation, these represented successive re-exposures and it
was this process that resulted in insight. Frank (1993) in a similar though more
integrative vein also suggests that behavioural change (e.g. as achieved through
cognitive-behavioural techniques) could help promote insight. This in turn could
promote further behavioural change and thus it was this cycle between behaviour
and analytic processes that could lead to the positive clinical outcome.
Thirdly, and probably most prevalent, is the view that insight and non-insight
factors are equally important in promoting therapeutic change, particularly where
factors such as interaction with the analyst are viewed as intrinsic to, or interde-
pendent with, the insight process itself (De Jonghe et al., 1992; Pulver, 1992;
Etchegoyen, 1993; Carveth, 1998; Currin, 2000). De Jonghe et al. (1992) provide
a two-factor model in which both insight and ‘support’ are seen as important factors
to therapeutic change based on different schools of psychoanalytic thought. Thus,
insight, as a curative factor, is embedded within the classical Freudian background of
ego psychology and addressing the intrapsychic conflicts thought to be responsible
for pathology. On the other hand, ‘support’, as a curative factor, is contextualised
against the postclassical analytic period (Anna Freud, Klein, Winnicott, etc.) of
a psychology focusing on developmental arrest. Support in this case addresses the
trauma thought to be the original pathogenic factor. Adopting the term ‘mutative’
59 The psychological perspective
to refer to the structural (and clinical) change that can occur with both ‘insight’
and ‘support’, De Jonghe et al. (1992) stress that both processes are important and
occur simultaneously during analysis.
One of the problems in trying to answer the question of the relative contribu-
tion of insight and other factors to symptomatic improvement is the difficulty
faced by empirical research in this area. Whilst the need for systematic research in
this area has been well recognised (Roback, 1971; 1974; Hatcher, 1973; Wallerstein,
1983), in practical terms this does pose numerous problems and consequently
empirical research has been relatively limited. Reviewing empirical studies in this
area, Roback (1971) concludes on the basis of identified methodological limita-
tions that there is a need for future studies to: firstly, adequately define insight in
empirical studies; secondly, employ measures that can capture the degree of insight
produced; thirdly, report on the specific operations carried out by the therapists in
bringing about the development of insight and fourthly, provide validating mater-
ial showing that insight has been developed. Such issues remain valid and have
been reiterated in subsequent reviews (Crits-Christoph et al., 1993). Clearly, how-
ever, one of the major difficulties identified concerns the translation of what is
obviously a complex concept into an operational definition of insight that can cap-
ture and measure at least some of its constituents. As in other clinical areas, a num-
ber of different approaches have been taken and, correspondingly, this is likely to have
contributed to the mixed ensuing results. Some of the early studies, for example,
define insight in terms of the congruence between patient views of themselves and
views held by others, with the assumption that ‘others’ hold the ‘correct’ views
(Dymond, 1948; Feldman & Bullock, 1955; Mann & Mann, 1959). Similar methods
have been adopted in the assessment of insight in patients with organic brain dis-
orders (Chapters 4 and 5) but, in the psychodynamic field, this raises particular ques-
tions concerning the ‘depth’ of self-knowledge that can be assessed in this way.
Another approach to assess insight has been the use of patients’ appraisals
of specific vignettes (Sargent, 1953; Tolor & Reznikoff, 1960). In the method
developed by Tolor and Reznikoff (1960), for example, 27 hypothetical situations
depicting the use of common defence mechanisms were constructed. For each situ-
ation, four possible explanatory statements were provided and ranked according
to the degree of ‘insight’ they were thought to represent. The test was given to a
sample of 68 inpatients with various psychiatric diagnoses (schizophrenia, neurosis,
personality disorder, etc.) and validated by comparing with independent insight
ratings of patients taken by psychiatrists/psychologists involved in the patients’
care. The authors subsequently reported that patients showed less insight on this test
than untrained nurses who in turn showed less insight than trained nurses. The test
was also used by Roback and Abramowitz (1979), who found that schizophrenic
patients scoring higher, were rated by hospital staff as better adjusted behaviourally
60 Historical and clinical
patients’ insight seems to develop linearly as therapy proceeds (Gedo & Schaffer,
1989; Grenyer & Luborsky, 1996; Kivlighan et al., 2000). Others report that
patients’ insight seems to follow a quadratic curve during the course of therapy, i.e.
higher insight found at the beginning and end of treatment with a reduction in
insight apparent during the middle of treatment (O’Connor et al., 1994). The
Kivlighan et al. (2000) study also found an association between higher insight and
a greater reduction of complaints in 12 clients undergoing psychoanalytic psy-
chotherapy. Other studies, however, have not found such a specific relationship
between insight and outcome. In fact, most studies seem to suggest that it is the
combination or interaction of insight and other factors that seems to determine
positive outcome. For example, in the study by Morgan et al. (1982), patients’
perceptions of the therapeutic relationship with their analysts were predictive of
positive outcome. Although patients’ insight correlated with the measures of thera-
peutic alliance, insight on its own did not predict outcome. Similarly, other studies
have specified the combination of insight with other factors such as interaction
(Roback, 1972), transference (Gelso et al., 1991; 1997) or ‘mastery’ (i.e. emotional
self-control as well as self-understanding) (Grenyer & Luborsky, 1996) as being
associated with improved outcome.
2.2.3 Summary
It can be seen that a range of views are held concerning the definition of insight
and approaches taken to its classification and to its empirical assessment. What is
apparent from the various conceptualisations, however, is that psychoanalytic
insight, in its broad sense, and particularly in comparison with conceptualisations
of insight in other disciplines, emerges as a specially complex phenomenon. This
complexity stands out because it relates not only to the content of the concept itself
but also to its singular position within the structure of the psychoanalytic dis-
cipline. Furthermore, these two aspects of psychoanalytic insight are inextricably
linked. As far as the content of the concept is concerned, its striking feature relates
to the depth of knowledge that is invoked. This depth is apparent in two aspects
relating to the concept. Firstly, it refers to a self-knowledge that is beyond ‘normal’
awareness or self-observation but reaches preconscious and unconscious mental
states. This immediately raises complex problems relating to the epistemology of
such unconscious mental processes. Thus, insight in the Gestalt and cognitive
fields involves knowledge of problem solutions that are more or less directly
verifiable. Insight in general psychiatry (Chapter 3) and in neurological states
(Chapters 4 and 5) involves knowledge of illness/disability that is inferred from
patients’ verbal utterances which are subsequently matched with professionals’
judgements of illness. In these other conceptualisations of insight, the validity of
the knowledge that can be determined, in terms of its extent, its limitations and
63 The psychological perspective
studies exploring the role of insight in promoting change are variable and the
specific role of insight remains to be determined.
2.3 Conclusion
Until relatively recently, there has been little interest in the empirical exploration of
insight in clinical psychiatry. However, over the last 10–15 years, increasing numbers
of studies have focused on this area. Such studies have, predominantly, set out to
examine the relationship between patients’ insight and clinical variables, such as prog-
nosis (McEvoy et al., 1989a; Amador et al., 1993), treatment compliance (e.g. Bartkó
et al., 1988; Buchanan, 1992; Cuffel et al., 1996; Mutsatsa et al., 2003) and severity of
psychopathology (e.g. McEvoy et al., 1989b; Amador et al., 1993; 1994; Carroll et al.,
1999; Goldberg et al., 2001; Drake et al., 2004), and have concentrated mainly on
examining this in patients with psychoses (Amador & David, 1998). More recently,
a number of studies have explored the relationship between patients’ insight and
neuropsychological impairment (e.g. Young et al., 1993; 1998; Cuesta & Peralta, 1994;
Lysaker et al., 1994; 1998a; 2002; Marks et al., 2000; McCabe et al., 2002; Mintz et al.,
2004) and, indeed, structural brain lesions as assessed, e.g. by magnetic resonance
imaging (MRI) (Takai et al., 1992; Flashman et al., 2001; Rossell et al., 2003). Much of
this work has yielded, as will be shown in this chapter, somewhat mixed and inconsist-
ent results. Consequently, the relationship between patients’ insight and various clin-
ical variables remains unclear (Marková & Berrios, 1995a, b). Various measures to
assess insight have been developed (e.g. McEvoy et al., 1989b; David, 1990; Amador
et al., 1991; Marková et al., 2003), suggesting that perhaps they capture different
aspects of insight and this might contribute to some of the variability in results.
This chapter reviews the empirical work carried out in this area and focuses on
identifying and defining some of the general and specific difficulties inherent to the
clinical exploration of insight. Firstly, the different definitions of and approaches
to assess insight in the various studies will be examined. Secondly, the results of
studies exploring the relationship between patients’ insight, and clinical and socio-
demographic variables will be reviewed and discussed in the context of the conceptual
and methodological problems of exploring patients’ insight empirically.
One of the most striking issues emerging from review of empirical work on insight
is the absence of a consistent definition of insight and means by which it is
66
67 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
assessed. In fact, there are two separate problems inherent to this issue. First, and
obvious, is the variability itself in definitions of insight and methods of insight
assessment, which clearly carries implications for making meaningful compari-
sons between studies. However, second is also the question of the extent to which a
particular insight measure reflects the definition or concept of insight on which it
is based. This problem more specifically has to do with the difficulties in translat-
ing from a complex concept to a measure that can capture the identified compon-
ents in a clinical form and hence raises different sorts of issues. In general, methods
of assessing insight can be broadly divided into those involving (i) categorical, and
(ii) continuous approaches.
extent to which such measures reflect the concept of insight held varies between the
different studies.
McEvoy et al. (1989a, b, c) were amongst the first to develop a standardised ques-
tionnaire to assess insight in psychotic patients as a continuous process and defined
it in terms of a correlation between the judgements made by patients and those made
by clinicians. They maintained that, ‘patients with insight judge some of their per-
ceptual experiences, cognitive processes, emotions or behaviors to be pathological in
a manner that is congruent with the judgement of involved mental health profes-
sionals, and that these patients believe that they need mental health treatment, at
times including hospitalization and pharmacotherapy’ (McEvoy et al., 1989b, p. 43).
Translating from this concept to an empirical measure, the ‘Insight and Treatment
Attitude Questionnaire’ (ITAQ), they focused on two aspects of their definition.
Firstly, the questions in the measure relate specifically to patients’ attitudes towards
the need for hospital admission, for medication and for future follow-up. Secondly,
the ratings of insight are based explicitly on the extent to which the patient is in
agreement with the mental health professional concerning such attitudes. As a result,
the empirical concept of insight captured by this measure emphasises more the (con-
cordant) views patients have concerning their management rather than any detailed
understanding they have concerning specific morbid experiences. The ITAQ
(11 questions: score range from 0 (no insight) to 22 (maximum insight)) was val-
idated against taped open interviews and was shown to correlate well with clinicians’
judgements of patients’ insight but it clearly reflects this specific and narrower
empirical perspective borne out also by its single factor structure.
A broader conceptualisation of insight is offered by Greenfeld et al. (1989) fol-
lowing an exploratory study of patients’ views concerning their psychotic experi-
ences. They propose a model of insight consisting of five distinct and independent
dimensions relating to: (1) views about symptoms, (2) views about the existence of
an illness, (3) speculations about aetiology, (4) views about vulnerability to recur-
rence and (5) opinions about the value of treatment. Their semi-structured inter-
view addresses each of these areas and insight is described qualitatively and
separately in each domain. Thus, the conception of insight here, both in defin-
itional terms and in its empirical evaluation, is focused more on patients’ under-
standing of what is happening to them and what individual sense they are making
of their experiences. As such, this represents a wider structure of insight. In empir-
ical terms the qualitative capture of these components makes it difficult for ‘rat-
ings’ of insight to be determined and hence comparisons between patients or
patient groups are more cumbersome.
Other multidimensional models of insight have been proposed by David (1990)
and Amador et al. (1991; 1993) and, in both, the emphasis lies in the translation
from the models to structured empirical measures that rate insight quantitatively.
71 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
etc.), and again include separately both current and retrospective views. Thus, this
is a comprehensive clinician-rated measure and, when used in its full form, places
emphasis on the judgements made by patients concerning the nature of their indi-
vidual symptoms. In turn, this is dependent on patients experiencing or showing
the symptoms/signs in question. However, the authors make it clear that the items
and scales can be used independently according to the need of investigators and in
that sense the phenomena of insight elicited will necessarily vary depending on the
scale/item employed. This is because the emphasis can change from rating a general
awareness of being ill, and needing treatment to a more specific awareness and attri-
bution of particular signs. For example, in their large study examining insight in
412 patients, Amador et al. (1994) used an abridged version of this instrument in
which items relating to retrospective awareness and attribution regarding illness
and symptoms were removed. Clearly, from a practical perspective it is not always
possible to evaluate insight in the full detailed and comprehensive way demanded
by the instrument but at the same time it is important to acknowledge that when
the different components of the instrument are used independently they do not in
themselves reflect the overall broad conceptualisation of insight that was the source
of the empirical instrument but, instead, elicit different aspects of insight as origin-
ally defined. However, the structured nature of the measure allows for the different
aspects of insight as captured by the independent components to be clearly defined
and demarcated.
Partly to avoid some of the complexities involved in measuring insight with the
above multidimensional models much of the empirical work on insight in psych-
iatry has used insight ratings taken from specific insight items within more general
psychopathological assessments, such as the PSE (Wing et al., 1974), the Manual
for the Assessment and Documentation of Psychopathology (AMDP) (Guy & Ban,
1982) and particularly, the insight item from the Positive and Negative Syndrome
Scale (PANSS) (Kay et al., 1987). Within these structured psychopathological
measures, insight is assessed along the same scales of increasing/decreasing sever-
ity as the other ‘symptoms’ or ‘signs’. Thus, the ‘lack of insight and judgement’ item
in the PANSS is rated from 1 (absent: no lack of judgement) to 7 (extreme:
emphatic denial of past and present psychiatric illness), with intermediate ratings
in between, in the same way that other ‘symptoms’ are rated as absent to extreme.
Similarly, the insight item in the PSE is rated along a 4-point scale of severity
(0 full insight, 3 denies condition entirely) in line with other ‘symptoms’ in
the schedule. Such measures are useful in that they are practical and simpler to
score but they lack the capacity to capture details of insight content and, despite
the scoring systems, are basically categorical assessments of severity.
A different approach to evaluating patients’ views about their illness was taken
by Carsky et al. (1992) who devised a self-report scale. Rather than concentrating
73 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
with the world (Marková & Berrios, 1992a, b; Marková & Berrios, 1995a, b). In
other words, the concept here focuses on awareness of changes to the self (and how
this affects perceptions of and interactions with one’s world) in relation to the
pathological state affecting the patient. In terms of conceiving insight as a continu-
ous process, the issues behind this particular concept of insight were, firstly, to
capture the intermediate stages of experienced change in the patient, i.e. before the
judgement was reached (if ever) that the changes represented a particular mental
illness and, secondly, to focus more on changes in perceptions of altered self. The
empirical measure, the Insight in Psychosis Questionnaire (IPQ), translated from
this broad concept of insight, consists of 30 items chosen on face validity grounds
(clinical observation together with clinical descriptions (e.g. Conrad, 1958)), to
reflect awareness of possible changes that individuals might experience during the
course of a psychotic episode. Following piloting of the IPQ (Marková & Berrios,
1992b), some items were re-phrased, some were deleted (those relating to views
about hospitalisation and taking medication) and the scoring was simplified to a
dichotomous (agree/disagree) form, and the resultant measure was subsequently
re-standardised (Marková et al., 2003). Clearly, this measure is thus eliciting very
different aspects of insight compared to most of the previous assessments where
the focus was specifically on judgements of mental illness and judgements concern-
ing the need for medication/treatment.
Finally, interesting approaches to assess insight have included the use of
vignettes describing various pathological states (e.g. McEvoy et al., 1993b; Chung
et al., 1997) and discrepancy measures, i.e. the difference in ratings made by
patients and their relatives (e.g. Exner & Murillo, 1975; Taylor & Perkins, 1991;
Dixon et al., 1998). The latter are much less often used generally in psychiatry
compared with empirical studies on insight in patients with neurological states
(Chapters 4 and 5). In the case of vignettes, insight is determined according to
views expressed by patients in relation to the content of the vignettes, e.g. the
extent to which patients feel the vignettes resemble their own clinical states
(McEvoy et al., 1993b) or whether the contents represent mental disorders
(Startup, 1997) or both (Chung et al., 1997). Insight is thus assessed indirectly in
that the phenomenon that is elicited is construed of judgements made in relation
to third-person scenarios with or without further judgements made concerning
any resemblance between such scenarios and patients’ own subjective experiences.
Similar issues to those raised in the review of insight measures used in psychoana-
lytic studies (Chapter 2) apply here. Thus, the aspects of insight captured by this
type of assessment, where patients’ judgements are demanded of external events,
will necessarily be different from insight that focuses on judgements made con-
cerning patients’ views of themselves. The use of a vignette depicting an individual
with psychotic symptoms given to a sample of the general population (Lam et al.,
75 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
1996) as well as in schizophrenic patients, relatives and the general public (Chung
et al., 1997) raised another important issue in terms of conceptualising insight.
Both the above studies reported a low recognition of mental illness and the need
for treatment in general public subjects who were given the vignette. Indeed,
recognition of illness and need for treatment was slightly higher (and hence insight
in those terms better) in patients and relatives compared with the general public
(Chung et al., 1997). This led the authors to highlight the need to consider patients’
insight in the context of the background knowledge or understanding of the soci-
ety and culture they lived in before attributing any impairment of insight to the
psychotic process. Startup (1997) found no association between schizophrenic
patients’ insight as assessed by the ITAQ and their judgements’ of others’ mental
disorder on the basis of vignettes suggesting that these different methods of assess-
ing insight involved independent judgements. This is an important complicating
factor in terms of conceptualising insight and illustrates the need to view insight as
a multidimensional structure rather than solely as a symptom that can be related
to a disease process (see Part II).
3.1.3.1 Definitions
As is evident, definitions of insight vary in terms of specificity, breadth, focus and
complexity. Some studies define insight very specifically e.g. as the recognition of
being mentally ill (Wing et al., 1974; Heinrichs et al., 1985) whereas other studies
use more general definitions such as the recognition of some mental disturbance
(Eskey, 1958; Van Putten et al., 1976). Some studies conceive insight narrowly in
terms of considering views only about illness (Heinrichs et al., 1985; Dittman &
Schüttler, 1990) whilst others broaden the concept to include a range of views
about any experienced changes and about effects of the disturbance on the self and
functioning (Greenfeld et al., 1989; Amador et al., 1991; Marková & Berrios,
1992a). The emphasis in the definitions varies in the studies with some focusing
primarily on the acknowledgement of illness and/or the need for medical treat-
ment (Lin et al., 1979; Bartkó et al., 1988; McEvoy et al., 1989b), and others focus-
ing more on the sense patients are making of their experiences and the effects of
these on themselves (Greenfeld et al., 1989; Marková & Berrios, 1992a; Marková
et al., 2003). And, the complexity of the concepts varies in studies with some defin-
ing insight in fairly simple terms such as a judgement concerning what is happening
76 Historical and clinical
to patients (Eskey, 1958; Wing et al., 1974) whilst other studies propose more com-
plex concepts which include a number of judgements or components relating to
different aspects of their experiences (Greenfeld et al., 1989; David, 1990; Amador
et al., 1991). Moreover, in all these respects, the level to which such definitions are
delineated is also variable. For example, the individual components of the concept
of insight in David (1990) and Amador et al. (1991) are clearly defined and demar-
cated. On the other hand, the broad concept of insight proposed in our work
(Marková & Berrios, 1992a) lacks defined boundaries and, hence, the extent of
knowledge or understanding patients are required to have concerning their condi-
tion and its effects in order to be deemed insightful is less clear.
3.1.3.2 Assessments
Assessment methods differ in a number of ways as well. Firstly, they differ in how
closely they reflect the researchers’ concept of insight. Where there does seem to be
a close match between the original definition and the measure itself, then the same
differences as described above, between the ways in which insight is defined, apply
to the assessment methods themselves. Additionally, differences can be identified
between the ways in which insight is captured and rated. Thus, the main difference
lies between methods using a categorical approach to rate insight (Eskey, 1958;
Small et al., 1965; Van Putten et al., 1976; Heinrichs et al., 1985) and those using a
continuous approach (McEvoy et al., 1989; David, 1990; Marková and Berrios 1992b;
Amador et al., 1993). Categorical assessments are simpler to use and generally
patients can be rated as having insight, not having insight or having partial insight
according to the particular criteria employed. However, judgements are necessarily
cruder in content and the anchor points between categories are often not
clear. Continuous measures on the other hand tend to capture more specific
information but vary in terms of the different components included in the meas-
ures as well as the particular focus (e.g. acknowledgement of illness or need for
medication or awareness of effects, etc.). In addition, further differences exist
between the methods using clinician rating of patients’ insight (Greenfeld et al.,
1989; McEvoy et al., 1989; David et al., 1992; Amador et al., 1993) and those using
self-rating measures (Birchwood et al., 1994; Marks et al., 2000; Marková et al.,
2003). Thus the clinician ratings necessarily incorporate additional factors, which
shape the clinician’s judgements concerning patients’ insight. The self-rating meas-
ures are more direct expressions of patients’ views but do not allow for elaboration
or explanation of answers. Similarly, methods using discrepancy measures involve
assumptions concerning the judgements made by non-affected individuals
and incorporate additional factors relevant to those whilst assessments using
vignettes demand different types of judgements. These issues are explored in detail
in Part II.
77 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
3.1.3.3 Implications
The differences in the conceptualisation of insight and in the measures devised to
assess insight, that are clearly present in the studies detailed above, have important
consequences. Firstly, they serve to highlight the difficulties in attempting to define
in a practical sense what is a complex concept. Both the content and the limits or
boundaries of the concept remain ill defined. Secondly, it is likely that, given such
differences in definitions and approaches used to assess insight, different aspects of
insight are elicited and rated in the various studies. This is an essential point as it
means that comparisons between results of the studies will be problematic as it
cannot be assumed that they are all capturing the same insight phenomenon. This
is not to say that the insight measures are all eliciting completely different phe-
nomena. Indeed, most of the studies, which have sought to correlate some of the
insight measures have found generally modestly significant correlations between
different insight assessments (e.g. David et al., 1992; Sanz et al., 1998; Francis &
Penn, 2001) or different subscales/dimensions of the same insight measure (David
et al., 1992; Larøi et al., 2000). However, some studies report more mixed results
with modest correlations between only some subscales/dimensions of insight
measures either with each other (Amador et al., 1993; McCabe et al., 2000) or with
other insight assessments (Marks et al., 2000). It is likely that whilst the various
insight measures may be capturing something that is common to most of them,
there will be, nevertheless, differences between them in the detail of the phenom-
ena elicited. Further support for this claim comes from the finding that in a same
study, different insight measures yield different results as far as relationship to clin-
ical variables are concerned (David et al., 1992; Cuesta et al., 1998; Sanz et al., 1998;
Cuesta et al., 2000). Furthermore, because, as was reviewed, differences between
the insight assessments occur at more than the content level, then comparisons
and generalisations between studies in terms of outcomes become more problem-
atic and it is questionable whether stringent statistical methods such as meta-
analysis (Mintz et al., 2003) may be applied to summarise such studies in a
meaningful way.
The question then is what can the empirical studies on insight tell us about the
nature of insight in patients with psychiatric disorders? The increased interest evi-
dent in exploring insight clinically seems to have arisen, in part, following observa-
tions that lack of insight is extremely prevalent in patients with psychiatric illnesses.
Indeed, ‘lack of insight’ was described as the most frequent symptom of schizo-
phrenia in the Report of the International Pilot Study of Schizophrenia (World Health
78 Historical and clinical
Organization, 1973). However, the basic question underpinning the empirical stud-
ies exploring insight in relation to patients’ symptoms, illnesses and various socio-
cultural and demographic variables, whether or not this is stated explicitly, is one
concerning the nature of insight as a clinical phenomenon. This question can be
reduced to some primary issues, namely: (i) is lack of insight in mental illness
inherent to the mental disorder, i.e. a product of the disease process and hence to be
considered as a ‘symptom’ in the same way as other illness features or (ii) can insight
be considered a separate or independent mental phenomenon, one that can be
affected by having a mental or other disorder, but also open to the internal and
external influences that determine individual knowledge/beliefs. In effect, this basic
issue is simply a reformulation of the question with which psychiatry has struggled
since the notion of insight was conceived as an independent phenomenon (Chapter 1).
In other words, is it possible for someone with a ‘disordered’ mind to have full
awareness/insight of the disorder itself? In spite of numerous studies examining the
relationship between insight and severity of the mental disorder or insight and cog-
nitive impairment, it remains difficult to answer this basic question. As has already
been seen, complexities around the definition and assessment of insight are an
important factor in this. However, consequently, the relationship between insight
and other clinical variables, such as prognosis, severity of psychopathology, treat-
ment compliance, cognitive impairment, etc. remains unclear.
Table 3.1 Studies reporting NO association between insight and socio-demographic variables
Lysaker et al. n 101 SUMD: abridged No differences between patients with and
(1998b) without insight in terms of their
backgrounds
Peralta and n 54 AMDP: three items (LII) No correlation between socio-
Cuesta (1998) demographic variables and insight at
admission, discharge or change in
insight
Schwartz n 64 PANSS: item G12 No correlation with age, total years of
(1998a) treatment
Larøi et al. n 21 SUMD No correlation with age, gender,
(2000) education and age at onset
Chen et al. n 80 SUMD: abridged No correlation with age, education,
(2001) illness duration
Schwartz (2001) n 223 SUMD No correlation with age, gender,
substance abuse
McCabe et al. n 89 SAI No correlation with socio-demographic
(2002) variables
Arduini et al. n 64 SUMD: abridged No correlation with age, gender, years of
(2003) education, duration of illness
* Diagnoses not specified here, since detailed in text and subsequent tables, but majority of patients diagnosed
with psychotic disorder, mainly schizophrenia, also schizoaffective, bipolar, affective and mixed psychoses.
Abbreviations: AMDP-LII: Lack of Insight Index from three items of the Manual for the Assessment and
Documentation of Psychopathology; ITAQ: Insight and Treatment Attitude Questionnaire; PANSS: Positive and
Negative Syndrome Scale; PSE: Present State Examination; SAI: Schedule for Assessing Insight; SUMD: Scale
to Assess Unawareness of Mental Disorder.
Table 3.2 Studies reporting some correlation between insight and socio-demographic variables
Linn (1965) n 593 Answers to questions about Increased duration of illness associated
what patients believed with reduced insight
was wrong with them
Soskis and n 32 Standardised questionnaire Women have more positive attitude
Bowers (1969) on attitudes to psychosis to psychosis than men
Appelbaum n 50 Standardised questionnaire: Men have greater insight than women.
et al. (1981) seven conceptual categories Younger age is associated with better
insight
Wciórka n 100 Structured questionnaire Patients with negative, isolating
(1988) on attitudes to illness attitudes had lower levels
of education
Caracci et al. n 20 Awareness of psychiatric Increased duration of illness associated
(1990) disorder dichotomised with reduced awareness of psychiatric
(present/absent). disorder and reduced awareness of
Awareness of involuntary movements
involuntary movements
(0–3 rating)
Taylor and n 30 1. Question whether they Poor insight associated with more
Perkins (1991) have mental health problem previous hospital admissions, female
2. Discrepancy between patients, older age
patients and staff on
Awareness of Disabilities
Scale
Amador et al. n 43 SUMD Age at first psychiatric evaluation
(1993) associated with insight (greater
retrospective awareness of achieved
effects of medication associated with
earlier age of psychiatric contact)
David et al. n 150 PSE item 104 Patients with better insight had parents
(1995) from socio-economic classes I and II
Kemp and n 29 SUMD: abbreviated Women showed increased insight
Lambert (1995) (attribution of past illness) over course
of hospital admission
Cuffel et al. n 89 Awareness of illness Women showed reduced awareness.
(1996) interview (recognition Use of illicit drugs associated
of mental illness and with increased awareness
need for psychiatric treatment)
82 Historical and clinical
Fennig et al. n 189 Insight item from Being married was associated with
(1996) Hamilton Depression better insight. (No correlation with age,
Rating Scale gender, ethnicity, etc.)
Lysaker et al. n 81 PANSS: item G12 Increased insight associated with earlier
(1998a) age of first hospitalisation
Lysaker et al. n 74 PANSS: item G12 Patients with impaired insight were
(1999) significantly older
Goldberg et al. n 211 PANSS: item G12 Association between insight and race:
(2001) white patients rated greater insight than
black patients.
Association between current substance
abuse and insight
83 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
Pyne et al. n 177 Dichotomised according to Duration of illness and younger age
(2001) answer whether patients correlated with reduced insight in
believed they had a outpatients.
mental illness.
* Diagnoses not specified here, since detailed in text and subsequent tables, but majority of patients diagnosed
with psychotic disorder, mainly schizophrenia, also schizoaffective, bipolar, affective and mixed psychoses.
Abbreviations: IPQ: Insight in Psychosis Questionnaire; ITAQ: Insight and Treatment Attitude Questionnaire;
PANSS: Positive and Negative Syndrome Scale; PSE: Present State Examination; SAI: Schedule for Assessing
Insight; SAI-E: Schedule for Assessing Insight – Expanded version; SAIQ: Self-Appraisal of Illness Questionnaire;
SUMD: Scale to Assess Unawareness of Mental Disorder.
few studies that find associations, yield conflicting results (Table 3.2). Age at first
admission to hospital was found in four studies to be related to insight (Kim et al.,
1997; Lysaker et al., 1998a; Weiler et al., 2000) or an aspect of insight (Amador et al.,
1993) with increased insight being associated with earlier age of hospital admission.
Interestingly, in a larger study using the abbreviated version of the SUMD (which did
not include ratings of retrospective awareness), this latter finding was not replicated
(Amador et al., 1994). Duration of illness was also found to be associated with insight
in three studies with increasing length of illness correlating with poorer insight (Linn,
1965; Caracci et al., 1990; Marks et al., 2000). Pyne et al. (2001), on the other hand,
only found an association between duration of illness and insight in their outpatients
as opposed to their inpatients. Furthermore, their reported association was in the
opposite direction from the previous studies in that patients with shorter duration of
illness seemed to show poorer insight. Owing to the methodological issues raised earl-
ier, it is difficult to draw very much from these results and there may be effects from
various confounding factors, e.g. as severity of illness itself. A few studies reported
a significant correlation between insight and education (MacPherson et al., 1996;
Rossell et al., 2003) whilst Sanz et al. (1998), in their study comparing the use of sev-
eral insight measures, found that insight was related to education only when insight
was assessed with the IPQ instrument. The study by David et al. (1995), appears to be
the sole to report a positive association between insight and higher social class.
Of interest are the studies that have started to explore the relationship between
insight and ethnicity. Conducting a case-note study with the specific aim of exam-
ining the relationship between ethnicity and patients’ insight, Johnson and Orrell
(1996) found that white British patients were rated as having significantly more
insight than other ethnic groups. Though, as the authors point out, the design of
the study did not permit administration of standardised or detailed assessments of
84 Historical and clinical
Table 3.3 Studies reporting on associations between insight and previous hospital admissions
Takai et al. n 57 PSE: insight item More previous hospital admissions associated
(1992) with increased insight
* Diagnoses not specified here, since detailed in text and subsequent tables, but majority of patients diagnosed
with psychotic disorder, mainly schizophrenia, also schizoaffective, bipolar, affective and mixed psychoses.
Abbreviations: IPQ: Insight in Psychosis Questionnaire; ITAQ: Insight and Treatment Attitude Questionnaire;
PANSS: Positive and Negative Syndrome Scale; PSE: Present State Examination; SAI: Schedule for Assessing
Insight; SAI-E: Schedule for Assessing Insight – Expanded version; SUMD: Scale to Assess Unawareness of
Mental Disorder.
87 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
do patients who show greater insight perhaps seek medical help more frequently and
are more willing to accept hospital admissions? Some indirect support could be
given to this view by the results of studies showing that informal patients show
greater insight than patients admitted involuntarily (McEvoy et al., 1989c; David
et al., 1992; Ghaemi et al., 1995; Upthegrove et al., 2002). On the other hand, the study
by Pyne et al. (2001) suggests a more complicated association between patients’
insight and hospital admissions showing that a significant relationship was only evi-
dent in outpatients whereas inpatients at the time of the study showed the opposite
association. Results also point to the possibility that perhaps some aspects of insight
might be more relevant in the association between hospital admissions than others
(Greenfeld et al., 1989; Amador et al., 1993; Sanz et al., 1998). An interesting recent
study explored the question in a different way by comparing insight (SUMD) in first
episode psychosis patients (n 144) with insight in multiple episode psychosis
patients (n 312) (Thompson et al., 2001). They found that a significantly greater
proportion of multiple episode psychotic patients were aware of having a mental dis-
order and were aware of the effects of medication than first episode psychosis
patients. The researchers thus suggested that over time patients might show
increased insight into their illness as they learn from their experiences, become less
defensive and become adept at using medical terms. They did caution, however, that
using medical terms may not necessarily reflect true insight. The question of the con-
tribution made by past experience towards the attainment of insight therefore
remains to be answered. Empirical work in this field is additionally difficult because
of the problems involved in trying to control for the multitude of variables likely
to be important in the development of insight.
Table 3.4 Studies reporting on association between insight and clinical outcome
*Diagnoses not specified here, since detailed in text and subsequent tables, but majority of patients diagnosed
with psychotic disorder, mainly schizophrenia, also schizoaffective, bipolar, affective and mixed psychoses.
Exceptions are indicated.
Abbreviations: BABS: Brown Assessment of Beliefs Scale; BFR: Brief Follow-up Rating; ITAQ: Insight and
Treatment Attitude Questionnaire; KAS: Katz Adjustment Scale; OCD: Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder;
SUMD: Scale to Assess Unawareness of Mental Disorder.
It can be seen that results of studies are varied. Slightly more studies appear to sug-
gest that better insight is associated with improved clinical outcome (Small et al.,
1965; Exner & Murillo, 1975; McGlashan & Carpenter, 1981; Heinrichs et al., 1985;
McEvoy et al., 1989a; Greenfeld et al., 1991; Amador et al., 1993). A few studies report
no association with prognosis (Eskey, 1958; Linn, 1965; Eisen et al., 2001) and some
suggest that insight is associated with worse clinical outcome (Kahn & Fink, 1959;
Hankoff et al., 1960b). Yet others indicate more mixed results with insight relating to
some aspects of good but also to some aspects of worse outcome (Hankoff et al.,
1960a; Roback & Abramowitz, 1979; Taylor & Perkins, 1991). However, given the
particular variability between the studies not only in how insight is assessed but also
in the different clinical outcome indicators and different patient groups, the rela-
tionship between insight and prognosis cannot yet be determined.
Table 3.5 Studies reporting on association between insight and severity of psychopathology
– retrospective
awareness and
reduced depression
disorganisation,
stereotyped thinking,
suspiciousness, etc
Depression Patients:
no correlation between
I and severity at
any time
David n 150 PSE: item 104 PSE total score No correlation between
et al. (1995) Mixed psychoses I and global severity
(DSM-IIIR), inpatients,
follow-up
Baier n 37
et al. (2000) Schiz./schizoaff. IS SAPS No correlation with
Inpatients and Davidhizar SANS severity except: poor I
outpatients et al. (self- associated with more
rating insight formal thought disorder
scale)
explained by symptom
severity
Abbreviations: AMDP-LII: Lack of Insight Index from three items of the Manual for the Assessment and
Documentation of Psychopathology; BABS: Brown Assessment of Belief Scale; BDD: Body Dysmorphic
Disorder; BDD-Y-BOCS: Yale-Brown Obsessive Compulsive Scale modified for Body Dysmorphic Disorder;
BDI: Beck Depression Inventory; BPRS: Brief Psychiatric Rating Scale; CASH: Comprehensive Assessment
Schedule History; CGI: Clinical Global Impressions global severity item; HDRS: Hamilton Depression Rating
Scale; HEN: High Royds Evaluation of Negativity Scale; I: Insight; IPQ: Insight in Psychosis Questionnaire; IS:
Insight Scale; ITAQ: Insight and Treatment Attitude Questionnaire; MADRS: Montgomery and Asberg
Depression Rating Scale; OCD: Obsessive Compulsive Disorder; PANSS: Positive and Negative Syndrome Scale;
PSE: Present State Examination; PSYRATS: Psychotic Symptom Rating Scales; Rx: Treatment; SADS: Schedule
for Affective Disorders; SAI: Schedule for Assessing Insight; SAI-E: Schedule for Assessing Insight – Expanded
version; SANS: Scale for the Assessment of Negative Symptoms; SAPS: Scale for the Assessment of Positive
Symptoms; Schiz.: Schizophrenia; Schizaff.: Schizoaffective disorder; SCI-FARS: Structured Clinical Interview
for the Functional Assessment Rating Scale; SMS: Scale for Manic States; SUMD: Scale to Assess Unawareness
of Mental Disorder; Y-BOCS: Yale-Brown Obsessive Compulsive Scale; YMRS: Young’s Mania Rating Scale.
aspects of the patient’s illness (Sevy et al., 2004). Reporting on an opposite direction
of association between insight and severity of illness, one study examining insight
in patients with anorexia nervosa found that good insight related to more severe ill-
ness as assessed by duration of hospitalisation and degree of emaciation (Greenfeld
et al., 1991). Finally, some studies using several insight assessment measures at the
same time report on different associations between insight and severity of illness
with the different measures used (Sanz et al., 1998; Cuesta et al., 2000).
In the light of the variable outcomes of these empirical studies, it is clear that the
relationship between insight and severity of illness is not yet possible to define
definitively. The finding that some studies have reported improvements in patients’
insight over time, which seem to be independent of improvements in psy-
chopathology over the same time (McEvoy et al., 1989b; Jørgensen, 1995; Fennig
et al., 1996; Cuesta et al., 2000), further complicates the overall picture. In addition,
103 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
Table 3.6 Studies reporting NO association between insight and cognitive function
Insight Neuropsychology
Study Patients assessment assessment Results
Insight Neuropsychology
Study Patients assessment assessment Results
Insight Neuropsychology
Study Patients assessment assessment Results
(Re-labelling dimension on
SAI correlated with motor
and arithmetic functions).
Cognitive deficit failed to
predict poor insight
Arduini n 64 SUMD: abridged WCST No correlation with WCST
et al. (2003) Schiz., bipolar in either or both patient
(DSM-IV) groups
Freudenreich n 122 SUMD: modified WCST, No association between
et al. (2004) Schiz. WAIS-III – IQ, symptom awareness and
(DSM-IV) CVLT, Stroop, cognitive variables
Benton’s Controlled
Word Association Test
Mintz et al. n 253 PANSS: Cognitive Battery: No association between
(2004) Schiz. item G12 COWAT, category insight and cognition at
spectrum, fluency, verbal, baseline or at follow up
DSM-IV auditory, visual assessments
F/u: n memory, WCST,
180 at 1 year visuo-constructive
skills, attention,
Trails A,B, etc
Abbreviations: AMDP-LII: Lack of Insight Index from three items of the Manual for the Assessment and
Documentation of Psychopathology; BPRS: Brief Psychiatric Rating Scale; FARS: Functional Assessment
Rating Scale; FBS: Frankfurter Befindlichketsskala; I: Insight; IPQ: Insight in Psychosis Questionnaire; ITAQ:
Insight and Treatment Attitude Questionnaire; PANSS: Positive and Negative Syndrome Scale; PSE: Present
State Examination; SAI: Schedule for Assessing Insight; Schiz.: Schizophrenia; Schizaff.: Schizoaffective
Disorder; SUMD: Scale to Assess Unawareness of Mental Disorder.
Neuropsychology abbreviations: CAMCOG: Cognitive section of the Cambridge Examination for Mental
Disorders of the Elderly; COWAT: Controlled Word Association Test; HWAST: Halstead-Wepman Aphasia
Screening Test; MMSE: Mini-Mental State Examination; NART: National Adult Reading Test; RBANS:
Repeatable Battery for the Assessment of Neuropsychological Status; RBMT: Rivermead Behavioural Memory
Test; Rey.: Rey’s Complex Figure Test; RMTW/F: Recognition Memory Test for Words and Faces; WAIS (-R):
Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale (Revised); WCST: Wisconsin Card Sorting Test; WMS: Wechsler Memory
Scale; WRAT-R: Wide Range Achievement Test-Reading.
107 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
Table 3.7 Studies reporting SOME association between insight and cognitive function
Insight Neuropsychology
Study Patients assessment assessment Results
David n 91 SAI NART Better I (on SAI but not PSE)
et al. (1992) Psychotic PSE: item 104 associated with higher IQ
(PSE)
Young et al. n 31 SUMD WCST, verbal Poor I associated with worse
(1993) Chronic schiz. fluency test, performance on WCST and
(DSM-IIIR) trails A and B, worse IQ. No correlation
WAIS-R IQ with verbal fluency or trails
Lysaker and n 92 PANSS: WCST, Slosson Poor I associated with lower
Bell (1994) Schiz./schizaff. item G12 Intelligence Test IQ, poorer performance on
(DSM-IIIR) WCST
Lysaker n 85 PANSS: WCST, Slosson Poor I associated with lower
et al. (1994) Schiz./schizaff. item G12 Intelligence Test, IQ, poor performance on
(DSM-IIIR) Gorham Proverbs WCST, bizarre/
Test (GPT) idiosyncratic thought
on GPT
Lysaker and n 44 PANSS: WCST, Slosson Greater levels of cognitive
Bell (1995) Schiz./schizaff. item G12 Intelligence Test, impairment predicted less
(DSM-IIIR) Digit Symbol improvement in I
Subtest (WAIS-R),
Gorham Proverbs
Cuffel n 89 Interview rating Neurobehavioural Poor I associated with
et al. (1996) Schiz. awareness of Cognitive Status cognitive impairment
(DSM-IIIR) illness Examination
McEvoy n 32 ITAQ WAIS-R (block, Poor total I associated
et al. (1996) Schiz. vocab), Judgement with poor R-L orient
(DSM-IIIR) of Line Orientation, Subscale from ITAQ (poor
Rey., Finger awareness of mental illness)
localisation test, associated with impaired
R-L orientation, WCST, block,
COWAT, FFT, R-L orientation
WCST
Voruganti n 52 PANSS: COGLAB (includes Poor I associated with poor
et al. (1997) Schiz. item G12 WCST, vigilance, performance on span of
(DSM-IIIR) span of apprehension, apprehension, backward
illusion task, masking task and WCST
reaction time, etc.)
Lysaker n 81 PANSS: WAIS-R, WCST, Poor I associated with
et al. (1998a) Schiz./schizaff. item G12 subtests of WMSR, impaired WCST scores
(DSM-IIIR) HVLT, CPT No correlation with other
tests
108 Historical and clinical
Insight Neuropsychology
Study Patients assessment assessment Results
Insight Neuropsychology
Study Patients assessment assessment Results
Abbreviations: I: Insight; IS: Insight Scale; ITAQ: Insight and Treatment Attitude Questionnaire; PANSS:
Positive and Negative Syndrome Scale; PSE: Present State Examination; SAI: Schedule for Assessing Insight;
SAI-E: Schedule for Assessing Insight – Extended version; SAIQ: Self-Appraisal of Illness Questionnaire; Schiz.:
Schizophrenia; Schizaff.: Schizoaffective Disorder; SUMD: Scale to Assess Unawareness of Mental Disorder.
Neuropsychology abbreviations: AMNART: American version of the NART; BFRT: Benton Facial Recognition
Test; COGLAB: Cognitive Laboratory computerised test battery; COWAT: Controlled Word Association Test;
CPT: Continuous Performance Test; CVLT: California Verbal Learning Test; DSDT: Digit Span Distractibility
Test; FFT: Figural Fluency Test; HVLT: Hopkins Verbal Learning Test; NART: National Adult Reading Test; Rey.:
Rey’s Complex Figure Test; RMTW/F: Recognition Memory Test for Words and Faces; RVLT: Rey Auditory
Verbal Learning Test; SPAN: Span of Apprehension Test; WAIS (-R): Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale
(Revised); WCST: Wisconsin Card Sorting Test; WMS(R): Wechsler Memory Scale (Revised).
1997; Lysaker et al., 1998; Young et al., 1998; Larøi et al., 2000; Drake & Lewis, 2003;
Rossell et al., 2003; Keshavan et al., 2004). However, the studies often differ in the
specific frontal lobe impairments found (Table 3.7) or some aspects/dimensions of
poor insight (McEvoy et al., 1996; Mohamed et al., 1999; Marks et al., 2000; Smith
110 Historical and clinical
et al., 2000; Buckley et al., 2001; Lysaker et al., 2002). Nevertheless, many other stud-
ies specifically exploring this relationship have failed to find an association between
poor insight and impairment on tests of frontal lobe function (Cuesta & Peralta,
1994, Cuesta et al., 1995; David et al., 1995; Almeida et al., 1996; Kemp & David, 1996;
Collins et al., 1997; Dickerson et al., 1997; Sanz et al., 1998; Goldberg et al., 2001;
Schwartz, 2001; Arduini et al., 2003; Freudenreich, et al. 2004; Mintz et al., 2004).
Curiously, one study reports a stronger association between poor insight and
impaired temporal lobe function (Keshavan et al., 2004).
An interesting hypothesis, attempting to explain such inconsistency of results in
studies exploring the relationship between insight and cognitive deficits, is sug-
gested by Startup (1996). He proposes that the relationship between insight and
cognitive deficits might more usefully be conceived as curvilinear on account of
the contribution of psychological or motivational factors in the manifestation of
insight. In other words, existing neurological and psychological theories put for-
ward to explain impairments of insight are not mutually exclusive and might con-
tribute proportionately according to the level of cognitive impairment suffered by
the individual. In a study involving 26 patients with schizophrenia (DSM-IIIR),
Startup administered a number of tests sensitive to frontal lobe dysfunction
(Cognitive Estimates, Verbal Fluency, Trail (B) Making Test, Stroop Test and Stylus
Maze Test), and used the ITAQ to assess insight. He was able to demonstrate that a
quadratic, rather than a linear, model could help explain the relationship between
insight and cognitive deficits, accounting for 56% of the variance. Following on
from this, Lysaker et al. (2003) carried out a cluster analysis on 64 patients
with schizophrenia spectrum disorder and, using the PANSS insight item, they
divided patients into those with good insight and those with poor insight. On
administering tests of frontal lobe function (WCST), they obtained three groups of
patients, namely, patients with good insight and average performance on WCST;
patients with poor insight and average performance on the WCST, and patients
with poor insight and poor performance on the WCST. They thus concurred with
Startup (1996) that perhaps there are subgroups of patients who may show poor
insight for different reasons: poor cognition on the one hand might underlie
problems in understanding reality in one group and a tendency to ignore or
deny unpleasant things might contribute more to impairment of insight in
another group.
Overall, however, it is evident from these studies that the relationship between
insight into mental illness and cognitive function also continues to be unclear.
Table 3.8 Studies reporting on association between insight and level of functioning/quality of life
Insight Measure of
Study Patients assessment function/quality Results
Insight Measure of
Study Patients assessment function/quality Results
Insight Measure of
Study Patients assessment function/quality Results
Abbreviations: AMDP-LII: Lack of Insight Index from three items of the Manual for the Assessment and
Documentation of Psychopathology; BQOLI: Brief Quality of Life Interview; CES: Customer Experience of
Stigma; CSPAS: Cannon-Spoor Premorbid Adjustment Scale; DSS: Davidhizar et al. – Self-Rating Scale for
Insight; FARS: Functional Assessment Rating Scale; GAF: Global Assessment of Functioning; GARF: Global
Assessment of Relational Functioning; GAS: Global Assessment Scale; I: Insight; IMSR: Interview Measure of
Social Relationships; IPQ: Insight in Psychosis Questionnaire; IS: Insight Scale; ITAQ: Insight and Treatment
Attitude Questionnaire; LQOLP: Lancashire Quality of Life Profile; LSP: Life Skills Profile; PANSS: Positive
and Negative Syndrome Scale; PSE: Present State Examination; QOL: Quality of Life Scale (Heinrichs et al.,
1984); QOLI: Quality of Life Interview (Lehman, 1988); SAI: Schedule for Assessing Insight; SBS: Social
Behaviour Scale; Schiz.: Schizophrenia; Schizaff.: Schizoaffective Disorder; SFS: Social Functioning Scale; SOL-I:
Standard of Living Questionnaire; SPS: Social Performance Schedule; SUMD: Scale to Assess Unawareness of
Mental Disorder.
115 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
poorer psychosocial function and quality of life (O’Connor & Herrman, 1993;
Lysaker et al., 1994; Peralta & Cuesta, 1994; Dickerson et al., 1997; Lysaker, et al.,
1998b; Larøi et al., 2000; Pini et al., 2001). One study reports that poor insight is
associated with some pre-morbid adjustment disorders in late adolescence and in
early adulthood (Debowska et al., 1998). Finally, there are studies, which yield
mixed results and generally these employ more detailed measures of different
aspects of psychosocial functioning and/or quality of life. For example, using the
Quality of Life Interview together with a Social Behaviour Scale, Smith et al. (1999)
found that whilst poor insight in schizophrenic/schizoaffective patients was related
to social behavioural deficits, their subjective quality of life assessments were not
related to insight. In contrast, White et al. (2000) found that better insight in
patients with schizophrenia was related not only to having more close friends and
family but also to less satisfaction with their relationships. And other studies, also
using more detailed social skills and quality of life measures, have suggested that
poor insight relates to impairment in some social skills but not in others (Francis &
Penn, 2001; Goldberg et al., 2001).
Insight
Study Patients assessment Results
Kemp and n 74
David (1996) (SZ-43, SZF-7, BPm-17, SAI Insight higher in non-SZ diagnostic
BPd-3, SA-4) DSM-IIIR groups
117 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
Insight
Study Patients assessment Results
Abbreviations: AMDP-LII: Lack of Insight Index from three items of the Manual for the Assessment and
Documentation of Psychopathology; AP: Affective Psychosis; BABS: Brown Assessment of Belief Scale; BDD:
Body Dysmorphic Disorder; BP: Bipolar Affective Disorder; BPd: Bipolar Depression; BPm: Bipolar Manic; BPp:
Bipolar Psychotic Disorder; HDRS: Hamilton Depression Rating Scale; I: Insight; IPQ: Insight in Psychosis
Questionnaire; ITAQ: Insight and Treatment Attitude Questionnaire; MDD: Major Depressive Disorder without
psychosis; OCD: Obsessive Compulsive Disorder; OP: Other Psychosis; PANSS: Positive and Negative Syndrome
Scale; PD: Psychotic Depression; PMDD: Major Depressive Disorder with Psychosis; PSE: Present State
Examination; SA: Schizoaffective Disorder; SAI: Schedule for Assessing Insight; SUMD: Scale to Assess
Unawareness of Mental Disorder; SZ: Schizophrenia; SZF: Schizophreniform Disorder; UD: Unipolar Depression.
118 Historical and clinical
(Sanz et al., 1998). Factors likely to contribute to the inconsistencies in this area
include not just the differences in insight assessments but also the specific diag-
nostic criteria used. In addition, the proportions of patient numbers in the differ-
ent diagnostic categories vary considerably across the studies described.
There have been few systematic empirical studies exploring insight in conditions
other than the various psychoses. Why the exploration of insight empirically should
be limited to the psychoses is not so clear, except presumably that since loss of
insight has long been intrinsic to the definitional criteria of certain psychotic symp-
toms such as delusions (Berrios, 1994b), examination of insight has been promoted
by the conditions where its loss is so dramatically apparent. Indeed, as far as the
so-called anxiety, dissociative disorders, milder depressive disorders, etc. (i.e., those
conditions traditionally conceived in the ‘neurotic’ sphere where, conventionally,
insight is assumed to be present), are concerned, much of the empirical work has
taken place predominantly in the psychodynamic field (Chapter 2). However, it is of
interest, that some of the traditional views concerning the notion that the presence
of insight can be used as a criterion to differentiate between the psychoses and the
so-called neuroses have begun to be challenged in practical as well as in theoretical
ways. For example, in recognition of the increasingly common observations that
patients with obsessive-compulsive disorders (OCD) show a wide range of insight,
particularly as far as regarding their obsessions/compulsions as senseless is con-
cerned (e.g. Insel & Akiskal, 1986; Lelliott et al., 1988), then the DSM-IV Field Trial,
using a structured scale, specifically explored insight in 431 patients with OCD (Foa &
Kozak, 1995). Their conclusions, confirming that patients with OCD do show a
range of insight resulted in a change made to the previous definitional criteria of
DSM-IIIR, and a new specifier of ‘OCD with poor insight’ was introduced into
DSM-IV (American Psychiatric Association, 1994). Nevertheless, there has not yet
been much work exploring the relationship between insight in patients with OCD
and other clinical correlates. Some small earlier studies yield mixed results. For
example, one study suggested that patients with poor insight into their obsessions/
compulsions showed worse clinical outcome after exposure treatment (Foa, 1979).
On the other hand, a larger study by Lelliott et al. (1988) found no difference in out-
come following behaviour therapy between those patients with and without insight.
Another more recent study found that patients with poorer insight in OCD (i.e.
patients who had strong beliefs in the feared consequences of not carrying out
their compulsions) had worse outcome following behaviour therapy than those
who expressed less strong beliefs in the consequences of not carrying out their
compulsions (Foa et al., 1999) (Table 3.4). However, the same study also found that
patients who showed less insight into their OCD (in terms of articulating fears con-
cerning consequences of obsessional beliefs) seemed to benefit more from the
behaviour treatment than those who showed better insight. In other words, the
119 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
mania and found that patients tended to show poor insight and that this did not
improve over the course of hospital admission. In contrast, Yen et al. (2003)
reported an overall improvement in insight in patients with mania as their manic
symptoms resolved though they found also that in some cases patients’ insight
remained either unchanged or worsened. Pallanti et al. (1999), on the other hand,
focusing on clinical differences between patients with bipolar I and II disorders,
found that patients with bipolar II disorders seemed to show poorer insight than
bipolar I patients. A different study, reported by Peralta and Cuesta (1998), explored
differences in insight (using the AMDP: 3 items) between patients with mania
(n 21) and patients with depression (n 33) and looked at the effects of psych-
otic symptoms in relation to insight. They found that manic patients tended to
show less insight than depressed patients, that patients with depression and psych-
otic symptoms had less insight than those with depression and without psychotic
symptoms (this same association with psychotic symptoms did not hold for
patients with mania), and that mood-congruent and mood-incongruent psychotic
symptoms did not differ in relation to contributing to insight. In another approach,
Ghaemi et al. (1997) examined insight change in patients with seasonal affective
disorder before and after light therapy, and found higher levels of insight associated
with more severe depressive ratings but no significant change in insight following
treatment. Lastly, and in yet a different vein, the study by Cassidy et al. (2001)
explored differences in insight between patients with pure manic disorders (n 42)
and those with mixed manic disorders (n 11). Using the ITAQ, they found that
patients with the mixed manic episodes showed greater insight than those with pure
manic episodes and linked this with more depressive symptoms experienced by the
former. Again, as with other variables, no definitive statements can be made con-
cerning the nature of insight in relation to affective disorders. However, the studies
do raise the issue of the relationship between depression and insight.
McEvoy et al., 1989b; Amador et al., 1993; MacPherson et al., 1996; Mutsatsa et al.,
2003) though some suggest only a weak correlation (Van Putten et al., 1976) or no
correlation (Taylor & Perkins, 1991) and even a negative relationship (Whitman &
Duffey, 1961). McEvoy et al. (1989a, b) found that schizophrenic patients with bet-
ter insight on hospital admission (ITAQ) were more compliant with treatments at
initial and early assessments but that good insight at this stage did not associate
with compliance at long-term (2–3 year) follow-up. Similar results were reported
by Cuffel et al. (1996) in their study of 89 schizophrenic patients in that better
insight (based on semi-structured interview addressing patients’ recognition of ill-
ness and need for psychiatric treatment) was associated with recent adherence to
outpatient treatment and medication but not with later use of services and adher-
ence to medication.
Studies examining the relationship between insight into mental illness and com-
pliance with offered treatments are, however, particularly difficult to interpret.
Some of the problems relate to the difficulty in evaluating treatment adherence
itself (McEvoy, 1998) but the main problem concerns the assessments of insight in
these circumstances and the consequent meaningfulness of results. Specifically, the
problem consists of the circularity that results when insight is defined, in part at
least, by acceptance of treatment (e.g. Lin et al., 1979; McEvoy et al., 1989a; David,
1990; Buchanan, 1992; Amador et al., 1993; Cuffel et al., 1996). Rating insight then
becomes tantamount to rating verbal compliance and difficulties arise in deter-
mining the individual aspects of the putative explored relationship. It is not that it
is invalid to address the question of a relationship between verbal compliance with
treatment and actual adherence to treatment for that will necessarily provide
important information in terms of understanding views and concerns of patients,
and help to plan future management. Indeed, studies have shown that there is not
a direct relationship between articulated attitudes towards treatment and actual
behavioural adherence (McEvoy et al., 1989b). The issues here, however, are two-
fold. First is the question of whether there are any theoretical grounds to consider
verbal compliance with treatment as a component of insight (Marková & Berrios,
1995a; McCabe et al., 2000). Second is the question whether it is meaningful to
treat verbal compliance qua insight as a variable against which actual treatment
adherence is assessed (David, 1990; Lambert & Baldwin, 1990). Interestingly, there
is some suggestion from the few studies where insight assessment does not, to any
great extent, incorporate attitudes to treatment, that the relationship between
insight and adherence to treatment is more complicated. For example, in the study
by Goldberg et al. (2001), better insight (assessed by the PANSS: item G12) was
associated with more positive attitudes towards medication but was not correlated
with self-reported ratings of medication compliance. And, similarly, the study by
Sanz et al. (1998) which compared insight evaluated by different scales found that
124 Historical and clinical
better insight, as assessed by ITAQ, SAI and PANSS, showed significant association
with adherence to medication, as well as compliance with attendance at mental
health centres. However, insight assessed by the IPQ (preliminary version) did not
correlate with medication adherence although it did relate to continued contact
with mental health centres.
Other occasional correlations have been sought between insight into mental dis-
order and different clinical variables. For example, Cuesta and Peralta (1994)
found no association between insight into mental disorder and the presence of
neurological soft signs. The rationale in examining this relationship was to look for
an association between neurological/cognitive dysfunction (using the soft neuro-
logical signs as proxy ‘organic’ variables) as a mechanism to ‘explain’ poor insight.
3.3 Conclusion
Over the last 15 years considerable interest has been taken in the empirical explor-
ation of insight in patients with mental illness and predominantly those with psych-
otic disorders. Whilst clinical interest in the notion of insight has been apparent
since insight was conceptualised as a clinical phenomenon, this specific research
interest seems to have been generated following the relatively recent attempts at the
operationalisation of the concept of insight. In turn, this has resulted in the devel-
opment of a number of structured measures of insight thus facilitating its quanti-
tative assessment and hence encouraging the surge of correlational studies.
In different ways, the underlying purpose of empirical studies, whether explicitly
stated or implicitly understood, has been to elucidate the nature of insight as a clin-
ical phenomenon. The primary questions have focused on three main issues. First
has been the question concerning the extent to which impairment of insight could
be considered intrinsic to the mental illness process itself. Thus, studies have exam-
ined the relationship between patients’ insight and clinical variables related to the
mental disorder, such as severity of illness, specific symptomatology, cognitive
impairment, brain dysfunction, etc. Second has been the question concerning the
extent to which impaired insight could be considered as an individual reaction to
the mental illness. In order to try to answer this, studies have examined the associ-
ation between patients’ insight and various mood disorders or reactions or specific
personality variables. Third has been the question concerning the extent to which
patients’ insight might be shaped by individual and external or environmental fac-
tors. Studies have attempted to explore this by examining the relationship between
patients’ insight and socio-demographic variables, cultural factors, past experi-
ences, educational/social knowledge, etc. Secondary questions explored by empir-
ical studies have related mainly to the clinical implication of having impairment of
insight, i.e., whether insight can be considered a prognostic factor and consequently
whether efforts should be made to help change patients’ insight.
It is evident, however, that clear or definitive answers to the above questions
are difficult to obtain. As this chapter has shown, the outcomes of empirical studies
in these areas yield, to varying extents, mixed and inconclusive results. Whilst
differences in study methodologies, e.g. patient samples (diagnostic categories,
127 Insight in clinical psychiatry: empirical studies
4.1 Introduction
Over the past 10–15 years, and paralleling the interest in the empirical examination
of insight in ‘functional’ psychiatric disorders, there has likewise been a prolifer-
ation of studies focusing on exploring patients’ insight into organic brain syndromes,
particularly, dementias (Marková & Berrios, 2000; Clare, 2004). Studies in this area
have concentrated predominantly on examining the relationship between patients’
insight and clinical variables, e.g. the severity or type of brain lesion/dementia, the
presence of affective disorder, etc. There has been, in addition, more emphasis on
developing specific measures to assess insight as well as on exploring possible neuro-
logical and neuropsychological mechanisms underlying impaired insight. As with
studies on insight in functional psychiatric disorders, outcomes have yielded
variable and inconsistent results (Marková & Berrios, 2000). Many of the problems
encountered in the empirical study of insight in functional psychiatric disorders,
such as, differences in the definitions of insight and underlying concepts, differences
in methods of assessing insight and different outcome measures employed, are likewise
evident in the studies of insight in patients with dementia and are likely to be
contributing to the variability in results. However, there are, in addition, issues
more specific to the exploration of insight in dementia and these also need to be
considered.
Firstly, the clinical status of the dementias themselves is of particular significance.
Dementias, or chronic organic brain syndromes, are conditions which, in contempor-
ary times, cross different clinical disciplines, occupying neurological, neuropsycho-
logical, psychiatric, etc., domains in clinically relevant ways. Consequently, studies
exploring insight in patients with dementias are subject to the additional influences
of the specific conceptual frameworks of insight held by these different clinical dis-
ciplines. Secondly, and relating to this first issue, the clinical features themselves of
the dementias are also likely important contributors to the mixed results obtained in
studies exploring insight. Dementias are characterised by a range of diverse symptoms
and signs as a result of organic, psychiatric, psychological and functional changes.
Problems therefore can include various specific cognitive impairments (including
128
129 Insight in organic brain syndromes: insight into neurological states
obvious impairment, the concept is much closer to the notion of a lack of conscious-
ness of a problem. In other words, it is lack of knowledge at the most basic level,
a loss of perception, which is invoked; that is, the ability to interpret apparent
changes in experienced sensory stimulation. The patient with anosognosia for
blindness cannot perceive he is blind. He is not making a correct interpretation of
his apparently disturbed sensory input. Similarly, the patient with anosognosia for
hemiplegia cannot perceive his disability, again he is not making a correct interpret-
ation of a neurologically apparent impairment of ability to move his limbs. The
concept is one of loss of perception, i.e. perception in the sense of the most primary
of knowledge involving direct interpretations of sensations. Clearly, as the concept
is extended to relate to a wider range of disabilities/neuropsychological impair-
ments, then these sensations become more complex structures incorporating internal
perceptions as well as sensations, e.g. in anosognosia for memory impairment. But
the core concept remains one of an impairment of perception or consciousness of
something. Within this framework, i.e. the inherent loss or impairment of basic
knowledge, there is not the scope for including other forms of judgements in the
way these are incorporated into the wider notion of lack of insight in relation to
psychiatric disorders.
It is important at this point to clarify another issue. Referring to the neurological
or neuropsychological conceptualisation of unawareness/loss of insight might give
the impression that there is only the one definition, only the one way of conceiving
loss of awareness in this field. In fact, that is far from the case. Here too, as in other
clinical areas, there are a multitude of definitions and models put forward in
attempts to describe and define a concept that remains complex and irreducible
except in very simplistic terms. The literature on consciousness or awareness is
extremely vast both in trying to explain normal mental and brain states as well as
pathological states. It encompasses perspectives from neurology, philosophy, psych-
ology, particularly cognitive neuropsychology, etc. and is a testament to the com-
plexity of the problem and the difficulties in trying to bring together phenomenal,
subjective qualities and neurological function/dysfunction into a common language
(Picton & Stuss, 1994). It is well beyond the scope of this chapter to review such work
and detailed and comprehensive texts can be found elsewhere (e.g. Brain, 1958;
Marcel & Bisiach, 1988; Milner & Rugg, 1992; Hameroff et al., 1996; Velmans, 1996;
Edelman, 2003). The essential point for the purposes of this chapter is that, accept-
ing the qualifications above, within the broad neurological/neuropsychological
framework, the core conception of impaired insight is that of impaired awareness or
consciousness. As such, it does not entail the secondary elaborations or judgements
that are intrinsic to the concept of insight in general psychiatry.
This narrower concept is reflected in the clinical phenomena of unawareness
that are elicited in neurological states and, as is described below, in the instruments
132 Historical and clinical
to broaden the notion and the instruments used to assess unawareness. For example,
in brain injury, attention has been paid to the different resulting deficits or disabil-
ities, e.g. behavioural problems, affective disorders, personality changes, etc. and
‘awareness’ has been examined in relation to these (Prigatano, 1991; Sherer, et al.,
1998; 2003b). Similarly, Blonder and Ranseen (1994) focused on examining
unawareness for cognitive and affective deficits rather than unawareness for hemi-
plegia in patients who had suffered strokes. Conceptualisation and evaluation of
unawareness in neurological states has therefore broadened in a number of ways
but, as is seen below, the core concept of unawareness remains narrow and rela-
tively circumscribed.
It is useful, for two main reasons, to briefly review some of the approaches assess-
ing impaired insight or unawareness in neurological states. Firstly, this helps to
illustrate more clearly the differences in conceptualisation of awareness/unawareness
between neurology/neuropsychology and general psychiatry. Secondly, the approaches
in this clinical area have been particularly influential in the methods developed for
exploring insight in patients with dementia.
1989; Allen & Ruff, 1990; Gasquoine & Gibbons, 1994; Sherer et al., 1998a). The
‘Patient Competency Rating Scale’ (Prigatano et al., 1986) evaluates patients’ aware-
ness of deficits on the basis of discrepancies between patients’ judgements of how
difficult they find tasks in certain areas (activities of daily living, cognitive func-
tioning, interpersonal functioning and emotional regulation) and the same judge-
ments made by relatives/clinicians. Ratings are scored on a Likert scale ranging
from 1 (can’t do) to 5 (can do with ease). Comparisons between patients’ judge-
ments and relatives or clinicians’ judgements determine the degree of unawareness
in patients by means of subtracting relatives/clinician scores from those derived
from patients. Similarly, Gasquoine and Gibbons (1994) report the use of Gasquoine’s
‘Self-awareness Questionnaire’ for patients with more severe head injury which also
compares patients and staff ratings in areas including awareness of: head injury,
physical impairment, communication difficulties, functional impairment and
sensory/cognitive impairment. The ‘Awareness Questionnaire’ developed by Sherer
et al. (1998a) likewise evaluates patients’ awareness of deficits on the basis of dis-
crepancies between patients’ judgements and relatives and/or clinician judgements.
However, the content of this questionnaire focuses on ratings made comparing
current and pre-injury functional abilities (cognitive area, behavioural/affective
area and motor/sensory area). Ratings are scored on a Likert scale ranging from
1 (much worse) to 5 (much better). Again, impaired awareness is evaluated by sub-
tracting scores of relatives’ or clinicians’ ratings from the patients’ self-ratings.
Similar approaches to evaluating insight have been taken in relation to patients
with dementia and will be reviewed in Chapter 5. However, what is evident from
the sorts of measures described above, is that the phenomenon of awareness or
unawareness elicited is, compared with the phenomenon elicited in general psych-
iatry, much sharper in definition and narrower in content. Patients are assumed to
either ‘know’ or ‘not know’ that they have a memory problem, or behavioural dif-
ficulty, or emotional changes, etc. Awareness is rated variously according to either
the perceived severity of the problem, or the frequency with which it is bother-
some, or the change from a previous state, or predicted ability on specific tests.
Irrespective of such ratings, the phenomenon is still focused on a unitary concept
of awareness in its narrow sense. This does not mean to say that the concept of
awareness is regarded as an all-or-none phenomenon and Schacter (1992) expli-
citly argues against such a point of view. Rather, it means that the qualitative differ-
ences in awareness are related directly and specifically to the tasks demanded of the
patients whether this is a judgement of severity, a comparison with previous func-
tion or with others, or prediction (and subsequent check) of performance on spe-
cific tests. In comparison, the conceptualisation of insight in general psychiatry has
necessitated different types of judgements on the part of the patient which have
determined a much wider, albeit less clearly defined phenomenon whose qualitative
136 Historical and clinical
the second patient was actually much lower than that of the first, suggesting that the
difference in awareness of deficits was unlikely to be due to generalised intellectual
impairment. In addition, the specificity of anosognosia for a particular deficit or
deficits, in the face of awareness of other impairments, also goes against the view
that generalised brain disease might underlie anosognosia.
More interest has thus focused on focal brain lesions as possibly underlying
anosognosia, e.g. thalamic (Roth, 1944; Redlich & Dorsey, 1945; Watson & Heilman,
1979) or striatal damage (Healton et al., 1982). Most focus, however, has been directed
at the right hemisphere, and particularly the parietal region has been implicated
(Hier et al., 1983a; Price & Mesulam, 1985; Bisiach et al., 1986; Goldberg & Barr,
1991; Rubens & Garrett, 1991; Bisiach & Geminiani, 1991; Starkstein et al., 1992;
Heilman et al., 1993). In general, though, findings have been inconclusive and
although anosognosia does seem to be more prevalent in patients with right hemi-
spheric lesions, it is also associated with left hemispheric damage (Cutting, 1978).
Experimental studies examining individual hemispheric function by inducing
temporary hemianaesthesia with intracarotid barbiturate injections have likewise
yielded mixed results. Some studies find anosognosia restricted to patients receiv-
ing right sided injections (and hence left hemiplegia) (Buchtel et al., 1992; Gilmore
et al., 1992) and others find no difference in the frequency of unawareness following
right and left sided injections (Kaplan et al., 1993; Dywan et al., 1995). Anosognosia/
unawareness in these experimental studies was elicited as a memory of the event
rather than elicited at the time of the hemiplegia developing which, as the researchers
pointed out, might influence the validity of the findings.
Numerous mechanisms subserving right hemisphere damage as the basis for
anosognosia have been suggested, including, e.g. disturbance of the body scheme
(Roth, 1944; Roth, 1949), ‘disconnection’ from the speech areas (Geschwind, 1965),
and personality disorder (Horton, 1976). However, there is little empirical evidence
provided for such mechanisms and, as others have argued, a body scheme disturbance
would not explain the unawareness manifest in relation to cognitive or behavioural
deficits or indeed to traumatic experiences (Weinstein & Kahn, 1955). Nor is there
evidence that patients are aware of deficits but are unable to express this awareness
(McGlynn & Schacter, 1989). The notion that unawareness develops as a result of
impaired position sense and sensory loss has also been refuted since researchers
found that neither somatosensory loss nor spatial neglect were sufficient to
account for anosognosia of hemiplegia in patients with right hemispheric strokes
(Bisiach et al., 1986; Levine et al., 1991; Berti et al., 1998).
Probably one of the most consistent findings has been the association between
anosognosia and frontal lobe dysfunction (McGlynn & Schacter, 1989; Goldberg &
Barr, 1991). And, much of cognitive neuropsychological work has likewise focused on
the frontal lobes as the central structures for self-monitoring and so-called executive
138 Historical and clinical
functioning (Stuss & Benson, 1986; Baddeley, 1987). An interesting model attempt-
ing to account for the different types of awareness in neurological deficits, pri-
marily related to memory, was proposed by Schacter (1990). This model, termed
DICE (dissociable interactions and conscious experience), postulated the existence of
a ‘conscious awareness system’ (CAS) which has direct links to individual ‘knowledge
modules’ such as lexical, conceptual, spatial, etc., as well as to an episodic memory
information system. Schacter suggested that whilst such modules/systems are in
constant or ongoing operation during normal mental and behavioural states, it
is only when the CAS is activated and when it interacts with such systems, that a
conscious experience of the particular information is obtained. Concentrating on
memory deficits, Schacter went on to discuss how damage at different levels in
such a system could explain both global and specific impairments of awareness. He
then put forward different levels of explanation within this model to account for
the various types of unawareness in both deficits and function (implicit memory, see
below). A first-order level of explanation, he said, would involve damage or impair-
ment within the CAS or with its individual connections. However, he favoured a
second-order level of explanation which would involve dysfunction at the level of
the knowledge modules themselves. Schacter then went on to postulate that the CAS
was a posterior system involving the inferio-parietal lobes, with connections to the
‘executive system’ situated in the frontal lobes (McGlynn & Schacter, 1989; Schacter,
1990; 1991). The model thus is an attempt to provide both a structural and func-
tional explanation of impairment in awareness and the dissociations in awareness
found in relation to different ‘modules’ or functions. In line with cognitive theory,
it assumes modularity of mental processes and hence the level of explanation is
directed at postulated individual cognitive systems and particularly at the proposed
connections between them. Models sharing similarity of approaches in terms of
integrating postulated cognitive processes and neuroanatomical structures can
be found also in Stuss and Benson (1986), Bisiach et al. (1986), Mesulam (1986),
Heilman (1991), and Prigatano (1991) amongst others. More recently, such mod-
els have been further elaborated and refined in attempts to capture the full hetero-
geneity found amongst anosognosic phenomena (e.g. Agnew & Morris, 1998).
Stuss and Benson (1986) make a conceptual distinction between self-awareness
and awareness of deficits in behavioural disorders such as neglect and aphasia. The
former is viewed as the highest psychological attribute of the frontal lobes, inter-
acting closely with organised function systems subserving various psychological
processes, e.g. attention, language and memory. Thus, damage to the frontal lobes
would result in a general disturbance of self-awareness, which, because of the varied
nature of the ‘self ’, in turn would lead to fractionation of disordered self-awareness
(Stuss, 1991). Awareness of deficits, on the other hand, is viewed as relating to the
specific functional systems themselves, such as language. Hence, impaired awareness
139 Insight in organic brain syndromes: insight into neurological states
of deficit would involve impaired knowledge associated with the specific system
and would be related to dysfunction in posterior or basal brain regions. This view is
reiterated by others (Bisiach et al., 1986; Mesulam, 1986; Prigatano, 1991). Indeed,
Bisiach et al. (1986) emphasise this point, stating that anosognosia for a specific
deficit ‘betrays a disorder at the highest levels of organisation of that function. This
implies that monitoring of the internal working is not secured in the nervous sys-
tem by a general superordinate organ, but is decentralised and apportioned to the
different functional blocks to which it refers’ (p. 480, my emphasis). Thus, whilst
sharing some similarities with Schacter’s (1990) model in terms of endowing indi-
vidual cognitive or psychological process with intrinsic ‘monitoring’ functions, we
find here, in addition, a conceptual and an anatomical separation between impaired
awareness for a specific deficit and impaired awareness of the self. Stuss’s hier-
archical model of awareness develops this further and proposes four levels of aware-
ness linked to different anatomical substrates: (i) arousal, (ii) perceptual analysis of
incoming stimuli and engagement in complex motor activity, (iii) initiation and
self-monitoring of goal-directed behaviour and, (iv) self-awareness (Picton & Stuss,
1994; Clare, 2004). Thus, the conceptualisation of awareness at the highest level, in
theoretical terms becomes, in this neurological/neuropsychological frame, a much
broader concept, distinct from anosognosia, and, closer perhaps to the theoretical
notion of insight in general psychiatry.
Empirical evidence pointing to the contribution of frontal lobe dysfunction in the
development of anosognosia has come from a variety of sources. For example, it has
been observed that patients with the amnesic syndrome as a result of frontal lobe
impairment tend to be unaware of their memory deficit whereas patients with
amnesic syndromes as a result of temporal lobe damage tend to show some aware-
ness of their memory difficulties (McGlynn & Schacter, 1989; Schacter, 1991).
Nevertheless, there have also been reports of patients with amnesic syndrome and
frontal lobe dysfunction who had preserved awareness of memory deficits (Luria,
1976; Vilkki, 1985; Schacter, 1991). The prevalence of frontal lobe damage in patients
with unawareness of deficits following head injury (Prigatano, 1991) has, on the
other hand, supported a putative aetiological role for the frontal lobes in awareness
of dysfunction. With respect to cerebrovascular accidents, Starkstein et al. (1993b)
found that patients with anosognosia for hemiplegia (n 8) were significantly
poorer on neuropsychological tasks of frontal lobe function compared with
patients without anosognosia (n 8), though there were no differences on com-
puterised tomographical (CT) scan lesions. On the other hand, neuropsychologi-
cal tests did not discriminate between patients with and without awareness of
deficits following head injury (Prigatano, 1991). However, in this instance, patients
with reduced awareness of deficits had greater incidence of frontal and parietal lesions
on magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) or CT scans. Similar work correlating
140 Historical and clinical
1990; Prigatano et al., 1997). Some studies suggest that patients with greater
awareness of their disabilities have more emotional distress or depression
(Gasquoine, 1992; Godfrey et al., 1993; Wallace & Bogner, 2000). A more consistent
finding reports patients, following traumatic brain injury, as being more aware of
their physical deficits than of their non-physical, i.e. emotional and cognitive prob-
lems (Gasquoine, 1992; Gasquoine & Gibbons, 1994; Prigatano, 1996; Sherer et al.,
1998b; Hart et al., 2004). Overall, however, there have been too few studies to
conclude very much about the relationship between awareness of disability and
characteristics of the traumatic head injury. Moreover, the studies are diverse
methodologically, employing different measures of evaluating awareness, of sever-
ity of head injury, of emotional and cognitive states, etc.
In regard to patient awareness and rehabilitation following head injury, Sherer
et al. (2003b) report that early self-awareness is associated with older age at admis-
sion to rehabilitation and with prediction of employability at discharge from inpa-
tient rehabilitation (Sherer et al., 2003b). Their study, examining 129 patients with
traumatic brain injury, used the Awareness Questionnaire (Sherer et al., 1998a).
Whilst needing replication, it highlights the need for early assessment of patients’
awareness in the prediction of various functional activities and stresses the need
for further research to determine if treatment programmes directed at impaired
awareness might help functional outcomes.
A number of interesting approaches to characterising impaired awareness have
been put forward with a view to devising treatment programmes directed at impaired
awareness following traumatic brain injury. For example, based on different time
frames, Crosson et al. (1989) proposed a nested conceptualisation of awareness dif-
ferentiating between awareness of the problem generally (intellectual awareness),
awareness of the problem when manifest (emergent awareness) and awareness of
the problem in advance (anticipatory awareness). The type of deficit in awareness
shown by the patient then determined the particular compensatory strategy that
could be employed in rehabilitation work. On the other hand, Allen and Ruff
(1990) suggested that patients’ assessment of their cognitive abilities was guided
by three processes, namely awareness (the ability to recognise problems), appraisal
(the ability to compare the current state with previous functioning) and disclosure
(the willingness to articulate or report their understanding of their state to others).
For rehabilitation purposes it would thus be important for the clinician to assess
the patient from the perspective of each of these processes.
A different approach, but sharing some similarities with the above, was taken by
Langer and Padrone (1992) who described a tripartite model for conceptualising
impaired awareness after brain injury attempting to integrate both the neurological/
neuropsychological and the motivational concepts of awareness. Thus, they identi-
fied three components of awareness, namely, information (actually having the right
144 Historical and clinical
1995) with the consequence that there is continued refining of such tests and mod-
els. Thus, in regards to implicit memory in this particular neuropsychological con-
text, the term has been defined in a specific technical sense: ‘Implicit memory is
revealed when performance on a task is facilitated in the absence of conscious rec-
ollection; explicit memory is revealed when performance on a task requires con-
scious recollection of previous experiences’ (Graf & Schacter, 1985, p. 501).
The neuropsychological tasks used to elicit implicit memory have involved primar-
ily repetition priming tests and skill-learning tasks (Schacter, 1987). Much work
has been carried out in researching implicit memory in healthy subjects but, inter-
estingly, implicit memory has also been demonstrated in patients with amnesic
syndromes, who are thus able, for example, to show effects of priming on memory
tests without recalling the priming itself (Warrington & Weiskrantz, 1968; 1974;
1982; Cermak et al., 1985; Shimamura, 1986; McAndrews et al., 1987; Schacter,
1991). In other words, dissociations between implicit and explicit memory can be
demonstrated suggesting that these may represent different aspects of memory
which may be disturbed independently. Furthermore, various impairments in
implicit memory itself and further dissociations between different types of implicit
memory tasks used (e.g. verbal/non-verbal material, words/non-words, patterns,
perceptual, auditory, etc.) have been found in patients with amnesic syndromes
indicating that dysfunction can occur at specific (task-determined) levels (Schacter,
1995). For example, it was found that while priming effects for common words and
idioms in amnesic patients is comparable to control subjects, amnesic patients
seem to fail to show priming effects for non-words (Cermak et al., 1985). Other
studies have found preserved implicit memory in amnesic patients using skill-
learning tasks. Patients were taught to learn and retain new skills such as computer
training and yet they remained ‘unaware’ of having such training or skills (Glisky
et al., 1986). Clearly, demonstration of the presence of implicit memory as well as
of different types of impaired implicit memory in patients with amnesic syndromes
(and patients with dementia) has been dependent on such very specific neuro-
psychological tasks.
The question that remains, however, concerns the structure of awareness and its
relationship to other mental structures. And how can the impairments in different
aspects of awareness be explained and understood? As far as neuropsychological
approaches are concerned, implicit memory or knowledge has tended to be addressed
predominantly from the perspective of the mental functions themselves rather
than from the perspective of an awareness or consciousness system although the
latter has been postulated in an abstract form in relation to the mental functions
(e.g. Schacter, 1990). For example, explanations for implicit memory, rather than
being directed at the awareness aspect of the concept, have focused on memory
itself in terms of how it is retrieved, the contribution of context and the possibility
147 Insight in organic brain syndromes: insight into neurological states
of multiple as opposed to single memory systems. This has led to some researchers
suggesting that the notion of implicit memory is redundant outside the specific con-
straints of neuropsychology testing (Willingham & Preuss, 1995).
Impaired insight/awareness of knowledge or function has been described also in
other neurological syndromes. Most striking perhaps is the example of ‘blindsight’,
where there is ‘visual capacity in a field defect in the absence of acknowledged
awareness’ (Weiskrantz, 1990, p. 166). The patient described by Weiskrantz had a
left hemianopia following excision of a malformation within the occipital lobe, yet,
was able to perform visual tasks in his left field at a level that was significantly
higher than chance. At the same time, he appeared unaware of his ability to per-
form at such a level, expressing surprise when informed he had ‘guessed’ correctly.
Likewise, patients with visual neglect responded to priming tasks despite overt
denial of the presence of stimuli in their neglected field, again indicating the pres-
ence of some form of unconscious or implicit appraisal (Berti & Rizzolatti, 1992).
Similarly, in prosopagnosia, where patients are unable to recognise familiar faces
overtly, implicit recognition has nevertheless been suggested by the fact that such
patients show increased autonomic responses (skin conductance responses, respir-
ation rate/depth) on testing with familiar faces (Bauer, 1984; Tranel & Damasio,
1988; Benton & Tranel, 1993).
A number of mechanisms have been proposed to explain such phenomena, includ-
ing, e.g. damage to one of two postulated separate channels (holding different
types of retinal information) involved in visual perception (Perenin & Jeannerod,
1975, 1978; Perenin et al., 1980). A different type of ‘neural disconnection’ has been
put forward by Weiskrantz (1988; 1990) who suggested that there was a split between
the capacity to perceive and an awareness or commentary on this, thus implying dam-
age to a parallel ‘monitoring’ system. Another ‘disconnection’ hypothesis, at a more
neuroanatomical level, based on damage to selective neural paths from the visual
system to the limbic systems, was proposed by Bauer (1984, p. 466) in relation to
prosopagnosia. He suggested that in prosopagnosia there is damage to the ‘ventral’
path which, following Bear (1983), is a ‘modality-specific “foveal system that recog-
nises objects [faces] by multiple attributes” and mediates modality-specific orient-
ing and stimulus-response learning’. The ‘dorsal’ path, on the other hand, which
carries emotional tone or ‘relevance’ for the face, is intact, and hence, there is the
observed autonomic arousal on presentation of familiar faces (Bauer, 1984; 1993).
As already mentioned, Schacter (1990) in relation to the amnesic syndromes, includ-
ing implicit or unconscious awareness of memory, suggested a mechanism involv-
ing impairment to the memory system itself rather than invoking damage at the
level of an awareness or monitoring system.
In these and other instances, e.g. in blindtouch (Paillard et al., 1983), the ‘object’
of awareness or insight relates to function or knowledge. Clearly, this contrasts with
148 Historical and clinical
4.4 Conclusion
The study of insight in neurological states has developed from two main perspec-
tives. First, has been the focus on patients’ apparent unawareness of major neuro-
logical disability (anosognosia). Second, has been the exploration of patients’
apparent unawareness of preserved function (implicit knowledge). In both areas of
study, unawareness has been conceptualised in a much narrower sense than lack of
awareness or insight in general psychiatry. The narrower conception of awareness
is reflected both in the types of empirical measures designed to assess awareness
clinically and in the neuroanatomical and neuropsychological models devised to
explain specific impairments in awareness.
150 Historical and clinical
Empirical studies exploring patients’ insight or awareness into dementia have been
notably prolific, particularly over the past 15 years. In contrast to the relatively con-
sistent approach taken to the study of insight in relation to neurological states,
studies examining insight in the dementias are striking in the range of different
approaches taken (Kaszniak & Christenson, 1996). As was suggested in the preced-
ing chapter, a likely explanation for the differences seen may be in part due to the
particular clinical nature of dementias themselves as well as their position in occu-
pying neurological, psychological and psychiatric professional domains. It is per-
haps not surprising that, much in the same way as research on insight in functional
psychiatric syndromes, outcomes from studies exploring patients’ insight into
dementia and clinical variables (e.g. stage of dementia, severity of dementia, level
of cognitive impairment, etc.) have been particularly mixed and inconsistent
(Marková & Berrios, 2000).
This chapter reviews the empirical studies exploring insight in dementia and
focuses on the specific conceptual issues arising from research in this area. First,
differences in definitions and underlying concepts are explored. Then, the varied
approaches taken to assess insight empirically are examined and related to the
likely clinical aspects of insight elicited. Lastly, the results of studies exploring the
relationship between patients’ insight, and various clinical and socio-demographic
variables are reviewed.
The first question relates to the meaning of insight in dementia. What is meant by
‘insight’ in dementia? Does it share similarities with the other notions of insight
discussed so far, e.g. insight in psychosis or in neurological states? Reviewing the
literature on insight in dementia, however, shows that there are some difficulties in
answering this question. These difficulties can be identified at various levels. First
of all, it is apparent that there are differences in both the terms used and concepts
involved between the various empirical studies. Secondly, there are striking vari-
ations between studies in terms of which features of dementia are the focus of
151
152 Historical and clinical
basis of clinical judgement (Aminoff et al., 1975; Gustafson & Nilsson, 1982; Neary
et al., 1986). More recently, however, attempts have focused on developing system-
atic methods of assessing insight in terms of both categorical and continuous ratings.
Broadly, such insight measures can be divided into: (i) clinician-rated assessments,
(ii) discrepancy measures and (iii) composite assessments which include a number
of different measures.
problem to be (e.g. Anderson & Tranel, 1989; McGlynn & Kaszniak, 1991a, b). As
others point out (Hermann, 1982; Sunderland et al., 1983; Larrabee et al., 1991;
Trosset & Kaszniak, 1996), the poor correspondence between what the tests are
assessing and what the patients are being asked to assess makes it difficult to attri-
bute the size of discrepancies solely to patients’ impaired awareness of cognitive
problems. Some researchers have attempted to reduce this particular problem by
devising measures that are more practically relevant to the individual (e.g. Clare
et al., 2002) and by the use of prediction and/or postdiction discrepancy methods.
In the former, specific neuropsychological tests (e.g. recall of word lists) are first
explained to the patients and then they are asked to predict how they would perform
on such tests. The discrepancies between patient predictions and actual perform-
ance are taken as a measure of patient awareness (e.g. McGlynn & Kaszniak, 1991a, b;
Green et al., 1993). In the latter, again, the tests are first explained to the patients,
but in this case the patients are asked to rate how well they have performed only
after completing the tests. The discrepancies between patient performance and their
postperformance assessments are taken as reflecting their insight into their cogni-
tive problems (Correa et al., 1996).
Within the metamemory framework, focusing on self-monitoring (rather than
awareness or insight), some studies have assessed patients’ predictions on recall
tests following practice (Moulin et al., 2000). Others have differentiated between
assessments based on patients’ predictions of recalling and those based on patients’
predictions of recognising (feeling-of-knowing) words from lists (Souchay et al.,
2002). However, the crucial point is that irrespective of the specific design of such
discrepancy methods, the phenomenon of awareness or insight elicited by the dif-
ferent methods (test performance, prediction, postdiction) will vary accordingly.
Thus, depending on the test’s demands (both in content and design), it will incorp-
orate different types of judgements into the discrepancy measure. Consequently,
the different assessments will elicit different aspects of insight. Trosset and Kaszniak
(1996) argue that discrepancy measures, based on psychometric tests, reflect not
only patients’ awareness of cognitive problems but also their judgements concern-
ing the difficulties of such unfamiliar tests. They suggest that one way to distin-
guish between these types of judgements is to consider also patients’ assessments
of their relatives’ performances on the tests as well as the relatives’ assessments of
themselves and the patients on the same tests. However, clearly all sorts of add-
itional judgements would then complicate the ensuing assessment and it might be
difficult to tease out individual aspects. Nevertheless, some studies have devised
insight measures that have included a combination of patients’ and carers’ predic-
tions (McGlynn & Kaszniak, 1991a, b), and postdictions of own and the others’
functioning as well as predictions and postdictions of the performance of an unfamil-
iar person (videotaped interview) on memory tests (Duke et al., 2002).
164 Historical and clinical
explicit division there. Furthermore, there is in addition a third position held in gen-
eral psychiatry, namely that of insight conceived as an independent phenomenon
or process, in the sense of being independent of both the disorder itself and of the
psychology or reactivity of the individual. In dementia studies, the polarity between
unawareness as intrinsic to the disease process and unawareness as a psychological
denial seems to have been driven to a considerable extent by the work on anosog-
nosia in non-progressive organic brain disorders (see previous chapter). Focus on
insight in empirical studies has thus been aimed predominantly at two issues.
Firstly, researchers have focused on developing understanding of the dementia
process itself. In other words, studies attempt to relate insight with disease severity
and to explore changes in insight in relation to different dementias or brain/neuro-
psychological dysfunction. Secondly, researchers have sought to examine the
changes and reactions of the person with dementia. In other words, studies explore
the relationship between insight and various moods and behavioural changes, such as
depression/anxiety, etc. From a slightly different perspective, interest in the explo-
ration of insight in dementia has also been generated from a wider consideration of
the patient and family affected by the disease and its consequences. Hence, studies
have attempted to consider the rehabilitation potential of insight (mirroring work
on insight in relation to traumatic brain injury), its prognostic value and the
effects of impaired insight on the family/carers looking after the patient.
It is perhaps not surprising that, in general, results of empirical studies explor-
ing the relationship between insight, clinical and socio-demographic variables are
as inconclusive in relation to dementias as they are in relation to functional psy-
chiatric syndromes. Once again it is likely that the differences identified in the way
insight is defined and conceptualised, the variable ways in which it is assessed, the
range of ‘objects’ of insight involved as well as the fact that different outcome meas-
ures are used will all contribute to the mixed and inconsistent results. This makes
it difficult to answer in a definite way some of the questions posed concerning the
nature of insight as a clinical phenomenon and its relationship to both the indi-
vidual and to the disease process.
Giovannetti et al., 2002). There are a few exceptions. For example, Sevush and Leve
(1993), whilst finding no association between denial and age of onset of Alzheimer’s
disease, years of education or duration of illness, found, nevertheless, a significant
correlation with gender, females showing more denial (less insight) than males. On
the other hand, Migliorelli et al. (1995) reported in their study that males showed
significantly more anosognosia (less insight) than females. Similarly, whilst most
studies find no association between insight and the age of the patient, a few stud-
ies report a negative correlation between insight and age, i.e. the greater the age, the
lower the patient’s awareness (Verhey et al., 1993; Weinstein et al., 1994; Derouesné
et al., 1999). And, likewise, duration of illness has not been found to correlate with
insight in most studies but a few have reported a negative correlation, i.e. less
insight associated with longer duration of illness (Migliorelli et al., 1995; Starkstein
et al., 1996; 1997a).
Given the few significant correlations between insight and socio-demographic
variables, in the face of mostly non-significant findings, it is difficult to interpret
very much. As is seen from Table 5.1, the studies vary in their methodologies, par-
ticularly, in their measures of insight and it is likely that different aspects of insight
are elicited which, in turn, is likely to affect the correlation sought. Moreover, vari-
ables such as duration of dementia can be very difficult to ascertain given the lack
of detailed understanding around the disease process.
Caine & Shoulson, 1983; Danielczyk, 1983). Caine et al. (1978) commented on
patients with Huntington’s disease showing not only insight into their cognitive
problems but also into changes of temperament or disposition, and into difficul-
ties in controlling their affect. However, most of these studies have not used any
structured assessments of insight nor provided defined criteria for establishing the
presence or absence or partial presence of insight.
Some studies using structured insight assessments (albeit of different kinds)
have explored differences in insight between patients with Alzheimer’s disease and
vascular dementias. One of the issues to consider here is the validity of using the
Hachinski criteria (Hachinski et al., 1975) to distinguish between Alzheimer’s dis-
ease and vascular or multi-infarct dementia which has been subject to some criti-
cism (e.g. Dening & Berrios, 1992). Interestingly, studies have shown opposing
results. Thus, some researchers have found no difference in the insight shown
between patients with Alzheimer’s disease and those with vascular dementias
(Verhey et al., 1993; 1995; Zanetti et al., 1999; Giovannetti et al., 2002). However,
other studies report a significant difference in insight between the groups, with
Alzheimer’s disease patients showing greater impairment of insight than patients
with vascular disease (De Bettignies et al., 1990; Wagner et al., 1997). Again, little
can be concluded at this stage and the differences in methodologies of the studies
are described in Table 5.1. More systematic work is needed to be able to address the
question of differences in patients’ insight in different dementias and such work
continues to be additionally problematic in the face of practical difficulties around
determining onset/stage of disease and its severity.
168
Main results
‘Object’ of Insight
Study Patients insight assessment Outcome variables Dementia /behavioural Other
169
between patient abilities
prediction and
performance on
cognitive tests
McGlynn and HD: 8 Memory As above and MMSE Poor insight – Poor insight with
Kaszniak (1991b) problems discrepancy Neuropsychology associated with questionnaire
Motor between patient tests: 10, 19, 22 more severe discrepancy
problems prediction and Motor tasks: a–e dementia Better insight on
performance on prediction tests
motor tests
Mangone et al. AD: 41 Physical self- Discrepancy MMSE, GDS, Poor insight Poor insight –
(1991) maintaining between patient BDRS, BPRS associated with more frequent
activities and carer on Neuropsychology more severe in patients
Activities of questionnaire tests: 9, 23–30 dementia with paranoid
Daily Living Best predictors delusions
(ADL) of poor insight:
GDS, BPRS,
tests: 23, 27
Main results
‘Object’ of Insight
Study Patients insight assessment Outcome variables Dementia /behavioural Other
Ott and Fogel AD: 37 1. Reason for Clinician rating MMSE, CDRS Poor insight Mixed association –
(1992) VD and clinic visit on scale in the HDRS, COR, associated with between insight
others: 13 2. Memory four areas based GerDS more severe and depression,
problems on information dementia depending on
3. ADL from patient depression scale
4. Progress and carer (see text)
of deficits
Green et al. (1993) AD: 20 1. Remote 1. Discrepancy Neuropsychology No association – Least insight into
memory between patient tests: 2, 35 between insight recent memory
2. Recent and carer on DRS and severity and ADL.
memory questionnaire of dementia No correlation
3. Attention 2. Discrepancy between the two
4. Daily between patient insight measures
activities prediction and
performance on
cognitive test
Reed et al. (1993) AD: 57 Memory Clinician rated MMSE, DSM-III No association No association Poor insight
problems from case notes. (for depression) between insight between insight associated with
Scale identified Neuropsychology and severity and depression reduced perfusion
four categories tests: 35–38 of dementia. in right
SPECT (n 20) Poor insight dorsolateral
associated with frontal areas
poor recognition
memory
Sevush and Leve AD: 128 Memory Clinician-rated ACAD Poor insight Poor insight –
171
(1993) problems structured Three-item scale associated with associated with
interview: three for depression more severe less depression
categories cognitive deficits
Verhey et al. AD: 103 Cognitive Clinician- GDS Poor insight No correlation –
(1993) VD: 43 deficits rated structured DSM-III-R associated with between insight
Others: 24 interview of (for depression), more severe and depression.
patient and carer HDRS dementia Correlation
between poor
insight and less
psychic anxiety
(HDRS)
Auchus et al. AD: 28 Cognitive Clinician rating DRS No association – –
(1994) deficits from case notes Neuropsychology between insight
tests: 2, 9, 27, and severity of
36–39 dementia.
Correlation
between poor
insight and poor
visuo-constructive
skills (38, 39)
Feher et al. (1994) AD: 83 Memory Self-report HDRS Poor insight Poor insight
AAMI: 200 problems of memory Neuropsychology associated with associated with
Conrols: 64 problems on tests: 4, 9, 10 more severe less depression
questionnaire dementia
Kiyak et al. (1994) AD: 40 1. Functional Discrepancy DRS Insight worse – Longitudinal
Control: 53 health between patient over time, in asso- study: partial
Follow-up 2. General and carer on ciation with decline preservation of
study health questionnaire of cognition insight over time
Table 5.1 (cont.)
172
Main results
‘Object’ of Insight
Study Patients insight assessment Outcome variables Dementia /behavioural Other
Lopez et al. (1994) AD: 181 Cognitive Clinician rating Structured Poor insight No difference –
deficits from case notes interview; associated with in depression,
DSM-III-R. more severe delusions or
Neuropsychology dementia. hallucinations
tests: 3, 5, 25, Poor insight between patients
31, 36, 40–45 associated with with and
poor frontal tests without insight
Michon et al. AD: 24 Memory Discrepancy MMSE, MADRS No correlation No correlation –
(1994) problems between patient Neuropsychology between insight between insight
and carer on tests: 22, 31, 32, and severity and and depression
questionnaire 36, 38 most of tests.
Behavioural Significant
observations correlation
(Luria) between poor
insight and poor
‘frontal’ tests
Weinstein et al. AD: 41 1. Memory Clinician-rated MMSE No correlation Poor insight Poor insight more
(1994) Followed up problems structured Neuropsychology between insight associated with often when AD
also after 2. ADL interview: three tests: 39, 46, 47 and severity or confabulation, presented initially
2–3 years categories history. with any of tests delusions, with memory
Premorbid misidentification, or behavioural
personality rating symbolic changes
disorientation
Dalla Barba et al. AD: 12 Memory Discrepancy MMSE, BDRS, No correlation Depressed –
(1995) DD: 12 problems between patient MADRS between insight patients had less
Controls: 24 rating of memory Neuropsychology and ‘frontal’ tests insight into
and performance tests: 22, 48–50 Poor insight memory, and
173
on memory tasks Occurrence of correlated with overestimated
‘intrusions’ more intrusions memory more
than AD, but
not statistically
significant
Kotler-Cope and AD: 13 nine objects – Discrepancy RBMT No correlation – Better insight for
Camp (1995) including between patient between insight and behavioural
cognitive, mood and carer on and severity problems than
and behaviour questionnaire of dementia for cognitive.
McDaniel et al. AD: 670 Cognitive Clinician-rated MMSE, CDRS Poor insight – Reduction of
(1995) After deficits direct question- BDRS correlated with insight over time
follow-up: ing: three BDRS-short more severe correlated with
1 year: 406 categories dementia greater severity
2 years: 148
Migliorelli et al. AD: 73 1. Cognitive Discrepancy MMSE, CDRS Poor insight Poor insight –
(1995) deficits between patient HDRS, HAS correlated with associated with
2. Personality and carer on FIM, STC, more severe more mania,
and interests questionnaire BMS, PLACS cognitive and pathological
(AQ-D): cut-off Neuropsychology ADL deficits laughing and
point for those tests: 4, 19, 32, No correlation less dysthymia
with and without 36–38, 43, 51–54 with specific tests and anxiety.
insight No correlation
with major
depression
Seltzer et al. AD: 226 Memory Clinician-rated MMSE, CDRS Poor insight Patients with –
(1995a) problems set questions: BDRS: BMIC associated with insight had
two categories and BPEA later stage and significantly more
(with and without interview more severe depressed mood
insight) dementia (not disorder)
174
Table 5.1 (cont.)
Main results
‘Object’ of Insight
Study Patients insight assessment Outcome variables Dementia /behavioural Other
Seltzer et al. AD: 36 Memory Discrepancy MMSE Poor insight Poor insight –
(1995b) problems between patient COR correlated with associated with
and carer on Three 5-point more severe less depression
questionnaire Likert scales to dementia and more carer-
(EMQ) assess mood rated irritability
Starkstein et al. AD: 24 1. Cognitive Discrepancy MMSE, HDRS, No difference No difference Patients with no
(1995a) deficits between patient FIM, STC in severity or in depression, insight had
2. Personality and carer on Neuropsychology test scores ADL and social reduced cerebral
and interests questionnaire tests: 4, 19, 32, between patients ties between blood flow in
(AQ-D) 36–38, 51–54 with and without patients with and right hemisphere
SPECT insight without insight
Vasterling et al. AD: 43 Memory, Discrepancy MMSE, CDRS Poor insight – Least insight in
(1995) general between patient associated with self-care and
health, self- and carer on later stage and memory.
care, mood questionnaire more severe Best insight in
(EMQ, GQ) dementia depression and
general health
Verhey et al. AD: 48 Cognitive Clinician-rated GDS, BDRS Poor insight – No difference
(1995) VD: 48 deficits structured DSM-III-R associated with in insight or
interview of (for depression) more severe depression
patient and carer HDRS dementia between AD
and VD
175
Correa et al. AD: 20 Memory 1. Discrepancy MMSE Poor insight – AD showed poorer
(1996) MII: 18 problems between patient Neuropsychology associated with insight into
Controls: 18 and carer on tests: 3, 4, 22, 55 more severe memory problems
questionnaire dementia compared with
2. Discrepancy memory impaired
between post- older adults
diction and
performance on
cognitive tests
3. Number of
intrusions and
self-corrections
Deckel and HD: 19 Cognitive Discrepancy Neuropsychology Poor insight – HD had less
Morrison (1996) Controls: 14 and motor between patient tests: 2, 5, 31, 32, associated with insight than
(Neuro- problems and and staff ratings 37, 43, 56 more impairments neurological
impaired) emotions on questionnaire on tests controls
Ott et al. (1996a) AD: 26 1. Reason for 1. Clinician rated MMSE Poor insight No association AD had less
Controls: 16 clinic visit (Ott & Fogel, COR associated with between insight insight into
2. Memory 1982, above) Neuropsychology poor performance and depression memory and
problems 2. Discrepancy tests: 19, 36, 37, on executive and ADL than
3. ADL between patient 39, 43, 57–59 visuo-spatial tests elderly controls
4. Progress and carer on
of deficits questionnaire
for memory
and ADL
Ott et al. (1996b) AD: 40 1. Reason for Clinician rated MMSE Poor insight Poor insight Patients with
clinic visit as above (Ott & IADL, PSMS, correlated with correlated with poor insight had
Table 5.1 (cont.)
176
Main results
‘Object’ of Insight
Study Patients insight assessment Outcome variables Dementia /behavioural Other
2. Memory Fogel, 1982) DBDS worse ADL more apathy lower perfusion
problems SPECT Small correlation in right temporo-
3. ADL between poor occipital cortex
4. Progress insight and
of deficits severity
Starkstein et al. AD: 170 1. Cognitive Discrepancy MMSE, HDRS, Poor cognitive Poor insight (cog) Factor analysis
(1996) deficits between patient HAS, AS, IS, (but not correlated with yielded two
2. Personality and carer on BMS, PLACS, behavioural) more delusions, factors: cognitive
and interests questionnaire DPS, FIM insight correlated apathy and less insight and
(AQ-D) interview with more severe depression. behavioural
Neuropsychology deficit on NP tests Poor insight insight
tests: 19, 32, 37, (beh) correlated
38, 51, 53, 54, 60 with mania and
pathological
laughing
Seltzer et al. AD: 40 Memory, Discrepancy MMSE, CDRS Poor insight in – Greater carer
(1997) self-care and between patient BIZ social and self- burden associated
social function and carer on care (not memory) with poorer
questionnaire function associated insight (into
(EMQ, PCRS) with more severe memory – not
dementia into self-care)
Starkstein et al. AD: 62 1. cognitive Discrepancy MMSE, HDRS, Insight gets worse Insight associated –
(1997a) Follow-up deficits between patient interview with progression with dysthymia
study 2. personality and carer on DSM-III-R of dementia but not with
and interests questionnaire (SCID), HAS major depression
(AQ-D) FIM, DPS, (poor insight with
BMS, OAS less depression)
177
Starkstein et al. AD: 55 1. Cognitive Discrepancy MMSE Poor insight asso- – –
(1997b) deficits between patient interview ciated only with
2. Personality and carer on Neuropsychology poor set shifting
and interests questionnaire tests: 4, 19, 36–38, and procedural
(AQ-D) 43, 52–55, 61 learning
Vasterling et al. AD: 28 Memory, Discrepancy MMSE Insight decrease – Insight falls in
(1997) Follow-up general between patient not correlate relation to all
study health, self- and carer on with progress of ‘objects’ over
care, mood questionnaire dementia time, no difference
(EMQ, GQ) in size
Cotrell and AD: 35 1. Remote Discrepancy MMSE, CDRS Poor insight – Only poor insight
Wild (1999) memory between patient ADL, IADL correlated with into attention
2. Recent and carer on 15-item more severe predicted patients
memory questionnaire questionnaire (MMSE) who no longer
3. Attention (Green et al., on driving dementia drove
4. Daily 1993, above)
activities
Derouesné et al. AD: 88 After Cognitive 1. Discrepancy MMSE, ADL Poor insight Poor insight Poor insight
(1999) follow-up deficits between patient ZD, ZA, PBQ correlated with correlated correlated with
of 21 and carer on Neuropsychology worse MMSE at mainly with lower perfusion
months: 52 questionnaire tests: 22, 31, 54, first visit but more apathy in frontal
Table 5.1 (cont.)
178
Main results
‘Object’ of Insight
Study Patients insight assessment Outcome variables Dementia /behavioural Other
2. Clinician rated 60, 66 not at follow-up. and with less cerebral regions
3. Carers’ ratings Frontal behaviours Correlation with anxiety.
SPECT ADL at both visits. No correlation
No correlation with depression.
with tests
Sevush (1999) AD: 203 Memory Patient-rated MMSE A small correlation – Greater correlation
Controls: 40 problems questionnaire ACAD between between poor
After (AMIS) poor insight insight and
follow-up of Also ratings by and severity at severity when
15 months: clinician and first visit but using clinician
AD: 106 discrepancy no correlation or discrepancy
measures used with progress measures
to compare of disease
Zanetti et al. AD: 37 Memory 1. Clinician-rated MMSE, CDRS, Poor insight No correlation No difference in
(1999) VD: 32 problems and interview (Verhey ADL, IADL correlated with between insight insight between
objects from et al.,1993, above) GerDS, NPI more severe and depression AD and VD
Ott and Fogel 2. Clinician-rated Neuropsychology dementia and
(1982, above) questions (Ott & tests (n 36): 5, 9, cognitive
Fogel, 1982, above) 19, 22, 32, 36, 54, 67 impairment but
complex (see text)
Harwood et al. AD: 91 Cognitive and Clinician rated: MMSE, NRS Poor insight Poor insight –
(2000) functional Item 12 BDRS-short associated with associated with
deficits (inaccurate more severe less depression but
insight item) dementia more agitation
from NRS No correlation
with psychosis
Smith C.A. et al. AD: 23 Cognitive, Discrepancy MMSE, GerDS No correlation Poor insight After controlling
179
(2000) Controls: 30 motor and between patient Neuropsychology between insight associated with for depression,
affective and carer on tests: 8,19, 37, 38, and severity, less depression poor insight
problems questionnaire 43, 57, 68, 69 except after correlated with
controlling for severity and with
depression poor frontal tests
(see text) performance
Gil et al. (2001) AD: 45 Identity, Clinician-rated MMSE Poor insight – Different ‘objects’
cognition, questionnaire Neuropsychology correlated with of insight affected
affect, body, answered by tests: 70 more severe to different extents
prospective patients (SCQ) dementia Body and identity
memory, No correlation least affected
introspection, with frontal tests
moral
judgements
Koltai et al. (2001) D: 22 Cognitive Clinician rated: MMSE, GerDS, Patients with – Relatives perceived
Randomised deficits two categories GerDS-rel., EMQ, insight made greater gains with
controlled (with and EMQ-rel. greater gains in MCP independent
trial with without insight) Neuropsychology memory with of insight
Memory and tests: 36, 57, 58 MCP than
Coping those without
Programme
(MCP)
Duke et al. (2002) AD: 24 Cognitive Discrepancy MMSE, DRS Poor insight – Patients and
deficits between: Neuropsychology correlated with carers both
1. Patient and tests: 71 more severe overestimated
carer on (PCRS) dementia performance of
questionnaire fictional patient
Table 5.1 (cont.)
180
Main results
‘Object’ of Insight
Study Patients insight assessment Outcome variables Dementia /behavioural Other
181
questionnaire BIZ dementia carer burden, but
(Green et al., disinhibition
1993, above) contributed more
Howorth and AD: 18 Cognitive 1. Clinician BDRS No correlation – Poor correlation
Saper (2003) VD: 8 deficits, ADL, rated (Verhey between insight between measures
LBD: 2 general: et al., 1993, above) and severity of insight
MD: 4 sense of self, 2. Discrepancy of dementia. (see text)
behaviours between patient Only insight
and carer on assessed by
IADL and PSMS prediction
3. Discrepancy in correlated with
patient rating cognitive test
and prediction performance
on memory tests
4. Interview with
patient and carer
Vogel et al. (2005) AD: 36 Memory 1. Discrepancy MMSE, CDRS, FBI, Correlation Performance on No difference in
MCI: 30 problems between patient Neuropsychology between insight FBI (behavioural insight between
Controls: 33 and carer on tests: 22, 32, 36, and dementia changes AD and MCI.
questionnaire 43, 55, 75–78, severity (MMSE). associated with Poor insight,
(Michon et al. SPECT No correlation lesions in but only on
1994) between insight prefrontal cortex) discrepancy
2. Clinician-rated and executive correlated with measure correlated
categorical 4-point function insight but only with reduced rCBF
scale (Reed et al., on discrepancy in right inferior
1993) measure frontal gyrus
Abbreviations:
Patients: AAMI: Age-Associated Memory Impairment; AD: Alzheimer’s disease; Dep.: Depressive Disorder; HD: Huntington’s Disease; HT: Head Trauma;
CVA: cerebral infarction subjects; D: Dementia (aetiology not specified); LBD: Lewy Body Dementia; MCI: Mild Cognitive Impairment; MD: Dementias of
Notes to Table 5.1 (cont.)
182
Multiple aetiologies; MID: Multi-Infarct Dementia; MII: Memory-Impaired Individuals (not meeting criteria for AD); PaD: Parkinson’s Disease; VD:
Vascular Dementia.
Scales/Measures: ACAD: Assessment of Cognitive Abilities in Dementia; AMIS: Awareness of Memory Impairment Scale; AQ-D: Anosognosia Questionnaire-
Dementia; AS: Apathy Scale; BDRS: Blessed Dementia Rating Scale; BIZ: Burden Interview (of Zarit et al.); BMIC: Memory–Information–Concentration com-
ponent of the BDRS; BMS: Bech Mania Scale; BPEA: Performance of Everyday Activities component of the BDRS; BPRS: Behavioural Pathology Rating
Scale; CDRS: Clinical Dementia Rating Scale; COR: Cornell Scale for Depression; DBDS: Dementia Behaviour Disturbance Scale; DPS: Dementia Psychosis
Scale; DRS: Dementia Rating Scale; EMQ: Everyday Memory Questionnaire; FBI: Frontal Behavioural Inventory; FIM: Functional Independence Measure;
FrSBe: Frontal Systems Behaviour Scale; GDS: Global Deterioration Scale; GerDS (-rel): Geriatric Depression Scale (-relatives version); GQ: General
Historical and clinical
Questionnaire; HAS: Hamilton Anxiety Scale; HDRS: Hamilton Depression Rating Scale; IADL: Instrumental Activities of Daily Living Scale; IS: Irritability
Scale; MADRS: Montgomery and Asberg Depression Rating Scale; MLAT-S: Multi-Level Action Test – Short form; MMSE: Mini-Mental State Examination;
NPI: Neuropsychiatry Inventory Scale; NRS: Neurobehavioural Rating Scale; OAS: Overt Aggression Scale; PBQ: Psychobehavioural Questionnaire; PCRS:
Patient Competency Rating Scale; PLACS: Pathological Laughing And Crying Scale; PSMS: Physical Self Maintenance Scale; RBMT: Rivermead Behavioural
Memory Test; SCQ: Self-Consciousness Questionnaire; STC: Social Ties Checklist; ZA: Zung Anxiety Scale; ZD: Zung Depression Scale.
Neuropsychology tests: 1: Benton Orientation Questionnaire; 2: Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale – Revised; 3: Rey Auditory–Verbal Learning Test; 4: Benton
Visual Retention Test; 5: Rey–Osterrieth Complex Figure Recall Test; 6: Multilingual Aphasia Examination; 7: Test of Facial Recognition; 8: Judgement of
Line Orientation; 9: Logical Memory from Wechsler Memory Scale (WMS); 10: Paired Associates from Wechsler Memory Scale; 11: Word Recall – immediate;
12. Word Recall – delayed; 13: Word Recognition – immediate; 14: Word Recognition – delayed; 15: Picture Recall – immediate; 16: Picture Recall – delayed;
17: Picture Recognition – immediate; 18: Picture Recognition – delayed; 19: Digit Span; 20: Verbal Span; 21: Spatial Span; 22: Verbal Fluency; 23: Continuous
Performance Test; 24: Alternating Sequence Test; 25: Go–No-Go Paradigm; 26: Alzheimer’s Disease Assessment Scale – ideomotor, ideational and construc-
tional praxis tests; 27: Visual Reproduction; 28: Right–Left Differentiation Test; 29: Spatial Relationships Test; 30: Word List Generation; 31: WMS;
32: Wisconsin Card Sorting Test; 33: Graphic Series; 34: Frontal Behaviours; 35: California Verbal Learning Test; 36: Boston Naming Test; 37: Controlled Oral
Word Association Test; 38: Block Design; 39: Clock Drawing; 40: Visual Form Discrimination and Face Recognition; 41: Simple Drawings; 42: 3-D Block
Design; 43: Trail Making Tests (A and/or B); 44: Simple Reaction Time; 45: Letter Cancellation; 46: Face–Hand Test; 47: Short Story Recall; 48: Modified
Card Sorting Test; 49: Sequencing Test; 50: Cognitive Estimates Test; 51: Buschke Selective Reminding Test; 52: Apraxia Subtest of Western Aphasia
Battery; 53: Token Test; 54: Raven’s Progressive Matrices; 55: Buschke Cued Recall Procedure; 56: Finger Tapping Test; 57: CERAD Word List Learning Test;
58: CERAD Constructional Praxis; 59: Mazes; 60: Similarities; 61: Maze Test; 62: CERAD Word List Recognition; 63: CERAD Verbal Fluency Test;
64: Vocabulary; 65: Information and Orientation from WMS; 66: Boston Diagnostic Aphasia Examination; 67: Corsi’s Block Tapping Test; 68: Orientation–Memory
Concentration; 69: Visual Span; 70: Frontal Assessment Short Test; 71: Hopkins Verbal Learning Test; 72: Boston Revision of WMS; 73: Goldberg Graphical
Sequences Test; 74: Semantic Probe Test; 75: Danish Mental Status Test; 76: Danish Adult Reading Test; 77: Stroop Test; 78: Design Fluency.
183 Insight in organic brain syndromes: insight into dementia
Howorth & Saper, 2003). One study found a significant correlation between poor
insight and severity of dementia only after controlling for depression (Smith C.A.
et al., 2000).
Given the vast amount of research carried out in this area (see Table 5.1), it is
worthwhile considering some of the factors that are likely to be contributing to the
continued lack of consistency in results. Most obvious of course is the employment of
different insight measures in the studies. As detailed above and indicated in Table 5.1,
such differences relate to how insight is assessed, who does the rating, how the rating
is expressed (dichotomies or categories or continuous ratings), the level of structure
and detail applied to the assessment as well as differences in the ‘object’ of insight, i.e.,
the aspect of the patient’s illness addressed by the insight measure. Clearly, the range
and types of differences that are involved would suggest that measures elicit somewhat
different aspects of insight and that this may make a difference to the results of corre-
lational studies. It is interesting that when studies employ a combination of different
measures of insight, results vary according to the measure of insight used. For exam-
ple, Sevush (1999) found only a small association between poor insight and more
severe dementia when using a patient-rated questionnaire but the same study found a
stronger correlation when using a patient-carer discrepancy questionnaire or when
using a clinician-rated measure. Similarly (but with contrasting results), Howorth and
Saper (2003) found no correlation between insight and severity of dementia when
using a clinician-rated measure and a patient-carer discrepancy questionnaire.
However, they found a correlation between insight and severity when using a discrep-
ancy method based on the patient’s prediction of cognitive test results.
When studies distinguish between various ‘objects’ of insight in their analyses,
then different correlations have obtained again. For example, Starkstein et al.
(1996) found that only poor insight into cognitive problems correlated with more
severe dementia, whereas there was no such association between insight into per-
sonality changes/interests and severity of dementia. Interestingly, the opposite result
was reported by Seltzer et al. (1997). They found that whereas there was no cor-
relation between insight into memory problems and severity of dementia, there
was a significant correlation between poor insight into social function, self-care
and dementia severity. It seems therefore that many aspects around the insight
measures are likely to be important contributors to the type of insight elicited and
hence determine the correlations obtained.
Apart from different insight assessment measures used in the various studies,
there are other likely factors contributing to the variability in results. Of particular
note is the complicated issue concerning the assessment of the severity and/or
stage of dementia. One of the most frequent measures used by studies to assess the
severity of dementia is the Mini-Mental State Examination (MMSE) (Folstein et al.,
1975). Whilst clearly this is a useful screening measure of global cognitive function
184 Historical and clinical
domain. Other studies report mixed results suggesting that patients show partial
preservation of insight over time (Kiyak et al., 1994; Derouesné et al., 1999). For
example, in the study by Derouesné et al. (1999), a correlation was found between
poor insight and more severe dementia as assessed by MMSE at baseline but not at the
follow-up assessment 21 months later. On the other hand, patients did show a corre-
lation between worse insight and more severe dementia at both time points when
severity was assessed by ADL rather than cognitive deterioration. Several studies
report that some patients seem to maintain their level of insight over time (Kiyak,
et al., 1994; Weinstein et al., 1994) or even show increased insight over time (McDaniel
et al., 1995). Clearly the mixed results and the too few longitudinal studies make it
difficult to conclude much about the relationship between patients’ insight and
disease progression. The same problems concerning different measures of insight in
various studies apply also to interpretation of results. Likewise, the practical difficul-
ties of measuring severity/stage of dementia and its longitudinal changes in a sensitive
way are the significant problems in research of this kind (Vasterling et al., 1997).
that patients with greater insight into their condition would show more depressive
symptomatology whereas patients without insight would show little in the way of
affective change. Studies exploring the relationship between patients’ insight into
their dementia and levels of depression once again yield variable results (see Table
5.1). Many of the studies find no association between patients’ insight and depres-
sion (De Bettignies et al., 1990; Reed et al., 1993; Verhey et al., 1993; Lopez et al.,
1994; Michon et al., 1994; Cummings et al., 1995; Starkstein et al., 1995a; Ott et al.,
1996a; Derouesné et al., 1999; Zanetti et al., 1999; Giovannetti et al., 2002). However,
in contrast, several studies do report a significant correlation between patients’
insight and depression, with greater insight being associated with more depression
(Sevush & Leve, 1993; Feher et al., 1994; Seltzer et al., 1995a,b; Harwood et al.,
2000; Smith C.A. et al., 2000). In addition, other studies present mixed results
reporting either weak correlations between insight and depression (Feher et al., 1991)
or correlations that are specific in particular ways. Thus, the study by Starkstein et al.
(1996) only found correlations between insight into cognitive problems and depres-
sion, whereas no such correlation was obtained between insight into behavioural
and personality changes, and depression. Other studies have specified the type of
depressive symptomatology correlating with insight. Migliorelli et al. (1995) and
Starkstein et al. (1997a) did not find a correlation between patients’ insight and the
presence of major depression (DSM-III-R) but they did obtain a correlation between
patients’ insight and the presence of dysthymia. Similarly, Seltzer et al. (1995a)
reported a correlation between patients’ insight and depressed mood but not with
a depressive disorder.
Exploring the relationship between patients’ insight into dementia and depres-
sion is, however, complicated by additional problems which make interpretation of
results particularly difficult and which are also likely to contribute to the variable
outcomes outlined above (Table 5.1). Firstly, the question of the nature of depres-
sion in patients with dementia needs to be considered. The hypothesis that greater
insight is associated with more depression in patients with dementia is based on
the assumption (amongst others) that the depression in these patients is ‘reactive’
in nature, i.e. a consequence of the experienced disabilities resulting from having
dementia. Thus, empirical findings of an association between levels of insight and
depression could be interpreted as supporting the notion that impairment of
insight was the result of psychological denial on the part of the patient. It might be
argued that patients, unable to face the knowledge of having such a terrible condi-
tion, could deny (by means of various psychological processes) this knowledge. In
turn, this lack of knowledge would prevent patients from experiencing the distress
(and hence depression) that this knowledge would entail. The problem is, however,
that there is little evidence to suggest that depression in patients with dementia is
solely a reactive process. Most research indicates that depression, either as a disorder
188 Historical and clinical
finding that the latter was valid in mild to moderate dementia only. Nevertheless,
like Burns et al. (1990), they found that patients with worse memory complained
of more depressive symptoms. Most studies however report that patients complain
less of depressive symptoms as their dementia progresses (Reifler et al., 1982;
Mackenzie et al., 1989; Ballard et al., 1991). Thirdly, there is also the issue concerning
different contents included within various depression measures. Harwood et al.
(2000), e.g., suggested that one of the reasons for inconsistent results was that the
studies using measures which contained a significant focus on somatic or neu-
rovegetative symptoms as inherent to depression (e.g. COR, HDRS, DSM-III-R
diagnoses) reported negative findings, whereas studies using measures which
included more subjective expressions of depression such as sad mood reported
positive correlations between insight and depression. However, it is likely that there
are additional factors involved for, as Table 5.1 shows, studies which have used
measures including somatic items have also reported positive correlations (Feher
et al., 1994; Seltzer et al., 1995b) and similarly, studies using more subjective meas-
ures have reported no correlations (Derouesné et al., 1999; Zanetti et al., 1999;
Giovannetti et al., 2002).
Given such variable results, as well as the complicated issues around the nature
and assessment of depression in patients with dementia, some researchers suggest
that, rather than searching for associations between patients’ insight and a depres-
sive disorder, it makes more sense to explore the relationship between patients’
insight and depressive/anxious symptoms since these may be more representative of
reactive states. As Table 5.1 shows, studies by Migliorelli et al. (1995) and Starkstein
et al. (1997a) found that whilst patients’ insight did not correlate with major
depression, it did seem to correlate with dysthymia. Seltzer et al. (1995a,b) likewise
found that whilst insight did not correlate with depressive disorder, it correlated
with depressive mood. Several studies suggested that patients’ insight was associ-
ated with more anxiety (Verhey et al., 1993; Migliorelli et al., 1995; Derouesné et al.,
1999) and one study found an association between patients’ insight and feelings of
hopelessness (Harwood & Sultzer, 2002). Other studies have found no correlation
between patients’ insight and anxiety (Seltzer et al., 1995b). There are too few stud-
ies in this area, however, to draw firm conclusions.
Similarly, studies exploring other psychiatric and behavioural phenomena in
relation to patients’ insight in dementia have been few in number and again yield
mixed results (Table 5.1). One of the more consistent results reported by a few stud-
ies is of a correlation between poor insight and greater apathy (Ott et al., 1996b;
Starkstein et al., 1996; Derouesné et al., 1999; Robert et al., 2002). Nevertheless, in
a study exploring the prevalence and clinical correlations of apathy and irritability
in 101 patients with Alzheimer’s disease, Starkstein et al. (1995b) found no correl-
ation between apathy and insight. The association between insight and apathy has
190 Historical and clinical
been based on the speculation that both poor insight and apathy may share a simi-
lar underlying pathophysiological mechanism involving either frontal or right
hemispheric function. However, any conclusions concerning the relationship
between insight and apathy would be premature particularly given the variable
findings in relation to the correlations between patients’ insight and measures of
cognitive/brain function.
Likewise, attempting to link impairment of insight with brain mechanisms
putatively underlying psychotic symptoms in dementia, some studies have
explored the relationship between patients’ insight into dementia and the presence
of psychotic/behavioural symptoms (Table 5.1). These studies have also yielded
mixed results with some researchers reporting an association between poor insight
and the presence of psychotic symptoms (Mangone et al., 1991; Weinstein et al.,
1994; Migliorelli et al., 1995; Starkstein et al., 1996; 1997a), and others finding no
correlation between insight and psychotic phenomena (Lopez et al., 1994;
Harwood et al., 2000). Starkstein et al. (1996) found that the correlations between
insight and different psychotic symptoms varied according to the ‘object’ of insight
assessed. Thus, poor insight into cognitive problems was associated with the pres-
ence of delusions whilst poor insight into behavioural/personality problems correl-
ated rather with more mania and pathological laughter. Seltzer et al. (1995b) reported
a correlation between carer-rated irritability in patients and worse insight, and
similarly Starkstein et al. (1995b) found a correlation between patients with irri-
tability and poor insight. Once again, the too few studies carried out in these areas
preclude any definite conclusions. In addition, the variable methods used in assess-
ing psychotic/other behavioural features and the different inclusions within these
(e.g. delusions, misidentifications, mania, etc.) are also likely to contribute to the
overall inconsistent results in this area.
greater carers’ burden. Thus, it is not yet clear what aspect of insight may or may
not be important in determining carers’ perceptions of stress and burden. Rymer
et al. (2002) found that whilst poor insight in patients (including insight into
memory and functioning) correlated with more carer burden, disinhibited behaviour
on the part of patients was a stronger contributor to such burden. Lastly, it should
be mentioned that isolated case reports found an association between patients’
insight and suicide risk (e.g. Rohde et al., 1995; Ferris et al., 1999), and one study
reported that poor insight into attention was a predictor of patients who stopped
driving (Cotrell & Wild, 1999). At this stage, such findings can only be considered
as possible indicators for further work and exploration.
For the sake of completion, a brief mention should be made concerning the notion
of impaired insight or awareness into function/knowledge in patients with demen-
tia. As already discussed in Chapter 4, the concept of implicit memory has been an
area of research from the neuropsychology and cognitive psychology perspectives
in healthy subjects and patients suffering from amnesic syndromes. To reiterate
briefly, performance on cognitive tasks can be improved on the basis of specific
experiences (e.g. priming or skill-learning tasks) of which individuals can remain
unaware (Schacter, 1995). In other words, implicit memory focuses on the idea that
learning specific tasks can be aided by mental processes of which the individual has
no conscious awareness. Patients with dementia, like those with various amnesic
syndromes, have been observed to show impaired explicit memory but, at the same
time, to preserve their implicit memory (McGlynn & Schacter, 1989; Schacter, 1995).
This demonstrates that dissociations can occur between possibly independent
aspects of memory functioning. In other words, patients’ performance on specific
memory tests can be enhanced using priming without the patients being aware of,
or showing insight into, the mechanisms by which they are able to recall set tasks.
Similarly to patients with amnesic syndromes, researchers have reported that
patients with Alzheimer’s disease show dissociations between the various types
of implicit memory that is preserved. Thus patients can exhibit different impair-
ments in implicit memory which suggests that awareness at an unconscious level
may be disrupted. For example, the commonest finding with respect to Alzheimer’s
disease has been that priming for word-stem completion tasks (lexical and pic-
torial priming) is impaired whilst priming for motor tasks is preserved (Shimamura
et al., 1987; Burke et al., 1994; Russo & Spinnler, 1994; Schacter, 1995). The con-
verse, i.e. deficits in procedural, motor-related tasks and sparing of verbal-related
tasks, has been found in patients with Huntington’s disease (Heindel et al., 1989;
Butters et al., 1990). This difference in the specific type of preserved implicit
192 Historical and clinical
memory observed between patients with Alzheimer’s disease and those with
Huntington’s disease has been related to possible different psychologically and
neurologically distinct implicit memory systems involved in the diseases. Thus,
Butters et al. (1990) postulate that verbal and pictorial priming may be dependent
on the integrity of neocortical association areas which are damaged in Alzheimer’s
disease. On the other hand, the motor skill learning is likely to be mediated by the
corticostriatal system which in turn is damaged in basal ganglia diseases such as
Huntington’s disease. Similarly, Keane et al. (1991) reported further dissociation in
priming deficits in their study of patients with Alzheimer’s disease finding that ver-
bal priming was impaired but perceptual priming was preserved. This they linked
to possible neuronal mechanisms relating to dysfunction of the temporo-parietal
lobe underlying the former and preservation of function in the occipital lobe relat-
ing to the latter, in keeping with the Alzheimer’s disease process.
The question, however, of whether implicit memory not only represents a dis-
tinct memory system from an explicit memory system but is also itself constituted
by a number of distinct implicit memory systems continues to be debated. Whilst
the observations of dissociations between explicit and implicit memory and,
particularly, the double dissociations observed in implicit memory is a powerful
argument for the existence of multiple distinct memory systems (Heindel et al.,
1989; Schacter, 1995; 1999), the underlying assumptions behind the implicit/
explicit memory research need to be understood (Chapter 4). At the same time,
others have argued against a purely multiple memory systems view, proposing
instead other possible explanations for the experimental dissociations in memory
observed focusing more on the ways in which memory might be stored, retrieved
and contextualised (see Bauer et al., 1993).
Finally, the question still remains, as far as implicit memory or knowledge is
concerned, where does awareness itself fit in the models proposed? Clearly, the dis-
tinction between explicit and implicit memory has been formulated as the absence
of conscious awareness in the manifestation of the latter. This then raises further
questions concerning the nature of awareness as a mental structure, the extent to
which the different mental functions might be associated with different levels of
awareness, the importance of awareness at different times, whether mental func-
tions themselves are defined in some way by awareness, etc. As was emphasised in
Chapter 4, the concept of implicit memory, or memory without awareness, has
been defined and formulated in a neuropsychological and cognitive psychological
framework in which mental functions are viewed in terms of independent/semi-
independent albeit interacting modules. Within this structure, implicit memory is
elicited on the basis of very specific cognitive tasks. The question, however, of how
unconscious awareness or mental processing might relate to an overall structure or
concept of insight remains to be explored.
193 Insight in organic brain syndromes: insight into dementia
5.4 Conclusion
Conceptual
So far, the chapters in this book have explored how, in clinical psychiatry, the
notion of insight has become conceptualised as an independent phenomenon, one
that not only could be observed (to different extents) in patients with mental illness
but one that could, moreover, be measured and related to other clinical and non-
clinical variables. We have seen how, in Western cultures, this demarcation of insight
as an independent variable became possible in the context of a number of factors
including, a background of philosophical/psychological thought encouraging self-
observation and self-understanding, changing ideas concerning the nature of
mental illness itself, and, an environment that fostered close clinical observation.
Then, reviewing the study of patients’ insight in various clinical areas, we have seen
that perspectives taken to understand and assess insight in clinical (and non-clinical)
populations have been quite different. In part, this seems to have occurred as a
result of diverse theoretical positions taken by the different professional disciplines.
In addition, however, and closely interlinked with this is the fact that the different
demands of the various clinical populations have determined to some extent the
approaches taken. This issue will be discussed in more detail later. However, it is of
interest to reiterate, that in general psychiatry it was the observation that patients
with mental illness could have insight that led to further work exploring this phe-
nomenon. In contrast, in patients with neurological/neuropsychological impair-
ments, it was the converse observation that determined approaches exploring
insight in this clinical group. In other words, the study of insight in patients in these
areas was approached from opposite perspectives. In the former it was the surprising
presence of understanding and in the latter it was the surprising absence of under-
standing that contributed to the different approaches taken in relation to these
patients. Apart from the differences in approaches to the study of insight between
the different clinical populations, we have also seen how within one clinical popula-
tion differences are evident in the way insight is conceived and evaluated. And,
common to all the clinical areas is the striking finding that studies exploring
insight in these patient groups have yielded mixed and inconsistent results when
attempting to relate levels of patients’ insight with other clinical variables.
From the work examined thus far, a number of questions seem to emerge. The
first question relates to the multiple approaches taken to the study of insight in
196 Conceptual
patients. What does this mean in terms of understanding the concept or structure
of insight? Can the different conceptions and measures of insight be related or uni-
fied in some way? Or is it simply the case that different phenomena are being
invoked sharing only a superficial resemblance with each other? Secondly, how can
the variable results of the studies on insight be explained? Why is it that despite
extensive empirical work, it is still not possible to conclude much about the pre-
dictive validity of insight in relation to mental illness or its relationship to either
the patients’ illness or to individual/environmental factors? While some of the
inconsistent results between studies exploring insight could be explained on
methodological grounds, i.e. differences in study designs, different patient groups,
different outcome measures, etc., I would argue that there has to be another import-
ant factor to consider here, borne out also by the other questions raised, and that
has to do with the concept of insight itself. Throughout my arguments so far, I have
emphasised the complexity of the concept, the difficulties in delineating its bound-
aries as well as its likely multidimensional structure.
Perhaps then, in order to start answering some of the questions raised so far, it is
important to examine the concept of insight in detail, to look at its conceptualisa-
tion and to identify the crucial issues for clarification. This section of the book
therefore focuses specifically on exploring the conceptual problems that arise in
relation to the study of insight. Chapter 6 examines the concept of insight from the
perspective of its likely nature. Specifically, it addresses the issues involved around
the various meanings of insight and their determinants and discusses the implica-
tions these have for the empirical study of insight. Chapter 7 focuses on a crucial
feature of insight, namely, its relational aspects. It explores the ways in which dif-
ferent ‘objects’ of insight influence the clinical phenomenon of insight that is
elicited and examines the implications this carries for the structure of insight.
Based on the issues identified in the preceding chapters, Chapters 8 and 9 go on to
develop a model for a structure of insight. Firstly, Chapter 8 argues, on theoretical
and empirical grounds, for a meaningful distinction to be made between awareness
and insight. Then, Chapter 9, on the basis of this distinction, proposes a model of
insight structure that accommodates the relational ‘object’ of insight assessment.
Thus, a framework is presented which allows the identification and definition of
specific insight phenomena for the purposes of future empirical work.
6
of insight. As implied above, this distinction is made for ease of analysis and it
should be understood that, in fact, in many respects the concept and phenomenon
of insight are interdependent. Hence, much of what is said about the concept will
apply to the phenomenon and vice versa. Throughout both sections, the chapter
highlights the implications of the issues raised for both the structure of insight and
for its empirical study.
The central question addressed in this section concerns the nature of the problems
which contribute to the complexities surrounding the concept of insight. In other
words, what is it about the concept of insight that gives rise to the difficulties we
have seen in defining it in a consistent way? Evidently, the different approaches to the
study of insight that have been reviewed share some things in common and, in vari-
ous ways, refer to some understanding or knowledge the individual has concerning
his/her condition. However, there are, as has also been clearly apparent, significant
differences. Such differences seem to present at various levels and need to be exam-
ined in some detail in order to allow us to develop a putative structure for insight.
The differences in meaning of insight can be usefully divided into two main types
or groups, namely, (i) problems of content and (ii) problems concerning the nature
of insight. Each of these will be explored in turn.
however, and broader views of insight are evident in the subsequent debates around
the notion (e.g. Société Médico-Psychologique, 1870) and in much of the later work
that focused specifically on this topic (e.g. Parant, 1888). Insight became more than
a perception of a madness state but was conceived as a knowledge of a madness state,
the knowledge that was understood in a wider sense than awareness or perception.
Hence, patients could have some knowledge about different aspects of their illness
and they could make judgements to varying extents about their condition and how
it affected them. This wider conceptualisation of insight meant that it was possible to
distinguish between various degrees of insight and patients, therefore, could be
described as showing different amounts and types of knowledge in relation to their
madness. In the context of increasing focus on quantitative research and the opera-
tionalisation of clinical variables, the empirical studies exploring insight in patients
with mental disorders highlight very clearly a similar range of definitions of insight
from the narrow to the wide (Chapter 3). Thus, the earlier studies view the patient’s
acknowledgement or recognition of being unwell as tantamount to having insight
(e.g. Eskey, 1958; Van Putten et al., 1976; Heinrichs et al., 1985) paralleling the narrow
conception of insight as awareness or perception of disturbance. At the same time,
the meaning of insight in such studies, whilst narrow in the sense of the awareness or
perception inherent in the definition, is broad in the sense of the lack of specificity
relating to the mental disturbance itself (see Chapter 3). Most of the studies where
insight is conceived in an all-or-none or categorical fashion imply a conception of
insight as a basic awareness or perception of a mental disturbance. Many of the more
recent studies, on the other hand, invoke a multidimensional conception of insight
where clearly the meaning of insight is broadened to a wider understanding of the
knowledge involved (e.g. Greenfeld et al., 1989; Amador et al., 1991; Marková &
Berrios, 1992a). This knowledge is wider in that it includes not just the perception
or awareness of some change in the patient but it also demands some judgements on
his/her part concerning the nature and consequences of the experienced changes.
Perhaps some of the widest conceptions of insight have been offered in the psy-
choanalytic literature (Chapter 2). Here, insight has been conceived as a much ‘deeper’
knowledge of changes in the self – deeper, in several senses of the term. Firstly, the
type or content of the knowledge itself is viewed as deeper, encompassing the under-
standing an individual has of his/her self in the context of life experiences and rela-
tionships together with the understanding of his/her motivations, the latter often
couched in terms of unconscious mental processes. Secondly, the way in which such
knowledge or insight is acknowledged is conceived as taking place at different levels
of understanding. In other words, distinctions are made between the levels at which
such knowledge is understood by an individual, e.g. cognitive, intellectual, emotional
or dynamic level (Reid & Finesinger, 1952; Bibring, 1954; Richfield, 1954). Thirdly,
possible reasons or motivations behind changes in insight are incorporated into
200 Conceptual
the concept itself. Denial in this context is a psychological coping response designed
to protect individuals from the consequences of having knowledge of their illness/
disabilities (Weinstein & Kahn, 1955). Thus, the concept of insight within this par-
ticular psychological framework is very much broader including knowledge not just
of particular experiences but of the way in which the self relates to them, absorbs
them and acts on them and understands underlying reasons and purposes.
In contrast, as has been emphasised in the work on insight in neurological states,
insight in the narrowest sense of awareness or perception has been exemplified
particularly by the original concept of anosognosia (Chapters 4 and 5). Perhaps
it is because of its derivation from the opposite perspective, namely, as the study
of the lack of insight or unawareness of a particular deficit/impairment (explored
in detail in Chapter 7), that the meaning of insight in this context has persisted
in the narrow, circumscribed sense of awareness, i.e. the perception (or lack of)
that something is wrong. Even with some broadening of this concept engendered
by the proliferation of empirical work, qualitative differences in awareness or
knowledge have been limited to knowledge of different aspects of the impairment
such as severity (Prigatano et al., 1986), change compared with previous ability
(Sherer et al., 1998a) or prediction of ability (Schacter, 1991). In other words,
the knowledge remains focused on different aspects of the actual impairment but
does not refer (in a comparable way to the conceptions of insight in general psych-
iatry or psychodynamic psychology) to knowledge of what the impairment means
for the self.
Captured within the range of breadths of meanings of insight are the other dif-
ferences between contents of definitions that were noted above. For example, striking
is the range of different types of judgements inherent to the various conceptualisa-
tions of insight, particularly as far as the more complex multidimensional definitions
are concerned. Thus, in addition to an awareness of some change, concepts of insight
include various judgements relating to the following:
1 an attribution of the change to pathology (e.g. Jaspers, 1948; David, 1990; Amador
et al., 1991);
2 social consequences of illness (Amador et al., 1991);
3 views concerning aetiology and likely recurrence (Greenfeld et al., 1989);
4 perception of changes in the self and one’s interaction with the world (Marková &
Berrios, 1992a);
5 need for medical treatment (McEvoy et al., 1989a; David, 1990; Amador et al.,
1991).
6 attitudes towards experiences (Soskis & Bowers, 1969; Cutting, 1978; Marks
et al., 2000);
7 comparisons with previous function (Sherer et al., 1998);
201 The conceptualisation of insight
what it can tell us about a particular aspect of the mind or the way in which indi-
viduals think and behave in regards to certain situations. In other words, taking an
epistemological perspective would mean that the ‘reality’ of insight as a structure is
defined not as an entity in itself but in terms of the validity of knowledge consti-
tuting it as well as through the way in which it helps to understand and organise
mental phenomena. Whilst this book takes an epistemological perspective in gen-
eral, this does not, at this point, help to clarify in a practical way the nature of the
concept of insight.
A somewhat different though related approach, therefore, and one that I propose
to take here, is to examine the nature of the concept of insight from the perspective
of clinical meaningfulness. The above distinction between ontological and epistemo-
logical perspectives is mentioned mainly because these perspectives are in some
ways reflected in the clinical approach. Specifically, I want to argue that the concept
of insight refers to a mental state and not to a mental symptom. This is a significant
claim because it carries important implications for understanding insight and for
empirical research in this area. These implications will be discussed later. At this
point, it is necessary to define the distinction between state and symptom.
By ‘mental state’ I am simply referring to a condition of the mind, or ‘the mental
or emotional condition in which a person finds himself at a particular time’ (OED,
2nd edition). For example, a mental state may comprise of mixtures of emotions/
feelings, thoughts, worries, daydreams, reflections, etc., any of which may assume
prominence at a specific time. By ‘symptom’ I am referring to an indicator of dis-
ease, i.e. ‘a phenomenon, circumstance, or change of condition arising from and
accompanying a disease or affection, and constituting an indication or evidence of
it; a characteristic sign of some particular disease’ (OED, 2nd edition, my emphasis).
For example, symptoms include a range of specific experiences which are perceived
as being out of the ordinary, uncharacteristic or even unexplained, such as pain,
low mood, fatigue, hallucination, etc. In other words, the main distinction between
the concepts I want to emphasise, and without making any assumptions concern-
ing ontology, lies in the crucial link with some form of pathology in the concept of
symptom. To repeat then, I would argue that it makes more sense to conceive the
nature of the concept of insight as a mental state and not as a symptom. Firstly,
however, are there grounds to this argument, i.e. is it the case that insight, or rather
lack of insight, is generally considered as a symptom, a phenomenon indicating dis-
ease, in the context of the empirical work that has been examined in this book?
empirically, there has been little work specifically exploring the possible nature of
insight as a concept or phenomenon. In general psychiatry, there is some direct ref-
erence to the view that poor insight represents a symptom or feature of the mental
disorder itself but otherwise most of the evidence substantiating this view is indir-
ect. In terms of the direct evidence, the most obvious source, as has already been
mentioned, has been the large study described in the Report of the International
Pilot Study of Schizophrenia (World Health Organization, 1973), in which ‘lack of
insight’ is reported as the most frequent symptom found in schizophrenia. This
finding, contained in a table depicting relative frequencies of symptoms found in
patients with schizophrenia has, since then, been reproduced not only in various
textbooks of psychiatry (e.g. Gelder et al., 1996) but also in numerous subsequent
articles exploring insight in patients. Thus, much of the empirical work examining
insight in general psychiatry has been based explicitly on this assumption that
poor insight is a symptom (or sign) of schizophrenia (e.g. Carroll et al., 1999;
Weiler et al., 2000; White et al., 2000; Pyne et al., 2001; and many more). In add-
ition, some researchers have themselves been explicit in articulating this view, e.g.
Cuesta and Peralta (1994) suggest that ‘lack of insight could be a primary symptom
resulting directly from the schizophrenic process’ (p. 359) and reinforce this view
in subsequent work (e.g. Peralta & Cuesta, 1994; Cuesta et al., 1995). Similarly,
Amador et al. (1994) reiterate that ‘poor insight is best viewed as a symptom (or
sign) comprising multiple components’ (p. 827). Cuffel et al. (1996) consider poor
insight to be an ‘important manifestation’ of schizophrenia, and, Kim et al. (1997)
refer to lack of insight as ‘an inherent trait of schizophrenia’ (p. 117). Perhaps one
of the most explicit expressions of the idea that poor insight is conceived as a
symptom of the disorder is seen in the study by Mohamed et al. (1999) where they
say, ‘poor insight can be conceptualised as an expression of the disorder [schizo-
phrenia], much as hallucinations or delusions’ (p. 525). Similar assumptions con-
cerning the notion that poor insight is a symptom of the disease can be found, to
varying degrees of explicitness, in studies exploring insight in organic brain dis-
orders (e.g. Green et al., 1993; see Clare, 2004 for review) and other conditions
(Chapters 3–5). There are some exceptions (and qualifiers, see below) to this gen-
eral view concerning the nature of insight. One obvious exception is the perspec-
tive taken within psychoanalytic psychology where insight is viewed as a mental
state, one which, moreover, explicitly colligates emotions and thinking into a
whole specifically relevant to the person. However, in general as far as empirical
studies of insight into general psychiatric disorders and organic brain syndromes
are concerned, it becomes apparent that poor insight is ‘treated’ as a symptom of
the patient’s condition.
Moving on to some of the indirect evidence for this claim, this can be inferred
from a number of points arising from both the theoretical and empirical work on
205 The conceptualisation of insight
insight reviewed in this book. First of all, as already mentioned, it is clear that there
has been little specific focus on examining the nature of insight as a concept/
phenomenon. In whatever way defined, insight has been referred to in general terms
as a concept, a phenomenon or a construct. However, these terms, whilst providing
a particular frame for the contents of the definition, do not say anything about the
nature of these contents in the sense of what sort of entity they might represent.
Thus, apart from the claims explicitly viewing poor insight as a symptom as
described above, little else has been said directly. In fact, it is fair to say that this
issue has tended to be disguised somewhat by some confusion engendered through
deployment of various allusions relating to this point. For example, the concept of
insight is discussed in terms of aetiology or mechanisms, i.e. focusing on processes
that might result in poor insight (e.g. Arduini et al., 2003; Drake & Lewis, 2003;
Rossell et al., 2003) or models/theories, i.e. structures or frameworks that might
help to explain poor insight (e.g. Birchwood et al., 1994; Lysaker et al., 2003;
Thompson et al., 2001) or perspectives, i.e. different ways of conceiving poor
insight (David & Kemp, 1997). In terms of such mechanisms or models or per-
spectives described, the nature of the concept of insight is indirectly addressed. As we
have seen in Chapter 3, in general psychiatric disorders these mechanisms/models
tend to fall predominantly into three groups so that poor insight is explained in
terms of: (i) organic/neurocognitive dysfunction (e.g. Lysaker et al., 1998a; Young
et al., 1998; Larøi et al., 2000) or (ii) psychological/motivational response to illness
or (iii) symptomatic, i.e. intrinsically linked to a disease process and hence associ-
ated with psychopathology (e.g. Collins et al., 1997; Smith et al., 2000) and many
researchers suggest that poor insight is a product of a combination of such
mechanisms (e.g. Vaz et al., 2002). In addition, some have suggested further possi-
ble models or perspectives, including personality factors and cultural or socially
determined attitudes (e.g. Johnson & Orrell, 1995; David & Kemp, 1997; White
et al., 2000; Clare, 2004). In the main, however, the underlying explanations for
poor insight have focused on the disease process itself either in terms of the
psychopathology of the illness or in terms of neurocognitive dysfunction. As
Amador et al. (1991) state clearly, ‘some forms of unawareness may stem directly
from the pathophysiology of the disorder’ (p. 128) and this view has been the prin-
ciple one on which the postulated mechanisms underlying poor insight are based.
These suggested models/theories underlying poor insight assume the link between
insight and disease and hence the nature of insight in these cases is construed as a
symptom or indicator of the disease process. Clearly, there are some qualifications
to this claim in that psychological defence mechanisms (or coping/motivational
factors) have also been invoked as possibly underlying poor insight and this would
then be counter to the notion that poor insight is a symptom of the condition and
instead would be seen as a response to the condition. Similarly, the suggestion that
206 Conceptual
the intensity or severity of the other symptoms are rated. Secondly, the overall
severity of the condition is assessed by the total score on such instruments and con-
sequently, it is clear that poor insight contributes to the severity of the condition in
an analogous fashion to that of the other ‘symptoms’. In other words, whatever the
theoretical notion of insight might be, the issue is that in practical terms, the con-
cept is handled as another symptom.
symptoms with the sorts of judgements that are involved in defining insight. Thus, a
complaint of feeling anxious or suffering pain or experiencing a hallucination are
symptoms which can be defined in terms of direct experiences on the part of the
individual. The patient may perceive a change in his/her state and the ensuing symp-
tom is an expression of the patient’s judgement concerning this change, his/her
description of the experience. In contrast, insight brings together a range of different
and disparate judgements in order to define the phenomenon; i.e. as we have seen in
metacognitive parlance, it involves judgements vis-à-vis the individual’s experience
as opposed to judgements involving the description of the experience. I suggest that
this would fit more with a mental state view of insight rather than a mental symp-
tom. There is, in addition, a further, more specific, point to consider here and one
that will be examined in more detail in the next chapters. Here, it is sufficient to say
that, by definition, any subjective experience described by an individual is dependent
on his/her awareness of this as a phenomenon for it would not be possible otherwise
to mark this out and apart from the underlying mental state. Consequently, it follows
that the experience of subjective phenomena is itself intrinsically linked with aspects
of the processes which constitute insight. This again implies that the concept of
insight has a wide, outreaching structure, one that would more easily be viewed as
underpinning a mental state than a symptom in the conventional sense.
Thirdly, the empirical work that has been reviewed both in general psychiatric
disorders and in organic brain syndromes shows convincingly the very mixed pictures
of outcomes between patients’ insight and clinical variables (Chapters 3–5). Thus,
some studies show an association between poor insight and more severe disease
(e.g. Verhey et al., 1995; Rymer et al., 2002; Vaz et al., 2002; Rossell et al., 2003) but
other studies disagree (e.g. Green et al., 1993; Lysaker & Bell, 1994; Chen et al.,
2001; Howorth & Saper, 2003). Similarly, some studies report an association between
poor insight and neurological lesion or neurocognitive dysfunction (e.g. Ott et al.,
1996a, b; Young et al., 1998; Lysaker et al., 2002) but, again, others find no such
association (e.g. Weinstein et al., 1994; Goldberg et al., 2001; Mintz et al., 2004). The
relationship between poor insight and disease factors can therefore at best be
described as variable. In other words, the rationale behind such studies, in terms of
viewing poor insight as an intrinsic feature of the illness itself, cannot be properly
sustained given the inconsistency of results. Again, this is suggestive of a wider con-
ception of insight as a mental state rather than a symptom.
Lastly, there is the issue of considering insight in so-called healthy individuals. Is
it the case, e.g. that healthy subjects are always insightful concerning experienced
events? Do such individuals always have full awareness and understanding about
their experiences and behaviours? It is difficult to argue for this being the case. In fact,
there is a great deal of evidence to suggest that in regards to ‘normal’ experiences and
behaviours, individuals show a range of insight or knowledge (Nisbett & Wilson,
210 Conceptual
1977; Wilson & Dunn, 2004). Leaving aside the question of value, i.e. whether full
insight is necessarily always beneficial to the individual, much work concerning
‘healthy’ individuals has focused on exploring possible mechanisms underlying the
different levels of insight or knowledge individuals have at different times and in
relation to different experiences. Just like in the work on insight in pathological
states, it has been postulated that both motivational and non-motivational processes
are important; the former are conceived in terms of both conscious and uncon-
scious mental processes and can be understood in various frameworks, e.g. psy-
choanalytic or self-deception (Fingarette, 1969; Haight, 1980); the latter are conceived
in more cognitive psychological approaches where unconscious mental processes
are viewed as intrinsic to the structure of the mind and consequently inaccessible
to introspection (Wilson & Dunn, 2004). The issue here, however, is that, irrespec-
tive of possible reasons and mechanisms underlying individuals’ insight into their
experiences, so-called lack of insight can be viewed as a common and normal and
sometimes adaptational phenomenon in healthy subjects. In this case, the question
of a link between lack of insight and pathology or illness simply does not arise.
This leaves us with the option that lack of insight in patients, conceived as a symp-
tom, represents a different phenomenon from lack of insight in healthy people.
Alternatively, and more plausibly I would argue that insight, is more usefully
viewed as a mental state whether this is in a healthy subject or in a patient with a
particular illness. Pathology or illness is only one factor that may affect an individ-
ual’s insight (or aspect of insight) but clearly many other factors will also be
important. In other words, as a mental state, insight will be independent from the
disease as such but interdependent with various factors, including disease, affect-
ing mental processes.
improved insight over the time of the study (e.g. McDaniel et al., 1995; Derouesné
et al., 1999) and yet this finding tends not to be discussed, presumably because this
would be counter to the notion that poor insight is a symptom intrinsic to the dis-
ease process. Viewing insight as a dynamic mental state, however, could help to
explain such findings as the disease would only be one factor affecting insight and
other changes, such as for example increased information given to patients about
what they are experiencing, might contribute to insight held at a particular time.
The other main implication for empirical work, arising from the view that insight
may more usefully be considered a mental state, lies in the design of studies search-
ing for relationships between lack of insight and disease variables. This will be
explored in more detail later but essentially the issue lies in the question of local-
isation of lack of insight with brain changes or cognitive dysfunction. As a mental
state, it would make little sense to attempt to correlate this with structural brain
lesions. Efforts made at examining possible neurobiology underlying poor insight
are unlikely to be successful in relation to the mental state as a whole. Instead, it
would make sense to determine first perhaps those aspects of poor insight that
might be more directly related to a pathological process such as unawareness/
anosognosia in the narrow neurological sense and concentrate on likely associ-
ations there. Similar principles would apply to studies exploring poor insight as
inherent to the disease process. In turn, this would depend on revising the methods
developed for assessing insight and addressing explicitly the specific aspects of
insight to be explored.
Earlier, for ease of analysis, the distinction was made between the concept and the
phenomenon of insight, the former referring to the theoretical structure or mean-
ing of insight and the latter referring to that aspect of the concept that is elicited in
a clinical or empirical situation. It was emphasised that the concept of insight was
wider than the phenomenon as it would be unrealistic to expect to be able to elicit in
a clinical event the totality of what insight as a whole might encompass. However,
it was also stressed that this distinction is artificial and made simply to organise the
arising theoretical issues around insight and its empirical study. Therefore, it is
important to reiterate that the problems of meanings of insight, as discussed
above, likewise apply to the phenomenon of insight. If, as was argued, insight is
most usefully viewed as a specific mental state with wide, undefined borders to its
content, then similarly, the phenomenon of insight can be viewed as a particular
aspect of such a mental state. In addition, however, the phenomenon of insight raises
other more specific issues and problems which also need to be examined. Whereas the
focus of the problems raised in relation to the concept of insight was seen as problems
212 Conceptual
of meaning, here in this section, the focus of problems in relation to the phenom-
enon of insight can be best described as problems of interpretation.
Problems of interpretation emerge by definition. Thus, by virtue of defining
the phenomenon of insight as that aspect of insight that is elicited clinically, the
question of interpretation necessarily arises because of the participation of judge-
ment on the part of another individual with respect to the patient. This is import-
ant because of the contribution of this external judgement to the phenomenon
of insight itself. In other words, while, as was stressed earlier, the concept of insight
is wider than the phenomenon of insight, nevertheless, the phenomenon of insight
will include extra or additional elements relating to different forms of external
judgements that are involved in determining the phenomenon itself. There are
several aspects to consider in relation to this and it is worthwhile to briefly exam-
ine these and the implications they carry for understanding the phenomenon
of insight.
on views concerning various abilities (e.g. Green et al., 1993; Vasterling et al., 1997).
In each case, the types of judgements elicited from the patients have been influenced
by the specific conceptualisations of insight by the researchers and by the particular
ways these should be translated into an empirical measure.
on the Present State Examination), then the greater will be the contribution of
individual clinician factors to the actual phenomenon of insight that is elicited.
brain syndromes, a wide range of measures have been developed to evaluate patients’
insight. The extent to which the judgement of discrepancy is exercised by the clin-
ician thus also depends, inter alia, on the type of measure used. For example, measures
of insight based on answers to general questions as to whether patients consider
themselves mentally or emotionally ill will demand different sorts of interpretation
of concordance from the clinician than measures which address a range of specific
aspects of the patient’s condition which perhaps narrow down some of the inter-
pretative elements. On the other hand, measures of insight which already rely on
discrepancies between patients and carers (e.g. Green et al., 1993; Smith et al., 2000)
will introduce additional interpretative factors, not only from the clinician who
evaluates the results but also from the family/carers who judge patients on various
problems/abilities. As was shown earlier, such judgements on the part of carers are
likely to be influenced by many factors, both individual and contextual, and may not
necessarily represent accurate appraisals (De Bettignies et al., 1990). The issue here,
however, is not so much about the accuracy or inaccuracy of such external judge-
ments of patients but about the fact that the final phenomenon of insight that is cap-
tured becomes a complex of subjective and ‘objective’ judgements and interpretations
whose individual components may not be easy to define. Similarly, where measures
of insight rely on discrepancies between patients’ appraisals of problems and per-
formance on specific tests (e.g. Anderson & Tranel, 1989), the assumption again is
that performance on the tests provides the ‘correct’ evaluation of patients’ abilities.
Nevertheless, the issue concerning the extent to which such tests actually reflect a sub-
jective experience of problems (generally couched in very broad terms) is a matter
of another type of interpretation. Different again is the interpretation of discrep-
ancy required in assessing insight on the basis of patients’ behaviours. In fact, as was
seen earlier (Chapters 3–5), there have been very few measures of insight focusing
on patients’ behaviours rather than speech but an interesting measure of insight in
patients with dementia was designed by Giovannetti et al. (2002) who observed
patients’ reactions to mistakes on ordinary tasks and on this basis made a judgement
of patients’ awareness. Clearly, the sorts of interpretations involved in this type of
appraisal will depend on different types of judgements and comparisons (i.e. judge-
ments concerning how a healthy subject might respond in a similar situation).
Apart from the type of measure of insight used, interpretation of discrepancy
between clinician and patient perception of problems will also depend on the ‘object’
of insight chosen for evaluation. In Chapter 5, the term ‘object of insight’ was intro-
duced to refer to the different aspects of dementia in relation to which insight was
examined (e.g. memory problems, activities of daily living, behavioural problems,
etc.).‘Object of insight’ as a general term referring to the relational aspects of insight
will be the focus of examination in Chapter 7. Here, the term is used to briefly illustrate
that different judgements are involved in the interpretation of discrepancies between
216 Conceptual
6.3 Conclusion
In order to address some of the complexities that have been raised around the study
of insight in the previous chapters, it is essential to examine in some detail issues
relevant to the conceptualisation of insight. For this purpose and reasons of analysis,
a distinction has been made between the concept of insight and the phenomenon of
insight. The concept of insight is defined as the theoretical structure of insight as a
whole whilst the phenomenon of insight refers to the clinical manifestation of insight
and, hence, reflects only an aspect of the concept of insight.
Examining the meaning of the concept of insight identifies two main areas of dif-
ficulties. Firstly, analysis of the range of definitions of insight in clinical and empir-
ical work indicates that it is the lack of defined boundaries to the various contents
that poses the main conceptual difficulty. In other words, the extent of the patient’s
knowledge or understanding of a condition that is required for insight, in terms of
detail of information, degree to which it affects oneself, the level of certainty, etc., is
difficult to demarcate clearly. Secondly, from a clinical perspective, exploring the
possible nature of the concept of insight shows that there is some confusion about
this in the literature. Most studies suggest that the concept of insight (or poor
insight) is viewed as a symptom or intrinsic feature of the condition affecting the
patient. On the basis of evidence provided here, however, I argue for a view of the con-
cept of insight as a particular mental state. In this sense, the concept of insight is, to
some extent, independent of the condition affecting the patient though its aspects are
likely to be affected by disease factors as well as by other non-disease-related factors.
Many of the multidimensional constructs of insight proposed in the literature would
fit in better with a mental state view of insight rather than a symptom view, partic-
ularly, since so far there has not been a theory put forward to help understand the
relationship of the various dimensions of insight to one another.
The view of the concept of insight as a mental state carries a number of impor-
tant implications including its conception as a dynamic process and one that is
likely to fluctuate under the influence of various internal and external factors. Most
importantly though, it carries implications for the way in which future studies on
insight need to be directed, especially as far as research on possible neurobiology is
concerned where more specified aspects of the concept of insight would need to be
determined.
Examining the phenomenon of insight identifies the main conceptual problem as
one of interpretation. In other words, as the phenomenon of insight is manifested
or elicited in a clinical situation, there will always be another participant/clinician
involved in making a judgement. Interpretation can be identified at different levels
including at the level of translation from concept to empirical measure, at the level
of clinician judgement and in relation to an interactive communicative context.
218 Conceptual
Following on from the previous chapter, in terms of examining some of the con-
ceptual problems underlying the meaning of insight, the focus in this chapter is on
another highly important aspect of insight, namely its relational nature. So far,
problems of meaning of insight have concentrated simply on the term itself. The
differences in the meaning of insight in regards to definitions varying in breadth,
detail, components, and otherwise, have been highlighted and difficulties around
specifying boundaries of the content of the concept have been identified. Likewise,
it has been argued that the nature of the concept of insight is most usefully regarded
as a mental state and consequently determined by multifarious elements of which
the mental disorder or condition affecting the patient is only one. Additional prob-
lems relating to the meaning of the phenomenon of insight have been raised on
account of the specific issues involved in the interpretation of a clinical state necessary
to the determination of the phenomenon of insight.
It has been apparent, however, both with respect to the exploration of insight in
different clinical disorders and with respect to the exploration of insight in a par-
ticular clinical disorder, that insight cannot be explored in isolation as some sort of
independent entity. Instead, the phenomenon of insight is always manifested or
elicited in relation to some aspect of the condition affecting the patient. In other
words, insight is a relational concept – or an ‘intentional’ concept in the sense of
Brentano (1874/1995). It can only be understood or expressed in terms of its relation
to something, be that a pathological state or a non-morbid experience. Thus, one
cannot have insight without there being something to have insight about and this
‘something’ has already been referred to as the ‘object’ of insight assessment
(Marková & Berrios, 2001). The ‘object’, therefore, refers to the particular mental/
physical state (e.g. mental symptoms, illness/disorder, neurological abnormality,
neuropsychological deficit, etc.) in relation to which insight is being assessed. The
essential point that will be argued in this chapter is that this relationship between the
phenomenon of insight and the ‘object’ of insight assessment is bi-directional (and
interactional). This means that, when exploring insight empirically, not only is it the
case that the ‘object’ of insight assessment needs to be specified but, and crucially,
the ‘object’ of insight assessment will, to a significant extent, determine the
219
220 Conceptual
phenomenon of insight that is elicited. This latter point forms the central issue in
this chapter and carries important implications for understanding the structure of
insight as well as for interpreting empirical studies on insight and for determining
future research in this area. In effect, this is saying that, different ‘objects’ of insight
assessments (e.g. delusions/hallucinations as opposed to mental disorder as opposed
to memory impairment, etc.) will determine phenomena of insight that are char-
acterised by essentially different clinical features. In other words, the phenomena
of insight elicited or manifested in relation to different ‘objects’ of insight assessment
will be structurally different from each other. Structure, in this context, refers to the
constitutive framework underlying insight, in terms of numbers and types of com-
ponents, their interrelationships and the rules (historical, theoretical, language based,
etc.) governing their interrelationships.
Before moving on to explore how different ‘objects’ of insight assessment might
exert their effect on the clinical phenomena of insight, the chapter first looks at the
importance of this claim in the context of current research work and in further
developing understanding around the meaning of insight at both the conceptual and
phenomenal levels. Next, the definition of ‘object’ of insight assessment will be exam-
ined in more detail and, finally, different ways in which the ‘object’ of insight assess-
ment may shape the clinical phenomenon of insight will be discussed.
At first glance it might seem that any discussion around the importance of, and
implications underlying, the relational aspects of insight is somewhat misplaced at
this point and would better belong at the end, after explication of the ways in which
objects of insight assessment may shape clinical phenomena of insight. However,
there is a two-fold purpose in dealing with this now and the second aspect relates
to presenting a rationale behind the examination of insight as a relational concept.
In other words, the significance of the relational aspects of insight is tightly bound up
in both the current assumptions made in empirical research as well as in the impli-
cations that are carried for future research and understanding of insight, and these
are difficult to disentangle cleanly from one another. Hence, from an explanatory
perspective, it is more useful to discuss the importance of the relational nature of
insight here.
What then is the significance of the relational aspects of insight? The fact that clin-
ically or empirically insight is explored in relation to different ‘objects’ of insight
assessment is not particularly surprising given the range and variety of conditions
affecting individuals. We have thus seen that, for example, insight has been elicited
in relation to different disorders (e.g. schizophrenia, bipolar affective disorder, depres-
sion, obsessive-compulsive disorders (OCD), dementia, head injury, cerebrovascular
221 The relational aspects of insight: the ‘object ’ of insight assessment
Clarifying the relational aspects of insight is, therefore, of theoretical and practical
importance. From a theoretical perspective, understanding the relationship
between insight and the ‘object’ of insight assessment should help to further deter-
mine the structure of insight both in terms of its overall structure as well as in terms
of structures underlying specific individual insight phenomena. From a more
practical viewpoint, clarifying the relationship between insight and the ‘object’ of
insight assessment may again also help to explain some of the inconsistent research
results and, furthermore, suggest appropriate methodological strategies for future
empirical work. In addition, from the research perspective, clarifying the insight–
‘object’ relationship is essential in order to address the assumption concerning
equivalence between insight phenomena. In particular, given the current focus on
brain localisation, it is vital that when exploring possible neurobiology of insight,
whether this is by means of neurocognitive function or neuroimaging or any other
way, the phenomena of insight chosen for investigation are of a similar structure.
Before moving on to discuss the ways in which the ‘object’ of insight assessment
might shape and determine the phenomenon of insight, it is important to examine
in a little more detail the sense in which the ‘object’ of insight assessment is meant.
There are three aspects to this that need to be emphasised.
made clearer in the next section when the ways in which the ‘objects’ of insight deter-
mine phenomena of insight are examined in the light of such differences in semantic
category and specific kind. Here, it is necessary to simply make the point that ‘objects’
are different in type. This also serves to distinguish from another term frequently used
in relation to insight assessment, namely ‘domains’ of insight or awareness.
The term ‘domain’ of awareness has been used particularly frequently in the empir-
ical work on insight in dementia (Chapter 5). We saw how, in dementia, researchers
tended to distinguish much more specifically the different aspects of dementia in rela-
tion to which insight was elicited (e.g. Kotler-Cope & Camp, 1995; Vasterling et al.,
1995; 1997; Starkstein et al., 1996). Domain, however, in this context refers to the
particular feature of dementia that is being accessed. For example, domains of aware-
ness are delineated in relation to memory problems, problems with activities of daily
living, mood changes, etc. all of which are viewed as common characteristics of
dementia as a disease. Thus, the domain can be considered an area or particular func-
tion affected by the disease and, as such, different domains contain different contents
but will share the common feature of being a characteristic of the disease. The
‘object’ of insight assessment, on the other hand, refers to a wider notion for it
includes not just characteristics of the condition affecting the patient but also the
condition itself and indeed any non-disease-related areas. For example, in studies
exploring insight in dementia where insight is explored into patients’ experience of
the condition as a whole, rather than specific features such as memory problems or
language difficulties (e.g. Schneck et al., 1982), the term ‘domain’ would not apply
but ‘dementia’ would be the ‘object’ of insight assessment. Thus, the ‘object’ of
insight assessment embraces anything in relation to which insight is assessed.
Whilst it will include ‘domains’ of the particular disease affecting the individual, it
also refers to other and different aspects of the specific condition experienced by
the individual as well as to any states (not necessarily morbid or specific to a con-
dition) chosen by clinicians or researchers.
directed at something. This something or ‘object’ becomes the focus around which
the perceptions and judgements are formed. Thus, when patients’ insight is explored
in a clinical or empirical situation, an ‘object’ of insight assessment is necessarily
chosen, usually, though not always, by the clinician, in order that the phenomenon
of insight is manifested. Without the ‘object’ there simply would be no phenomenon
of insight to elicit. Consequently, in the manifestation or elicitation of the clinical
phenomenon of insight, the ‘object’ of insight assessment becomes inherent or intrin-
sic to the structure of the phenomenon. The separation that is being made here, in
this chapter, between the ‘object’ of insight and the phenomenon of insight, has to
be understood, therefore, as a clarificatory device to help emphasise the direction
from which the insight–object relationship is being explored and is not meant to
signify a ‘real’ separation as far as the structure of the phenomenon of insight is
concerned.
‘object’ of insight assessment, then differences between clinician and patient in their
understanding of what ‘mental disorder’ actually means may result in consideration
of different ‘objects’ of insight assessment. It is likely that the degree to which the
‘object’ is made explicit, as well as the individual understanding of what the ‘object’
means or represents, will both determine the extent to which there is agreement on
this between the patient and clinician. As was discussed earlier in regards to the
interpretative issues involved in the determination of the phenomenon of insight,
this is likewise an issue that carries implications for the empirical assessment of
insight particularly in relation to research. Again, this is something that simply
needs to be understood, or taken into some account, when the structure of the
phenomenon of insight is considered.
of the disciplines, but also reflect more profound differences in structure. In other
words, the ‘objects’ of insight assessment (and concomitantly, because of the nature
of the insight–‘object’ relationship, the conceptualisation of insight with respect to
the objects) are embedded in a theoretical background that itself is only under-
standable in terms of the historical development of the discipline. It is in virtue of
this particular difference between ‘objects’ of insight assessment in relation to different
disciplines that the ‘objects’ will exert their differential effect on the phenomenon
of insight. This is best illustrated by looking at some examples.
This structure underlying the rules of the diagnostic process forms the framework
of the clinical psychiatric discipline. Eliciting patients’ mental and behavioural
phenomena on the part of the clinician is dependent, therefore, amongst other
things, on a particular way of conceiving such mental and behavioural phenomena,
and their disturbances. This sort of understanding is, in turn, dependent on a tax-
onomy of mental function (and dysfunction) which is assumed a priori but is one
that has developed within the discipline, and, in the context of other influences,
over time. The question of whether such a taxonomy is ‘valid’, i.e. whether there is
correspondence between the conventional mental taxonomy with brain mechanisms
or functions, is not the issue here. Instead, the point here is that it is governed by the
concepts developed specifically in the context and function of clinical psychiatry as a
discipline and its antecedents. Mental and behavioural phenomena are identified,
classified and prioritised on the basis of such concepts. And it is thus that the ‘object’
of insight assessment, necessarily enmeshed within this framework, will elicit a phe-
nomenon that is likewise structurally bound to the same frame. Related disciplines,
whilst sharing some of the conceptual background, are, by reasons of diverse histor-
ies, foci, and functions, underpinned by different theoretical structures constituted
by different concepts and assumptions.
versus emotional versus dynamic insight (Reid & Finesinger, 1952), or manifested –
e.g. structured and/or re-created (Abrams, 1981; Sternbach, 1989; Blum, 1992). The
‘object’ of insight in psychoanalytic theory, therefore, determines a structure of the
phenomenon of insight in ways that are different from those shaped by the ‘object’
of insight assessment in general psychiatry. Furthermore, apart from these differ-
ences determined by content, theory (i.e. the particular conceptual framework
underlying psychoanalytic theory) and focus, the very nature of the ‘object’ of insight
assessment (i.e. the ‘deep’ self-knowledge) makes it difficult for the phenomenon of
insight to be elicited directly. Hence, the phenomenon has to be elicited indirectly
through the exploration of likely mechanisms or effects of attaining insight in the
individual. This carries specific implications for research in this area particularly as
far as developing insight measures is concerned (Chapter 2).
7.3.1.3 Neurosciences
Different from general psychiatry and psychoanalytic psychology is the conceptual
framework underlying the neurological and neuropsychological disciplines. Apart
from the differences in terms of content and focus of the work undertaken, and the
language and theoretical/conceptual frame on which this is based, one striking differ-
ence, already mentioned several times, is the perspective from which neurosciences
have developed interest in insight and awareness. For example, in contrast to general
psychiatry, it has been the dramatic loss of awareness or insight in the face of prom-
inent neurological abnormality that has stimulated interest and research on insight
in these disciplines. Consequently, conceptualisation of insight has been, from the
very beginning (apart from some qualified exceptions where motivational theories
have been proposed (Chapter 4, Weinstein & Kahn, 1955)), strongly linked to the
neurological abnormality itself. This has resulted in a phenomenon of insight that
has, analogously, a narrower content and much more clearly demarcated borders.
Putting this another way, the ‘objects’ of insight within the neurosciences disciplines
refer to the particular neurological deficits or neuropsychological impairments
that are evident to the clinicians. These neurological deficits and neuropsychological
impairments are themselves enveloped in the theoretical backgrounds of these dis-
ciplines. Therefore, in simplified terms the neurological and neuropsychological
understanding of such impairments and deficits (e.g. hemiplegia, amnesic syn-
dromes, dysphasia, etc.) is framed in a language (and concepts) relating to the brain
and to putative brain processes. Thus, neurological impairment and deficits are
explained in terms of brain localisation theories, either in structural (specific brain
lesions) or functional (neuropathology or neuropharmacology of specific brain sys-
tems) terms or structured on modular and information-processing models in which
neuropsychological processes are viewed as independent or semi-independent func-
tions loosely superimposed on brain structure (e.g. Mesulam, 1986; Schacter, 1990;
231 The relational aspects of insight: the ‘object ’ of insight assessment
Stuss, 1991). The point here is that the ‘object’ of insight assessment, represented by
the neurological and neuropsychological impairments and deficits, is understood,
within these disciplines, in this particular ‘brain processes’ language. In turn, this
‘object’ of insight assessment determines a phenomenon of insight that is likewise
understood within this same theoretical structure. Hence, the phenomenon of insight
elicited in relation to the ‘object’ determined by the neurosciences disciplines, is a
structurally much narrower and more encapsulated phenomenon than that elicited
in relation to the ‘object’ of insight assessment in general psychiatry or psychoanalytic
psychology.
7.3.1.5 Dementia
Whilst dementia does not refer to a particular discipline, it is mentioned briefly
here because of the special position it occupies in terms of crossing several profes-
sional disciplines and the implications this carries for the exploration of insight in
this area. In other words, in clinical work and research in dementia, many of the
232 Conceptual
(Mullen et al., 1996; Amador & Gorman, 1998; Young et al., 1998; Flashman et al.,
2001, see above). As has already been demonstrated, this assumption has had
important consequences for the direction of research taken in these areas, particu-
larly, in terms of searching for a neurobiological explanation for impairment of
insight. This assumption of equivalence between insight phenomena in relation to
different ‘objects’ of insight assessment is, therefore, an important issue. Whereas
above this assumption was challenged on the grounds that ‘objects’ of insight
assessment, embedded in the specific conceptual backgrounds underlying differ-
ent disciplines (in this case, general psychiatry versus neurosciences), determined
phenomena of insight that were correspondingly structurally different, here the
argument against this assumption lies in the different order of meanings presented
by the ‘objects’. The terms ‘neuropsychological deficit’ and ‘mental illness’ are sim-
ply different with respect to the categories of meaning they represent. A similar
analogy can be made, for example, with the terms ‘flower’ and ‘nature’. The former
refers to a specific entity, directly observable and relatively easily demarcated with
clear boundaries. The latter may incorporate flower within its definition but refers
to much more than a collection of flowers and other such objects, and is not
directly observable nor easily demarcated. Perhaps another more relevant analogy
would be the difference between terms such as ‘nurse’ or ‘doctor’ and ‘the National
Health Service (NHS) system’. Whilst the former terms refer to specific entities or
subjects, directly observable and relatively easily described and defined, the latter is
clearly very much more than the sum of all the health professionals and resources
(and patients, etc.) contained within it. Instead, it includes within its meaning
the ways in which different parts of it work and interact, the politics involved,
the social issues, the hierarchies, and all possible structural elements and their
functional interrelationships. It is not directly observable and nor is it easily
demarcated.
Returning then to the terms ‘neuropsychological deficit’ and ‘mental illness’, we
are faced with similar categorical differences. The former refers to something that
is ‘objectively’ ascertainable in the sense that it is in principle determinable by a
third person either through direct observation or by means of specific tests and can
be relatively sharply demarcated. There is a one-to-one relationship between the
‘object’ (neurological or neuropsychological deficit, e.g. amnesia, hemiplegia,
dysphasia, etc.) and its determinable manifestation (e.g. poor memory, inability to
move limb, difficulty with speech). The term ‘mental illness’, on the other hand,
refers to a much broader construct and again, like ‘nature’ or ‘the NHS system’, does
not simply consist of a number of like subcomponents but embraces a wider struc-
ture that, in the case of ‘mental illness’, includes not only the signs and symptoms
of abnormal psychopathology (and the pathological aetiological factors) but also
the social, cultural, environmental and political determinants of the construct.
234 Conceptual
Direct observation and/or specific tests might not necessarily elicit it and bound-
aries of the construct are far from clear. There may be a one-to-one relationship
between some aspects of the construct (such as specific psychopathological signs)
and their determinable manifestation (e.g. psychomotor retardation, hallucin-
ations) but there is no clear one-to-one relationship between the construct as a
whole and its determinable manifestation. Indeed, as a construct in this wider
sense it would be illogical for it to have such a direct manifestation. Like ‘nature’ or
‘the NHS system’, it is simply not ‘observable’ in this sense and is only elicited or
determined (in the technical sense) by means of the specialised clinical judgements
exerted by health professionals. Moreover, many of the psychopathological, social,
cultural, political, etc., determinants fluctuate over time. Hence, this is not a fixed
concept and, as is clear from historical accounts, concepts of mental illness have
changed over the years and will continue to change (Berrios & Porter, 1995). Signs
and symptoms taken to indicate mental illness in one decade may not necessarily
apply in another decade. Similarly, they may differ from one culture to another or
even from one clinician to another.
In addition, whilst referring to a wide construct, the term ‘mental illness’ may,
from the perspective of the sufferer questioned about his/her insight, be confusing
or misleading in another sense, namely, with respect to the ‘illness’ component of
the term. Thus, although the clinician or observer are in a position where they may
be able to conceive ‘mental illness’ widely in terms of its theoretical determinants
and understand ‘illness’ in terms of morbidity, the patient may not experience
‘illness’ in the conventional meaning of the term. This means that there has to be
further distortion of the relationship between ‘mental illness’ as the ‘object’ and its
overt manifestation. This serves to highlight in another way the contrast between
the more direct one-to-one relationship between the ‘object’ of insight assessment
and its determinable manifestation that is present when the ‘object’ refers to a ‘neuro-
logical’ or ‘neuropsychological deficit’ and the lack of such a direct relationship
when the ‘object’ of insight assessment refers to a construct such as ‘mental illness’.
It seems, therefore, that there are important differences between terms such as
‘mental illness’ and ‘neuropsychological impairment’. These differences are not
simply those of content but relate to the way in which the referent is understood.
In other words, they belong to different categories of meaning. When ‘objects’ of
insight assessment refer to such terms, then likewise, they refer to different seman-
tic categories and in that sense they cannot be considered comparable (Ryle,
1949/1990). The phenomena of insight that are elicited in relation to such differ-
ent ‘objects’ of insight assessment, consequently, will be structurally different.
Thus, as is evident above, the phenomena of insight determined by these ‘objects’
must be constituted from different sorts of judgements, which are different not just
in terms of their content but in the types and complexities of judgements involved.
235 The relational aspects of insight: the ‘object ’ of insight assessment
It follows from this that the phenomenon of insight elicited in relation to mental
illness may not be equivalent to the phenomenon of insight elicited in relation to
neurological or neuropsychological impairment.
symptoms, the nature of the features referred to is not that of a loss of function/
ability but that of an added or new experience. In other words, something that was
previously not present in the normal or healthy mental state is added to it such that
there is an experience of change. Even where that ‘addition’ results in a subjective
experience of loss of ability or function (e.g. loss of interest, enjoyment, motiv-
ation, etc.), the point is that there is, by definition, an experienced change, which,
whilst it may be qualitative or quantitative in nature, still represents an ‘addition’ to
a mental state experience. What then does this mean for the phenomenon of
insight elicited in relation to each of such ‘objects’ of insight assessment?
When the ‘object’ of insight assessment refers to an observable loss of function
or ability, the phenomenon demanded by such an ‘object’, has as its primary focus
the direct awareness of this loss or deficit. This seems to be the result of a combin-
ation of two factors, namely, the nature of the ‘object’ in this ‘loss of function’ sense
together with the traditional perspective from which this is explored (i.e. as has
been emphasised already, from the perspective of insightlessness or anosognosia) in
neurological states. In other words, because interest in patients’ insight into such
problems arose following the observations that patients seemed to be oblivious to
major impairments (Chapter 4), and because the impairments concerned are of a
relatively clearly defined and objectively evident kind, in terms of loss of ability (e.g.
loss of movement, loss of memory, loss of speech, etc.), this drives the insight phe-
nomenon to focus purely on awareness of the impairment in the narrow sense. If a
neurological loss of function/ability is clearly present, then awareness of not being
able to function in the normal way has to be the imperative focus. If a patient is not
aware of a deficit or disability, then that patient cannot make other judgements
about this. Consequently, the elicited phenomenon of insight has to be structured in
the narrow sense of awareness of the problem. Further judgements concerning the
nature and effects of the problem become irrelevant if the patient is simply not aware
of the loss of function in the first place. Clearly, as was also seen, with further clarifi-
cation around the different natures of the various neurological or neuropsychological
deficits, the phenomena of insight have widened somewhat to include judgements
concerning severity of deficits, impact on functioning, etc. (Sherer et al., 2003a, b), but
the core of the phenomenon determined by such ‘objects’ has necessarily remained
tightly bound to awareness in its narrow sense.
When the ‘object’ of insight assessment refers to ‘subjective mental symptoms’, the
phenomenon of insight demanded by such an ‘object’ has, by definition, a different
structural focus. It is a truism to say that individuals will be aware of ‘subjective
mental symptoms’ (e.g. hallucinations, delusions, depressed mood, preoccupations
with worries, etc.) because that is inherent to the definition of ‘subjective’. Patients
may either complain spontaneously of hearing ‘voices’, of being filmed by the govern-
ment, of feeling low in mood or sad, of being constantly worried by something,
237 The relational aspects of insight: the ‘object ’ of insight assessment
approached from the perspective of insight, e.g. insight into mental symptoms, or
awareness of activities of daily living, or insight into behavioural changes, etc. the
phenomenon of insight that ensues will naturally include additional judgements
relating to the degree or extent of insight held. This will occur irrespective of how
narrow or wide the elicited phenomenon becomes. In other words, from the per-
spective of ‘insight’ (or ‘awareness’), the ‘object’ of insight assessment will demand
a phenomenon that, whether or not taken up in research or empirical terms, incorp-
orates judgements that involve ratings of the insight. For example, exploring
insight into mental symptoms or awareness of memory problems, etc. will deter-
mine a phenomenon of insight based on judgements which can include the extent
of knowledge individuals will have concerning their mental symptoms or their
memory problems. Again, the issue is not whether in empirical terms such know-
ledge is actually sought. The point is, however, that the phenomenon of insight
elicited in relation to this perspective has the potential in terms of its structure to
include such judgements.
On the other hand, when the ‘object’ of insight assessment is approached from
the perspective of ‘insightlessness’, for example, unawareness of mental symptoms,
or anosognosia in relation to hemiplegia or amnesia, etc., the phenomenon of
insight that ensues is generally much more limited or narrower in structure simply
because the other judgements do not follow in the same sort of way. Thus, and as
was mentioned earlier, if an individual has no insight into his/her inability to move
a leg or no insight into the fact that he/she has memory problems, then judgements
concerning degree or extent to which the individual does not know cannot develop.
If a patient does not ‘know’ that he/she is unable to walk, then he/she cannot judge
the effect of this inability. In fact, as we have seen, speaking empirically, judgements
have been incorporated into measures purporting to evaluate ‘unawareness’ or
‘anosognosia’ but in those situations, what is actually being assessed is degree of
awareness and it becomes a purely semantic point. From the theoretical perspective,
however, and borne out by the historical origins of the conceptualisations of insight
(in general psychiatry) and insightlessness (in neurosciences), respectively, the
following observation can be made. The phenomenon of insight determined by
the ‘object’ of insight assessment will be narrower and more circumscribed in
structure when approached from the perspective of insightlessness than when elicited
from the perspective of insight.
It has to be acknowledged that, the dichotomies identified here with respect to the
‘object’ of insight assessment are not operating independently but interact in terms
of their effects on the phenomenon of insight. Separating them as has been done
in this section, however, helps to demonstrate the various different ways in which
the nature of the ‘object’ of insight assessment will influence the structure of the
phenomenon of insight elicited.
241 The relational aspects of insight: the ‘object ’ of insight assessment
7.4 Conclusion
includes wider judgements concerning the nature, meaning and effects of such
experiences on the self.
The relational aspects of insight carry important implications for understand-
ing and research on insight. Most importantly, since clinical phenomena of insight
are determined to some extent by the ‘object’ of insight assessment, then phenom-
ena of insight in relation to different ‘objects’ of insight assessment will vary in
structure and, consequently, will likely involve different underlying mechanisms.
This means that assumptions held concerning equivalence between insight phe-
nomena in relation to different clinical studies will need to be qualified. Similarly,
results of different studies will need to be interpreted in the context of the particu-
lar insight phenomenon under investigation.
8
Various conceptual issues arising in the study of insight have now been identified
and their likely role explored with respect to providing some explanation for the
variable results obtained in empirical work on insight. It is evident that empirical
research on insight faces many difficulties most of which relate to the ways insight
is treated theoretically and to the sense that is made of the clinical phenomenon
elicited. These, in turn, reflect the complexities inherent to the nature of insight as
a concept. It remains crucial, however, notwithstanding the difficulties involved, to
continue with efforts focused on clarifying and understanding the conceptual
problems surrounding the study of insight. The meaningfulness of empirical stud-
ies, i.e. their theoretical significance and clinical importance as well as their limita-
tions, is necessarily dependent on the level of such conceptual understanding.
While the previous chapters focused on unpacking some of these conceptual prob-
lems, these last two chapters aim to bring together the identified points and issues
with a view to developing a basic preliminary structure for the concept of insight.
This chapter focuses on exploring the distinction between awareness and insight,
and determines this as theoretically important and clinically relevant. The next
chapter explores the relationship between awareness and insight in the context of
a proposed overall structure for insight.
In Chapter 1, and following Berrios (1994a; 1996), it was pointed out that terms,
concepts and behaviours do not inevitably correspond in a one-to-one manner to
an object of inquiry. Thus, in order to understand the historical origins and devel-
opment of the object in question, it is necessary to deal with the histories of the
terms, concepts and behaviours independently, before points of convergence can be
considered. This method was followed in the historical Chapter. It is of interest, how-
ever, how the subsequent reviews of empirical studies on insight in different clin-
ical conditions bring this lack of correspondence to a particularly overt focus,
although clearly from a different, i.e. non-historical perspective. This is evidenced
mainly through the use of a range of related terms to variably defined concepts. As
was shown in the previous chapters, the same term could be used to refer to differ-
ent sorts of concepts (e.g. ‘lack of insight’ could refer to both a lack of perception
of a deficit/problem as well as to a lack of an understanding of the nature and
243
244 Conceptual
As mentioned above, setting aside the variable terminology, the literature and
research that was examined in the earlier chapters provide grounds for making a
conceptual division between ‘awareness’ and ‘insight’ as a narrow and wide concep-
tualisation of insight, respectively. In other words, despite the interchangeable use of
terms (including awareness, insight, etc.), two distinct concepts relating to insight
can be identified as running in parallel, albeit, also converging and interacting. The
distinguishing point between these concepts, I will argue, revolves around the nar-
rowness or breadth of the concept involved and, as already stated, the terms ‘aware-
ness’ and ‘insight’ will be used, respectively, from now on, to refer to these specific
245 Awareness and insight: an essential distinction?
senses. The immediate question that arises with respect to this claim, must be what
are the grounds for making this particular distinction? After all, we have seen
throughout the book that in fact, there appear to be numerous distinctions between
the various ways in which insight is conceived and, indeed, this fact has been con-
tinuously discussed and emphasised. However, the point I want to make here is that,
whilst there are many different distinctions proffered in the conceptualisation of
insight, the distinction between ‘awareness’ and ‘insight’ is of unique importance
firstly, because this has direct implications for the structure of insight and, secondly,
because this is essential for understanding the clinical phenomena elicited in rela-
tion to these concepts. In order to substantiate this claim we first need to under-
stand what specifically is meant by a narrow and a wide concept of insight in the
context of the sorts of conceptual distinctions that can be identified. Therefore, it is
important to revisit some of the distinctions that have been made in the literature
between concepts of insight in order to then identify and focus on the features that
differentiate the nature of this particular distinction, i.e. on the ‘narrow’ (as ‘aware-
ness’) and ‘wide’ (as ‘insight’) concept, from other types of distinctions.
Chapter 1 referred to some of the distinctions formulated by the earlier alienists.
For example, amongst patients who seemed to show some insight into their condi-
tion, i.e. those who were aware of the pathological nature of their experiences,
Billod (1870) distinguished between those who, despite this awareness, judged
their psychotic symptoms as ‘real’ and those who judged their psychotic symptoms
as ‘false’, albeit still experiencing distress as a result. Parant (1888) made several
additional distinctions between different forms of insight that patients could show.
These were based on other types of judgements, e.g. judgements concerning the
morality of their actions, judgements that their experiences were pathological, dis-
crepancies between patients’ judgements, their behaviours and so on. Pick (1882),
using the term ‘awareness of illness’ (Krankheitsbewußtsein) conceived a broad
concept of understanding that patients had concerning the pathological nature
of their experiences and divided this further into ‘awareness of feeling ill’
(Krankheitsgefühl) and ‘insight into illness’ (Krankheitseinsicht). In other words, his
distinction was based on changes in feeling in the case of the former and processes
of reason or reflection in the case of the latter. On the other hand, Arndt (1905)
argued for this same distinction (i.e. between awareness of feeling ill and insight
into illness) to be based on the degree of clarity with which the feeling/knowledge
was experienced. Influenced to some extent by Pick, Jaspers (1948) made a distinc-
tion between ‘awareness of illness’ (Krankheitsbewußtsein) and ‘insight proper’
(Krankheitseinsicht). He conceived the former concept as referring to experiences
of feeling ill and changed but without this capturing all symptoms or the illness as
a whole. The latter, on the other hand, referred to a concept which encompassed a
correct assessment made by the patient of the nature and severity of all symptoms
246 Conceptual
together with the illness as a whole affecting him/her. Therefore, it can be seen that
various types of distinctions between concepts of insight were made. Divisions
have been drawn, e.g. between thoughts and feelings (Jaspers, 1948; Pick, 1882),
between thoughts and behaviours (Parant, 1888), between degrees of clarity/detail
in knowledge (Arndt, 1905; Aschaffenburg, 1915) and between specific types of
thoughts/judgements (Billod, 1870; Parant, 1888), etc.
If we move on to the clinical areas of general psychiatry and psychoanalytic psych-
ology, we find that again various distinctions between the concepts of insight have
been made. In general psychiatry, it was pointed out that views of insight ranged
from the more narrow, such as recognition of illness (Wing et al., 1974; Heinrichs
et al., 1985), to much wider concepts which included further judgements demanded
in relation to a variety of aspects of the patient’s experiences (Greenfeld et al., 1989;
David, 1990; Amador et al., 1991; Marková & Berrios, 1992a). The distinctions con-
tained within these various conceptions of insight thus lie around the numbers and
types of judgements involved concerning the patients’ experiences. In some cases the
judgement or acknowledgement of being ‘ill’ was sufficient in itself to constitute
insight and in other cases, additional elaborations concerning views about the nature
of illness or symptoms, the social consequences of the illness, need for treatment, etc.
were necessary to determine insight (Chapter 3). In psychoanalytic psychology, we
have seen that insight has been conceived even more broadly so that the judgements
demanded of individuals in the elicitation of the phenomenon have been more com-
plex. Here, distinctions between such judgements have been made not only with
respect to the different types of judgements, i.e. extent of understanding patients have
of different aspects of their experiences, but also of the ways in which such judge-
ments might be assimilated. Thus, distinctions are made according to whether
knowledge is attained in a relatively more superficial sense (e.g. intellectual, cognitive
or descriptive insight) or whether it is in a relatively deeper sense (e.g. ostensive or
emotional insight, etc.) and according to the extent to which judgements relate to
more ‘hidden’ knowledge including unconscious processes underlying motivations
and actions (Reid & Finesinger, 1952; Richfield, 1954; Chapter 2).
In neurological states (Chapters 4 and 5), we saw that there was a much more
explicitly described polarity between awareness (or unawareness) of neurological
impairment in the narrow sense and denial of impairment in the wider sense. The
former referred to insight as the perception or awareness of the specific impair-
ment and the resultant phenomenon of awareness was thus simply based on
judgements acknowledging the presence of the impairment. On the face of it, this
particular conception of insight is striking in its immediate contrast to the views of
insight seen in the psychiatric literature where even the relatively narrow concep-
tions of insight lacked the clearly-defined and circumscribed boundaries of the
‘neurological’ concept. As was demonstrated, instruments for assessing the clinical
247 Awareness and insight: an essential distinction?
demanded and their relationship to the self, were those relating to subjectivity
(where insight is explored into an experience that by definition incorporates some
awareness), positivity (where insight is explored into the presence of an abnormal
experience) and where the ‘object’ of insight was explored from the perspective of
insight as opposed to insightlessness. Furthermore, where ‘objects’ of insight
assessment referred to a more complex construct (such as ‘mental disorder’), the
phenomenon of insight determined by this ‘object’ was correspondingly broader in
terms of its contained judgements. It is of important note that all these features
relating to the ‘objects’ of insight assessment are those most characteristic of
‘objects’ as defined mainly in psychiatric disciplines. In the neurosciences, on the
other hand, the ‘objects’ of insight assessment are more likely to be objective in
nature (referring to the issue of being determined specifically by tests or a clin-
ician), negative in type (referring to the absence or impairment of normal function)
and approached from the perspective of insightlessness. In turn, such ‘objects’ as
was demonstrated earlier, determine a phenomenon of insight that has to be much
narrower and circumscribed in structure.
stimulus). However, we have seen that ‘narrow’ conceptions of insight have also
been found in the work of the earlier alienists as well as in the empirical research
reviewed in general psychiatry. Therefore, why is the line being drawn between
awareness as construed in the neurosciences and awareness or insight as presented
in the various psychiatric clinical areas?
The answer appears to lie once again in the crucial difference between the ‘objects’
of insight assessment in these respective areas. Even when the most narrow views
of insight within psychiatry are examined (narrow in the sense of being presented
as unitary definitions with no further explication), e.g.‘awareness of emotional prob-
lems’ or ‘recognition of mental illness’, the phenomenon of insight/awareness
demanded by the ‘objects’ in these cases, i.e. ‘emotional problems’ or ‘mental ill-
ness’, will always be wider than the phenomenon of insight/awareness determined
by the ‘objects’ focused on in the neurosciences (i.e. neurological deficits or neuro-
psychological impairments). In other words, and for reasons that were explored in
the previous chapter, whether termed ‘awareness’ or ‘insight’, the phenomenon
sought and elicited within psychiatry (and psychoanalytic psychology) will be con-
stituted of judgements which reach beyond that of an awareness or perception of
‘impairment’. In a sense, awareness or perception of change must, to some extent,
be a given in the conceptualisation of insight within psychiatry (with some qualifi-
cations, see later) but it is, in effect, the subsequent judgements based on this
awareness that constitute insight. This is the case because, again as was demon-
strated in the previous chapter, insight or awareness of, e.g. ‘mental symptoms’, in
reality refers to more than the awareness of the presence of the symptoms (in an
akin manner to the presence of a neurological impairment). In addition, it refers to
awareness of the sense the mental symptoms make to the patient, i.e. of the judge-
ments he/she makes concerning the nature and/or morbidity of the experiences.
Likewise, insight or awareness of having a ‘mental illness’ refers to the judgements
the patient makes in the context of awareness of a variety of subjective experiences.
It is thus these judgements that are determined by the ‘objects’ of insight in psychiatry
that constitute the difference between awareness and insight. In turn, it is the nature
of the differences in ‘objects’ (with respect to the relevant discipline, the category
type and the relative position along the dichotomous dimensions identified earlier,
Chapter 7), determining the presence of such judgements, that fixes this distinction
between awareness and insight. Distinctions between various concepts of insight
identified by the early alienists or those identified in the empirical exploration of
insight in general psychiatry are based on the types of subsequent judgements
made on, already assumed, awareness of experiences. On the other hand, the dis-
tinction between the concept of insight in the neurosciences and the concept of
insight in psychiatry is based on the focus on awareness in the former and focus
on judgements based on awareness in the latter. Awareness may be a necessary
250 Conceptual
negative (i.e. loss or impairment of function) and objective qualities (i.e. directly
evident on observation or tests). Consequently, as far as awareness is concerned,
the focus has to be on the patient’s understanding of the impairment in terms of
the actual observable effects. And, because these observable effects can only be
assessed by means of quantitative measures (frequency of problems experienced,
degree of severity of problem, etc.), then awareness as a phenomenon is elicited
in a quantitative way. Qualitative aspects of awareness are simply not accessible to
the external person (clinician/carer). Hence, no comparisons between patient and
another individual can be made for the purpose of determining the patients’
‘knowledge’ or perception of what is happening to them. The only qualitative fea-
tures that are accessible for the purpose of such comparison are those features that
characterise the impairment itself. As already emphasised previously, the intrinsic
relationship between insight and the ‘object’ of insight assessment means that as
far as the phenomenon of insight or awareness is concerned, the focus of qualita-
tive features will lie on the ‘object’ of awareness in this case rather than on the
‘awareness’ itself. This is not to say that qualitative features of awareness are never
elicited within the neurosciences disciplines. There are many different areas of
clinical experiences where qualitative aspects of awareness are sought specifically,
as in delineating abnormal sensory experiences e.g. phantom limb, or even in char-
acterising various pains. However, the issue in these situations is different. The
qualitative changes in awareness that are explored in these contexts are not carried
out from the perspective of examining the understanding the patient has about a
particular experience but from the perspective of describing and presenting the
particular symptom concerned.
kinds of knowledge. Among these, is the general knowledge (e.g. information from
books, media, peers, etc.), and the personal knowledge held by the individual (e.g. past
experiences in relation to self/others, the degree to which subjective experience is
thought to match the theoretical knowledge/past experiences, etc.), as well as the way
such knowledge is shaped and affected by the individual’s own attitudes (i.e. in terms
of general views of the world, personal biases, cultural perspectives, etc.). Similarly, the
sorts of judgements that might be involved in making the decision concerning the
morbidity of the ‘mental symptom’ will also have to draw on a wide range of mental
activities. These will include a personal/individual interpretation of the subjective
experience, which, in turn, is also likely to be based on a variety of factors (e.g. inten-
sity of subjective experience, difference from ‘normal’ experience, context in which
occurring, past experience, general understanding about mental illness, etc.).
Therefore, the judgements involved in making sense of an experience (whether
this is demanded in terms of ‘mental illness’ or ‘mental symptom’) incorporate a
range of heterogeneous judgements diverse in contents and type, and complexity.
Thus, in contrast to the concept of awareness, the concept of insight, even in a
narrow sense, in relation to psychiatric states, has an inherent qualitative aspect,
which can be addressed in the elicitation of the clinical phenomenon. Patients are
asked to judge in a wider sense what it is that they are experiencing in terms of
what the experience means for them and how this might affect them in their ability
to function and/or relate to others and possible implications for them (e.g. need for
treatment) (Chapter 3). These judgements relate not just to the ‘objective’ charac-
teristics of the problem or experience but to the personal sense the individuals
make of these characteristics and, more directly, to the sense in which the experi-
ence is related to themselves. Consequently, such judgements are by their very
nature qualitative in type, drawing on a wide range of experiences and knowledge
held by the individual and related to the self. Here, in contrast to awareness, it is the
nature of insight in relation to the ‘object’ (mental illness/mental symptoms) that is
being demanded of patients rather than insight in relation to the nature of the ‘object’
(mental illness). Insight, as a phenomenon, is thus assessed both quantitatively
(patients can be said to have no insight, full insight or again a measure/score in
between) and qualitatively (patients can be evaluated on the sorts of judgements
they are expressing). This makes sense given the nature of the ‘object’ of insight
assessment concerned, namely, its positive (presence of an abnormal/different
experience) and its subjective (not accessible in a direct way by the external person)
qualities. Hence, as far as insight is concerned, the focus has to be on the patient’s
understanding of the abnormal experience in terms of what sense the patient
makes of his/her symptoms, how this links up with his/her knowledge and views,
etc. These sorts of judgements are assessed by means of both quantitative (degree
to which patient acknowledges problem) and qualitative (types of judgements
253 Awareness and insight: an essential distinction?
In fact, because ultimately the patient’s views are compared with those of the clin-
ician, in these situations the problems would be formulated in terms of the patient’s
insight rather than the patient’s awareness (even if termed interchangeably). This
shows very obviously that reduced insight is not the same as reduced awareness.
The issue of directionality would seem to be of some importance in also distin-
guishing between the concepts of awareness and insight. Thus, awareness is generally
conceived in terms of a reduction or absence of awareness in relation to a particular
‘object’ (e.g. in relation to memory impairment, to hemiplegia, etc.). When awareness
is conceived or discussed in terms of an increase in awareness, this tends to be a relative
increase from a level of poor awareness, rather than an increase from a ‘normal’ level
of awareness (e.g. patients showing increased awareness of their difficulties/limitations
following rehabilitation, etc.). Other situations when increased awareness may be
conceived include the sorts of clinical experiences where qualitative aspects of aware-
ness are also explored, e.g. some of the brain stimulation studies or various forms of
epilepsy, but again here the focus is not on the understanding a patient is showing in
relation to his/her experiences but on the nature of the experience itself.
Insight, on the other hand, tends to be more easily conceived as increasing as
well as decreasing with respect to a ‘normal’ level. This difference between the two
concepts is likely to be due to a number of factors. Firstly, the clinical backgrounds
relating to these concepts are important. Awareness, in the neurosciences has tended
to be modelled along neurological and neuropsychological frames in which ‘aware-
ness systems’ (generalised or inherent to specific cognitive functions) are seen as
structures or functions which can ‘go wrong’ in the same sort of way that other
cognitive functions do. Thus, whilst it is conceivable that an awareness structure or
function can become damaged by some brain lesion or disease, it is much more
difficult to think of the same structure or function becoming enhanced in some
way (without invoking the use of some specific stimulatory techniques akin to
those used to enhance other aspects of cognitive function). The clinical background
of insight in its broad conceptualisation is, as we have seen, very different and, in
various ways, the psychiatric disciplines, psychoanalytic psychology and indeed
Gestalt psychology all contribute to determining the potential for the concept of
insight to increase as well as decrease from a ‘normal’ level. From the perspective of the
psychiatric and psychoanalytic psychologies, this seems to relate to the issue of the
complexity and of the judgements involved in constituting insight and the fact
that, as was discussed earlier (Chapter 6), there is no clearly defined boundary to
the different types and qualities of knowledge that can be held in relation to differ-
ent ‘objects’. Thus, there is always the possibility or potential for increasing insight,
even from a ‘normal’ level. In the case of Gestalt psychology, we saw that insight
was conceived very much in terms of newly acquired knowledge, and hence,
involved an increase in capacity to solve particular problems.
256 Conceptual
Having explored some of the theoretical reasons for making a distinction between
awareness as a narrow concept and insight as a broad concept, let us consider an
empirical study that may help illustrate some of the issues raised. The study is
257 Awareness and insight: an essential distinction?
described in detail elsewhere (Marková et al., 2004) and here only the salient
aspects are presented and discussed. Essentially, the study was designed to explore
insight into memory problems in a heterogeneous group of patients attending
a memory clinic, i.e. in patients presenting with memory problems of various
aetiologies. Crucially, such aetiologies spanned both ‘organic’ (e.g. neurological,
mainly dementia) and ‘non-organic’ (e.g. depression, anxiety and others) factors.
Hence, this study contrasted from previous studies which tended to focus on the
exploration of insight in relation to either memory problems in dementias (e.g.
Verhey et al., 1993; Seltzer et al., 1995a; Duke et al., 2002; Chapter 5) or amnesic
syndromes (e.g. Schacter, 1991; 1992; Chapter 4) but did not, generally, cut across
the organic/non-organic categories.
The more specific aim of the Marková et al. (2004) study was to compare insight
between patients with an organic basis (i.e. neurological pathology) and patients
without an organic basis (i.e. no neurological pathology) to their memory prob-
lems. This perspective was taken in the light of some of the conceptual problems
around insight raised earlier. Thus, in order to circumvent some of the identified
preconceptions resulting from the conventional conceptualisations of insight in
neurological/neuropsychological and the psychiatric disciplines, patients’ insight
was explored, in a sense, independently of the cause of the memory problem. All
patients presented with memory complaints; and thus ‘memory complaints’ were
chosen as the ‘object’ of insight assessment. By using the same instrument to assess
insight across the diagnostic categories (i.e. loosely, ‘organic’ and ‘non-organic’),
and applying the same ‘object’ of insight assessment (‘memory complaints’), the
intention was to compare insight manifested between the patient groups and assess
whether the phenomena of insight shared common patterns and hence could be
‘explained’ in terms of a single concept of insight or whether different patterns
emerged and needed reference to more than one concept.
a
t-test for independent samples.
b
Chi-squared.
S.D.: Standard Deviation.
Table 8.2 Neurological and psychiatric groups compared on main psychiatric measurements
a
References for psychiatric measures are in text.
b
Bonferroni corrected.
3 negative discrepancy values – indicating that the patient’s memory problem was
evaluated as more severe by the patient than the carer (i.e. poor insight).
Table 8.3 Neurological and psychiatric groups compared on main neuropsychological measurements
a
References for the neuropsychological tests are in text.
b
Bonferroni corrected.
c
Raw scores have been age adjusted to give scale scores (Warrington) and percentiles (Wechsler).
Table 8.4 Comparison of total insight scores (as functions of discrepancy values on the MIQ) between
neurological patients and psychiatric patients
a
Bonferroni corrected.
To take account of the direction of the discrepancies, the sum of the positive and
negative discrepancies were separately calculated for each patient. Results are
shown in Table 8.4.
The results show that there is no significant difference in the total discrepancy
scores between the patient groups. However, the neurological patients show sig-
nificantly more positive discrepancies than the psychiatric patients and, conversely,
the psychiatric patients show more negative discrepancies than the neurological
patients. This indicates that the neurological patients evaluated their memory
problems as less severe than their carers whereas, the psychiatric patients evaluated
their memory problems as more severe than their carers.
Table 8.6 Neurological and psychiatric patients compared on insight scores in relation to
the four areas on the MIQ: general, memory, language and cognitive
to evaluate their language function as more severely impaired than their carers did.
In quantitative terms, both groups showed similar degrees of impaired insight (i.e.
no significant difference in size of discrepancies) in each area.
framework in this context would mean that one would have to consider such
‘hyperawareness’ as arising on the basis of some sort of stimulation of a generalised
awareness system or a specific module-linked awareness function.
Therefore, the issue arising from this study is primarily concerned with the
question of whether using a single concept or model will help to explain the dif-
ferent types of impaired insight seen in the patients or whether it makes more
sense to view the impairment of insight in each patient group as reflecting, to some
extent, different concepts. In fact, it is difficult to conceive of a unified model that
could ‘explain’ in a plausible way both the ‘reduced awareness’ shown in one group
of patients and the so-called ‘increased awareness’ shown in the other. I would con-
tend that the two phenomena obtained in the different patient groups reflect the
distinction, that has been argued for in this chapter, between awareness in the nar-
row sense and insight in the broad sense.
One further question that could be asked is, given that the same assessment
instrument was used in both groups of patients and that the same ‘object’ of
insight was being addressed, why should the two elicited phenomena of insight
reflect two distinct concepts? Here, it is once again important to look properly at
the ‘object’ of insight assessment. Although the ‘object’ of insight assessment in this
study was ostensibly ‘memory complaints’, it is clear in fact that the actual ‘object’
of insight assessment was different in each patient group. In the ‘neurological’
group, the ‘object’ of insight assessment had to be ‘memory dysfunction’ (because
comparisons were made with ‘abnormal’ results on psychometric testing). On the
other hand, in the ‘psychiatric’ group, the ‘object’ of insight assessment was ‘mem-
ory function’ (because here comparisons were made with ‘normal’ results on psy-
chometric testing). Hence, it makes sense that the different ‘objects’ played their
part in determining the specific phenomenon of insight involved.
The study thus highlights that patients whose memory problems arise from
different causes, manifest different types of impaired insight. This issue would
not necessarily emerge if the patient groups were studied independently. In that
situation, one study would show the ‘neurological’ patients as having poor insight
(or awareness) and likewise another study would show ‘psychiatric’ patients as
having poor insight (or awareness). The possibility of different ‘types’ of mani-
fested impaired insight might not follow in the same way. However, our study
design allowed for the emergence of these two distinct phenomena of impaired
insight (underestimation and overestimation of problems) and consequently
these needed explaining. The implications arising from this finding lie in ques-
tioning the assumption of equivalence between different insight phenomena.
Clearly, the types of impaired insight shown by the patient groups are different
and are likely to be underpinned by different mechanisms. It would make little
sense to search for a common neurobiology (e.g. brain localisation of impaired
267 Awareness and insight: an essential distinction?
insight) of poor insight in both cases. In crude terms, the phenomenon of aware-
ness and the phenomenon of insight are likely to be organised differently in the
brain.
At this point, it is important to stress another issue, in part arising from
the results of this study but one that also may have been misconstrued from the
analysis and justification for the distinction between awareness and insight
made earlier in this chapter. Much of the argument presented for making this dis-
tinc-tion was based on highlighting some of the explicit differences in conceptual-
isations of awareness/insight as explored in the neurosciences and those as
explored in more general psychiatry and psychoanalytic psychology. Here, I want
to emphasise that this was not intended to mean that exploration of awareness in
the narrow sense was exclusive to the neurosciences disciplines and that explo-
ration of insight in the broad sense was exclusive to clinical psychiatric disciplines.
The differences in the way in which insight has been approached and explored in
the different disciplines simply help to illustrate in a particularly overt way the dis-
tinction that is argued for between the narrow and wide concepts of insight.
However, it is a conceptual distinction, a differentiation that is made between two
concepts on the basis of some identified specific differences in meaning. At the
same time, whilst they are distinct, it is clear that they have features in common
and that they interact in particular ways. I have touched upon this already and
in the next chapter I shall examine the structural relationship between awareness
and insight in some detail. In practical terms, it is clear that exploration of aware-
ness/insight in patients is a mixed or combined enterprise in the sense that, gener-
ally, clinicians may evaluate aspects of both awareness and insight in patients.
Patients with various neurological/neuropsychological impairments, depending
on the ‘object’ of insight assessment as well as on the degree of awareness held, may
be asked about their views and judgements concerning the changes in a wider
sense than those captured by ‘awareness’. Hence, insight will be assessed as a com-
bination of both awareness and insight. Similarly, in psychiatry, patients may be
asked about signs (e.g. tardive dyskinesia) of which they may be ‘unaware’, i.e.
they simply are not perceiving in a direct sense the ‘object’ that is observable to
others. Hence, the phenomenon of insight elicited in relation to such ‘objects’
will in fact relate more closely to the narrow concept of awareness rather than to
insight. Likewise, in the study described above, whilst both patient groups manifest
impaired insight predominantly of the one type, the results show a mixture of
both positive and negative discrepancies in both groups (see Table 8.5). In other
words, both patient groups at some points overestimate their memory problems
and at other points underestimate their difficulties. Whilst one has to consider here
also the contribution to the ‘insight score’ from the carers in terms of the accuracy
of their judgements of patients’ problems, it is also likely that combinations of
268 Conceptual
awareness and insight (i.e. wider judgements based on awareness) are elicited in
both patient groups.
8.3 Conclusion
(i.e. perceiving a change in the first place or, in other words, being aware of a change)
but then making sense of this with respect to themselves and their experiences
(hence the wider judgements involved). Since perceiving a change (i.e. awareness
of some change in mental state) is inherent to the articulation of subjective com-
plaints, then awareness, whilst a necessary component of insight in psychiatric dis-
ciplines, is not always a sufficient component of insight in these areas.
The clinical phenomena of awareness and insight share some characteristics but
also have distinguishing features which help to determine in practical terms the
division between awareness and insight. Both are phenomena that can be captured
in quantitative terms, i.e. patients can show different degrees or extents of aware-
ness and of insight. However, they differ in the source or focus of the qualitative
features that are captured in clinical assessments. In the case of awareness, the
focus of qualitative aspects determined by awareness measures is directed at the
‘object’ of awareness. In other words, patients are assessed in terms of awareness in
relation to the qualitative aspects of the ‘object’ (e.g. the severity of an impairment,
frequency with which the deficit interferes with function, etc.). In the case of
insight, the focus of qualitative aspects determined by insight measures is directed
at the phenomenon of insight itself. In other words, patients are assessed in terms
of qualitative aspects of insight (i.e. different types of judgements held concerning,
e.g. the nature of their experiences, whether these represent illness, in what way the
experiences impact on their lives, etc.) in relation to the ‘object’. In the previous
chapter, the phenomenon of insight was proposed to be linked intrinsically with
the ‘object’ of insight assessment, though, analysing the way in which the ‘object’ of
insight assessment shaped the phenomenon of insight necessitated an artificial
separation. The point however was that as far as the structure of the phenomenon
of insight was concerned, the ‘object’ and the phenomenon were bound in a
bi-directional relationship. Therefore, structurally the qualitative aspects of aware-
ness are focused on the ‘object’ whereas the qualitative aspects of insight are
focused on the phenomenon.
Another feature helping to differentiate the phenomenon of awareness from the
phenomenon of insight is directionality. The quantitative assessment of awareness
is generally described in terms of greater and lesser degrees but these degrees are all
subsumed below an implicit ‘normal’ level of awareness. We can say that patients
have reduced awareness of an impairment or they may show increased awareness
following, e.g. rehabilitation, but there is not a situation where patients are
expected to show greater levels of awareness than so-called ‘normal’ levels in rela-
tion to an impairment. In contrast, the phenomenon of insight has the potential for
both a reduction below ‘normal’ and an increase above ‘normal’ levels.
The distinction highlighted between awareness and insight is crucially important
because it provides a means of understanding the way in which different clinical
270 Conceptual
Throughout this work emphasis has been placed on the range of meanings of
insight evident in the research and contributing to the variety of approaches taken
to assess insight in patients with different clinical conditions. Within the range
of meanings of insight a crucial distinction has been made between insight in its
narrowest meaning as awareness i.e. the direct simplest perception of a particular
stimulus/state affecting the individual and insight in its wider sense as self-
knowledge, i.e. involving more complex judgements made by individuals concern-
ing a particular state. Furthermore, it has been stressed that these latter judgements
depend on, and relate to, an initial awareness of a particular state (though there are
271
272 Conceptual
Figure 9.1 The structure of insight. A schematic representation of the structure for insight: central
sphere represents core awareness and arrows represent judgements issuing from
awareness of experience
273 Towards a structure of insight: the relationship between awareness and insight
state and as such there are no clearly defined limits to the numbers and types of
judgements that can be invoked (see Chapter 6). Thus, as was seen in studies explor-
ing insight in patients with psychoses, a wide variety of judgements demanded of
patients concerning their experiences have been viewed as constitutive of insight.
For example, researchers have included patients’ views on the nature of their experi-
ences, their judgements as to whether such experiences are pathological, their ideas
on how the experiences affect their functioning or their relationship with others,
their opinions on medication and other forms of treatment, etc. (refer to Chapter 3).
In addition, apart from the range of types of judgements that can constitute insight,
the level of knowledge required for ‘complete’ insight is far from clear and this
again contributes to the lack of clear boundaries around the structure. What level
of understanding should patients have of their illness or experiences? Do they need
to know the details of the problems? To what degree do individuals need to judge
the effects of their experiences on themselves and on the way they perceive and
interact with their external environment? It can be seen that the sorts of judge-
ments that can be made in relation to a particular clinical state (illness, symptoms,
normal experiences, etc.) are infinite and ultimately for clinical/research purposes
will have to be determined and limited by clinicians or researchers themselves.
In contrast, awareness is conceived as a more circumscribed concept. In clinical
terms, patients are viewed as having or not having awareness or having various
degrees of awareness of a particular state. Assessments of awareness are limited to
capturing its quantitative aspects. Qualitative aspects of awareness are, as described
in Chapter 8, directed at the ‘object’ of awareness and as such are constituted by the
attributes of the particular object. This means that awareness itself in comparison
to insight as a whole has more clearly defined boundaries.
It is important to emphasise at this point that the schematic representation of
the basic structure of insight is intended to portray a potential basic structure. In
other words, it is the concept of insight that is represented, i.e. insight as has been
conceptualised within the clinical disciplines from the narrowest to the widest of
theoretical conceptions. As is shown in Figure 1, the outward limits, in terms of the
possible judgements that can constitute insight as a theoretical concept, cannot be
properly demarcated. As a potential structure of insight, however, it provides a the-
oretical framework against which clinical phenomena of insight can be understood
and positioned and delineated as described below.
If the basic structure of insight can be represented as constituted by core aware-
ness underpinning a multiplex of judgements, where does the phenomenon of insight
fit in? The phenomenon of insight has already been defined as referring to that aspect
of insight that is manifested or elicited clinically. It has also been shown that it would
be impractical to think that the phenomenon could capture everything that might
be entailed by the concept of insight. As such, the phenomenon of insight might be
274 Conceptual
Figure 9.2 The basic phenomenon of insight (first level). A schematic representation of the structure
for insight: central sphere represents core awareness; arrows represent judgements
issuing from awareness of experience; and stippled triangle represents phenomenon of
insight
275 Towards a structure of insight: the relationship between awareness and insight
Figure 9.3 The phenomenon of insight (second level). A schematic representation of the structure for
insight: central sphere represents core awareness; arrows represent judgements issuing
from awareness of experience; bi-directional arrows represent interactional effects of
clinician, type of ‘insight’ measure chosen, interview situation, other external individual,
etc.; stippled triangle represents phenomenon of insight; and superimposed triangle
represents ‘new’ phenomenon of insight incorporating changes as a result of the
interactional effects
to share a similar form, then, it could be argued, that this might impose a common
structure to these judgements irrespective of their specific contents. This would be
much in the way that delusions are generally considered as sharing a basic struc-
ture irrespective of their contents and, likewise, obsessional thoughts, auditory hal-
lucinations, etc. To briefly clarify, the structure of a symptom or mental phenomenon
refers to its theoretical framework whilst the form and content have traditionally
referred to the clinical representation of symptoms/mental phenomena (Marková &
Berrios, 1995c). Thus, ‘content’ can be defined as the actual substance of the symp-
tom whereas ‘form’ relates to the modality or medium in which the content is
expressed, such as feeling, perception, thought, etc. (Jaspers, 1948). This is not the
place to explore this issue in detail (and caveats would be needed in specific clin-
ical areas, such as psychoanalytic psychology, where the structure of mental symp-
toms might be considered as dependent on symptom contents as much as their
form). Certainly there are theoretical arguments against this view in that the judge-
ments considered here are not unitary phenomena but a heterogeneous group
which are constituted primarily from secondary judgements. Such secondary judge-
ments are themselves complexes based on a range of other judgements, on various
types of beliefs, on associated feelings, on past experiences, on general knowledge,
attitudes and so on. Thus, although at a clinical level the judgements can be said to
differ in content, this content in turn is dependent on a multitude of mental phe-
nomena which themselves differ in form and content. In other words, there are
theoretical grounds for suggesting that differences in phenomena of insight (in the
broad sense) may be structurally meaningful. However, this issue, as well as that
concerning the location of possible distinctions between judgements, to some extent
remains to be determined empirically. It is highlighted here simply to illustrate that
the nature of differences between phenomena of insight distinguished on the basis of
judgements may be of a different order to the differences in phenomena which are
distinguished on the basis of ‘awareness’ on the one hand and ‘awareness and judge-
ments’ (insight in broader sense) on the other (see below).
As was argued in Chapter 8, the distinction between the phenomenon of aware-
ness and the phenomenon of insight is based on a more striking structural differ-
ence between ‘awareness’ (as a direct perception of an ‘object’) and ‘insight’ (as
‘awareness’ together with the secondary judgements based on the awareness). It is
important, therefore, to examine, in relation to the outlined insight structure, the
determinants of phenomena of insight whose structures focus either on awareness
or on insight in the wider sense. Understanding the ways in which awareness and
insight are determined in this context may help to clarify their relationship in more
detail. Following the argument developed in Chapter 7 concerning the crucial role
of the ‘object’ of insight assessment in determining the clinical phenomenon of
insight, the structure of the phenomenon of insight will be examined in relation to
278 Conceptual
different types of ‘objects’ of insight assessment. For the purposes here, this will
be limited to three types of ‘objects’ of insight assessment, namely, (i) subjective
mental states, (ii) loss or impairment of function, and (iii) specific diagnostic
constructs (e.g. mental illness).
Figure 9.4 The phenomenon of insight in relation to ‘subjective mental states’. A schematic
representation of the structure for insight; central sphere represents core awareness;
arrows represent judgements issuing from awareness of experience; stippled triangle
represents phenomenon of insight; and pale triangle within the stippled triangle
represents the awareness that is intrinsic to, and hence inseparable from, the
subjective state itself
him/herself as feeling happy may describe this as feeling good and bright. In this
sense, he/she is interpreting an awareness of a particular mental state and giving it
a specific name, i.e. happiness. At this stage, the individual would be described as
reporting a subjective mental state but it is unlikely this would be termed insight.
Similarly, a patient complaining of people plotting against him and being unable to
accept evidence to the contrary would be described as reporting a subjective fear/
worry that was not amenable to reasoning (and the clinician might then describe
this as a delusional belief). However, the reporting of the worry on the part of the
patient would not, in itself, be viewed as insightful even though the patient is
reporting this on the basis of an awareness of some change in his/her mental state.
In other words, in both these cases, the reporting of subjective states whilst, by def-
inition, are indicative of awareness of particular changes in mental state, is not suf-
ficient for determining insight. The phenomenon of insight would demand, in
both these examples, further judgements concerning the nature and effects of the
articulated subjective state. In the case of the individual reporting feeling happy,
elicitation of insight into the happiness might, for example, involve judgements
concerning how the happiness affects him/her in terms of general feelings, in terms
280 Conceptual
have been put forward in relation to specific individual symptoms (e.g. Garety &
Hemsley, 1994). However, from the perspective of making sense of psychopath-
ology as a whole, in terms of understanding the ways in which symptoms/signs
may develop, the factors affecting these, the assumptions that need to be taken into
account and the extents and limits to which different types of approaches help
acquire such knowledge, much research remains to be done. It is in this context
that further understanding concerning the sort of factors and likely mechanisms
underlying impairment of insight in relation to pathological mental states might
be developed.
Thirdly, and relating to this, there is little knowledge so far concerning the effects
of mental illness as a whole on the judgements made relating to insight. In other
words, in spite of the numerous empirical studies exploring the relationship between
levels of insight and illness/disease variables (refer to Chapters 3–5), the contribu-
tion of the illness itself on different types of judgements has not been clarified. The
situation is different as regards awareness, or insight in its narrow sense (see below),
where research has, with greater validity, indicated some association between
impaired awareness and neurological and/or neurocognitive dysfunction (e.g.
Prigatano, 1991; Derouesné et al., 1999). However, in terms of insight in its wider
sense, i.e. in terms of the relationship between specific judgements relating to
insight and the mental illness itself, then at present little is known. For example,
does having schizophrenia or bipolar affective disorder or a delusional disorder
affect the way in which individuals think about themselves, does it affect percep-
tions concerning themselves and their functioning, are perhaps only some types of
judgements affected or is there a pervasive influence on reasoning? Thus, the ori-
ginal question as posed by the early alienists and echoed by subsequent researchers,
as to whether and/or to what extent a ‘disordered’ mind can judge its own prob-
lems has not yet been answered.
comparison between the patient’s perception of his/her ability to move and direct
observation of the patient’s movements. Depending on the degree of awareness
held by the patients in relation to such dysfunction, further judgements can be
demanded, generally relating to observable or measurable features of the dysfunc-
tion itself, such as severity of the problem, the frequency with which it causes dif-
ficulties, etc. Clearly, where patients lack complete awareness of the dysfunction,
further judgements cannot be determined.
The phenomenon of insight determined by ‘objects’ of insight assessment relat-
ing to ‘objective dysfunction’ (i.e. loss/impairment of function), therefore, whilst
comprising both structurally and clinically of awareness and insight in its wider
sense, is focused predominantly on awareness, i.e. on insight in its narrow sense.
This results in a more circumscribed phenomenon whose boundaries are fixed by
the limits imposed by quantitative assessment. Patients will have either awareness
of say, a hemiplegia or dyskinesia, or reduced or absent awareness of the same. The
concept of increased awareness, i.e. beyond ‘normal’ awareness does not apply
because the external verification of the dysfunction is carried out quantitatively
and has a finite limit. And, awareness is judged on the basis of a comparison with
this external verification. Thus, a patient who is unable to move a leg can state that
he/she cannot move a leg thus displaying awareness of this problem. Alternatively,
the patient may say that he/she has some difficulty in moving a leg, indicating
reduced awareness of the problem and finally, the patient could say that he/she
is able to move the leg normally, suggesting absent awareness (anosognosia).
However, the patient would not be described as having increased awareness of the
problem. Qualitative assessment of awareness, from the point of view of eliciting
patients’ understanding of a dysfunction, is not ‘measurable’ simply because there
is no external concomitant. Thus, to reinforce the argument from Chapter 8, quali-
tative descriptions around the phenomenon of awareness in relation to dysfunc-
tions are constrained to characterising the dysfunctions themselves. These features
characterising the phenomenon of awareness together with the relative lack of
judgements elaborated in the wider sense suggest that the structure of this phe-
nomenon in relation to verifiable dysfunction might lend itself more easily to
research seeking to explore the neurobiology of awareness.
‘objects’ of insight assessment. In other words, and again, as was argued earlier,
because of these ‘extra’ elements contained within ‘diagnostic constructs’, then in
contrast to the previous ‘objects’ of insight assessment, there is not the same one-
to-one relationship between the ‘diagnostic construct’ and its determinable mani-
festation. Eliciting insight into persecutory delusions relates to judgements patients
are making about a particular mental state they are experiencing. Similarly, eliciting
insight into memory dysfunction relates to judgements patients make about an
‘overt’ or ‘objectively determined’ problem. Eliciting insight into schizophrenia,
however, may require judgements not only of particular mental experiences and/or
problems the patient may be having but also judgements made in relation to a con-
cept that, through its social, cultural and political elements, may be quite distant to
a personal experience. In fact, different sorts of insight phenomena may be deter-
mined by such a construct.
One sort of phenomenon may be elicited where the focus is on the judgements
made by patients based on the sum of individual abnormal mental experiences
thought to be the symptoms and signs of illness. For example, some approaches to
assessing insight in patients with schizophrenia include questions concerning
whether the ‘abnormal’ experiences they are having are the result of mental illness
(e.g. Amador et al., 1991). This can again be represented schematically as in Figure 9.6.
Figure 9.6 shows three triangles extending from the core awareness and incorp-
orating wider judgements. These represent the same sorts of phenomena of insight
that are obtained in relation to subjective mental states (i.e. comprising of both
awareness of a particular mental state, as inherent to the subjective mental state,
and judgements based on this awareness) (Figure 9.4). In addition, these phenom-
ena reach out to a larger stippled triangle which represents judgements that are
based on other information (i.e. not on awareness itself) in terms of general
knowledge, personal views and biases, individual experiences, etc. relating to the
wider elements of the construct. In other words, the composite phenomenon of
insight in relation to schizophrenia in this case becomes constituted of both per-
sonal and more general judgements. As was the case in relation to the phenomenon
of insight determined by subjective mental states, structurally this composite phe-
nomenon is constituted of both awareness and insight in the wider sense and,
clinically, the phenomenon is composed of a multitude of judgements ranging in
complexity. In contrast, however, to the phenomenon of insight determined by
subjective mental states, this phenomenon also includes judgements which are not
purely based on awareness of a particular mental state but are based, in addition,
on the individual’s general knowledge and opinions about the ‘object’ in question.
It could be argued that these latter judgements are likewise important in the for-
mation of the insight phenomenon in relation to subjective mental states. Indeed,
these sorts of factors were raised earlier as likely to influence the sorts of judgements
285 Towards a structure of insight: the relationship between awareness and insight
held by patients concerning the nature and effects of subjective mental states.
However, the difference in this case is that, whilst it is likely the factors will inter-
act, there is in addition the added element that perhaps more of the wider judge-
ments which are elicited will be unrelated to the patient’s actual experience. This
can be illustrated further by examining another sort of phenomenon of insight
that might be determined by a construct such as ‘mental illness’.
For example, other approaches to assessing insight in patients with schizophre-
nia include questions which ask the patients directly whether they think they are
suffering from a mental illness (e.g. David, 1990). This could result in a somewhat
different phenomenon of insight as illustrated in Figure 9.7.
Figure 9.7 shows a phenomenon of insight, represented by the stippled triangle,
that is composed entirely of different sorts of judgements in relation to the con-
struct but there is no relationship to any sort of awareness of a mental state or
experienced problem. In other words, and in qualification to what has been said
earlier, in some situations, the phenomenon of insight in the wider sense may not
be dependent on awareness of a particular state. For example, it is possible that a
286 Conceptual
patient with schizophrenia may not ‘feel’ ill in any way or may not perceive that
he/she has particular problems and, yet, the patient may judge on the basis of
information given to him/her by others that he/she is suffering from schizophre-
nia. This could be considered similar to the situation where patients with, for
example, silent or asymptomatic cancer are diagnosed with the condition (and
given information about it including management and prognosis), and acknow-
ledge that they have the disease, understand the effects this may have on their life
and the implications for treatment again without necessarily feeling ill in any way.
The phenomena of insight determined by ‘objects’ of insight assessment relating
to diagnostic constructs can therefore be of different kinds. Some will be similar to
the phenomena of insight elicited in relation to subjective mental states and thus
comprise structurally of awareness and insight in its wider sense though clinically
only in insight in its wider sense. Others will comprise both structurally and clin-
ically only of insight in its wider sense and, because of this, clinically the judgements
formed in relation to the construct will not be based on awareness of a particular
287 Towards a structure of insight: the relationship between awareness and insight
state (i.e. relating to experience of components of the construct) but will be based
on other sources of information.
insight is concerned, the distinction between awareness and insight may help to direct
such research in particular areas. For example, the structural differences between
awareness and insight highlighted by the schematic representation of insight suggest
more than that the processes underlying awareness and insight are different. Instead,
the implication is also drawn that whilst awareness can be represented by a relatively
circumscribed and contained structure, by contrast, insight is conceived as a structure
whose boundaries are undefined and whose content encompasses limitless judge-
ments. The arguments supporting this structural distinction were expounded earlier
when the characteristics of the respective phenomena were delineated, for example,
in terms of qualitative and quantitative aspects, directionality, etc. (refer to Chapter 8).
The proposed insight structure however shows this difference in an explicit albeit
simplistic way. From this, though, it follows that research aiming to explore possible
brain representation or neurobiology of insight might more usefully focus on aware-
ness rather than on insight in its wider sense. In other words, it would seem to be a
more legitimate enterprise to be exploring associations between brain function and a
structure that, because of its circumscribed nature, is not only more reliably accessed
but is also likely to be underpinned by a common and consistent mechanism.
Secondly, again from the perspective of research into brain representation, and
following from the above, it makes sense to concentrate on eliciting phenomena
which are constituted primarily by ‘awareness’ as opposed to ‘insight’. To this end,
the dependency of insight phenomena on their ‘object’ of insight assessment indi-
cates that exploring insight in relation to, for example, ‘objective’ dysfunction will
determine a phenomenon that will more meaningfully lend itself to such correl-
ational research. On the other hand, exploring insight in relation to ‘subjective men-
tal states’ or to ‘diagnostic constructs’ will determine phenomena that are constituted
mainly by the wider judgements pertaining to insight and, as such, are unlikely to
associate consistently with a specific neuronal system.
Apart from research into the neurobiology of insight, the structure of insight
carries implications for research on insight in psychiatry in other directions. In
particular, it is evident that much research is needed to develop further under-
standing around the nature of phenomena of insight in the wider sense. Here, as
indicated earlier, many questions need exploring both from a theoretical perspec-
tive but also by empirical means. For example, it seems plausible, though needs
empirical testing, that some insight phenomena, based on particular types of judge-
ments, might be of more predictive value, in terms of prognosis or quality of life,
than other insight phenomena. Similarly, it might be that phenomena of insight
based on different judgements may be clinically important or useful in different ways.
Again this would need addressing empirically. Other questions alluded to earlier
concern the possibility of further distinguishing between different insight phenom-
ena. In other words, might there be some validity in making further distinctions
290 Conceptual
between insight phenomena based on the types and contents of judgements involved?
In a different vein, but crucially, research into insight might usefully concentrate on
exploring the factors that might be important in the formation of the judgements
that constitute insight. For example, one important focus here might concern distin-
guishing between ‘illness’ factors (e.g. current mood, past experience of similar states,
cognitive problems) and non-illness factors (e.g. cultural, social and environmental
influences). In addition, and as mentioned earlier, research may need to address
the question of ‘symptom’ formation, i.e. look at developing models for the ways in
which mental symptoms may arise and be expressed.
contribute to the resultant structure of the elicited insight phenomenon. Once again
the grounds for this have been put forward previously (Chapter 6) but the
schematic representation of insight helps to bring this out in a more explicit way.
In turn, this helps to understand the factors likely to influence the assessment of
insight and expression of insight in a clinical setting.
Third, the schematic representation of insight and the phenomenon of insight
situated against this framework highlight the descriptive nature of this model.
In other words, the structure of insight, both as a concept and phenomenon, is
depicted in terms of its possible and potential constituents and their likely interre-
lationships. On the other hand, mechanisms postulated to underlie changes in
insight, such as denial in its psychodynamic sense or specific neuronal dysfunction
or others, have to be addressed separately. The essential point, however, is that
exploration of such mechanisms are necessarily dependent on an understanding of
the insight phenomenon at its descriptive level.
Knowledge concerning the determinants of insight phenomena also carries
implications for further research. Thus, understanding about the way in which dif-
ferent ‘objects’ of insight assessment can determine a particular phenomenon of
insight allows for a clearer appreciation of the structure of the phenomenon that is
elicited. In turn, from a research perspective, this allows for more valid compari-
sons between phenomena of insight elicited in studies within and between clinical
areas. Furthermore, it also enables researchers to choose and devise measures which,
on theoretical grounds, can most usefully assess the particular phenomenon under
study. Likewise, understanding about the contribution of judgements made by clin-
icians, instruments and the interactive situation towards the formation of the
clinical phenomenon of insight allows for a clearer appreciation of the structure of
the insight phenomenon elicited. Again this is important from a research perspec-
tive as such factors may be important to take into account when exploring insight
in patients and when making comparisons between different insight phenomena.
In addition, this is an area where empirical work would be useful in order to help
determine the levels and types of influence possessed by different insight measures.
Such knowledge, in turn, would be important once again for choosing a particular
method of assessing patients’ insight in different clinical situations.
9.3 Conclusion
in relation to any self-experience, awareness forms the core around which insight,
in terms of more complex and elaborate judgements, is constructed. Although
judgements forming the wider structure of insight are shown as independent
entities issuing from the core awareness, it is understood that this is an oversimpli-
fication and that relevant judgements are elaborated not only on the basis of
awareness but on the basis of and interaction with other judgements. For the pur-
poses here, the crucial issue is the fundamental distinction between awareness
and insight. Whether subsequent distinctions between different levels of judge-
ments are possible is a matter for further theoretical and empirical research.
The structure provides a framework against which clinical phenomena of insight
can be defined and delineated. Different ‘objects’ of insight assessment determine
phenomena of insight that differ structurally and clinically mainly on account of
the relative proportion of awareness and further judgements in their constitution.
The structure provides the space to show the added contribution of external fac-
tors (i.e. in terms of clinician/measure contribution) to the determination of the
insight phenomenon. The focus on the ‘object’ of insight assessment allows the
external factors contributing to the phenomenon of insight to be considered more
specifically in relation to the nature of the ‘object’ itself. In these ways, the structure
of insight helps to organise understanding about clinical phenomena of insight
explored in different clinical situations. In addition, it helps to identify areas where
research may usefully focus.
The relationship between awareness and insight is evidently not straightforward
and it has been argued here that the terms are not synonymous. Individuals are
able to have at the same time poor awareness and good insight and conversely good
awareness together with poor insight. The structural distinction between aware-
ness and insight suggests that research aimed at exploring the nature and correlates
of insight needs to make a like distinction since different approaches to such study
may be required in each case.
References
Abramowitz, S.I. & Abramowitz, C.Z. (1974) Psychological-mindedness and benefit from
insight-oriented group therapy. Archives of General Psychiatry, 30, 610–615.
Abrams, S. (1981) Insight. The Teiresian gift. In The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, Eds.
A.J. Solnit, R.S. Eissler, A. Freud, M. Kris & P.B. Neubauer, vol. 36. New Haven: Yale University
Press, pp. 289–305.
Ackerknecht, E.H. (1967) Medicine at the Paris Hospital 1794–1848. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
Press.
Adelung, T. (1811) Grammatisch-Kritisches Wörterbuch der hohdeutschen Mundart. Vienna: Bauer.
Agnew, S.K. & Morris, R.G. (1998) The heterogeneity of anosognosia for memory impairment
in Alzheimer’s disease: a review of the literature and a proposed model. Aging & Mental
Health, 2, 7–19.
Alexander, F. & French, T.M. (1946) Psychoanalytic Therapy: Principles and Applications. New
York: Ronald Press.
Allen, C.C. & Ruff, R.M. (1990) Self-rating versus neuropsychological performance of moderate
versus severe head-injured patients. Brain Injury, 4, 7–17.
Almeida, O.P., Levy, R., Howard, R.J. & David, A.S. (1996) Insight and paranoid disorders in late
life (late paraphrenia). International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 11, 653–658.
Amador, X.F. & David, A.S. (Eds) (1998) Insight and Psychosis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Amador, X. & David, A. (Eds) (2004) Insight and Psychosis. Awareness of Illness in Schizophrenia
and Related Disorders, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Amador, X.F. & Gorman, J.M. (1998) Psychopathological domains and insight in schizophrenia.
The Psychiatry Clinics of North America, 21, 27–42.
Amador, X.F. & Kronengold, H. (1998) The description and meaning of insight in psychosis.
In Insight and Psychosis, Eds. X.F. Amador & A.S. David, 1st edn. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 15–32.
Amador, X.F. & Strauss, D.H. (1993) Poor insight in schizophrenia. Psychiatric Quarterly, 64,
305–318.
Amador, X.F., Strauss, D.H., Yale, S.A. & Gorman, J.M. (1991) Awareness of illness in schizo-
phrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 17, 113–132.
Amador, X.F., Strauss, D.H., Yale, S.A., Flaum, M.M., Endicott, J. & Gorman, J.M. (1993)
Assessment of insight in psychosis. American Journal of Psychiatry, 150, 873–879.
Amador, X.F., Flaum, M., Andreason, N.C., Strauss, D.H., Yale, S.A., Clark, S.C. & Gorman, J.M.
(1994) Awareness of illness in schizophrenia and schizoaffective and mood disorders. Archives
of General Psychiatry, 51, 826–836.
293
294 References
Amador, X.F., Friedman, J.H., Kasapis, C., Yale, S.A., Flaum, M. & Gorman, J.M. (1996) Suicidal
behavior in schizophrenia and its relationship to awareness of illness. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 153, 1185–1188.
American Psychiatric Association (1987) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders,
3rd edn. revised (DSM-III-R). Washington, DC: APA.
American Psychiatric Association (1994) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders,
4th edn. (DSM-IV). Washington, DC: APA.
Aminoff, M.J., Marshall, J., Smith, E.M. & Wyke, M.A. (1975) Pattern of intellectual impairment
in Huntington’s chorea. Psychological Medicine, 5, 169–172.
Anderson, S.W. & Tranel, D. (1989) Awareness of disease states following cerebral infarction,
dementia and head trauma: standardized assessment. The Clinical Neuropsychologist, 3, 327–339.
Ansburg, P.I. (2000) Individual differences in problem solving via insight. Current Psychology:
Developmental, Learning, Personality, Social, 19, 143–146.
Anton, G. (1899) Ueber die Selbstwahrnehmung der Herderkrankungen des Gehirns durch den
Kranken bei Rindenblindheit und Rindentaubheit. Archiv für Psychiatrie und Nervenkrankheiten,
32, 86–127.
Apel, K-O. (1987) Dilthey’s distinction between ‘explanation’ and ‘understanding’ and the possi-
bility of its ‘mediation’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 25, 131–149.
Appelbaum, P.S., Mirkin, S.A. & Bateman, A.L. (1981) Empirical assessment of competency to
consent to psychiatric hospitalization. American Journal of Psychiatry, 138, 1170–1176.
Appelros, P., Karlsson, G.M., Seiger, Å. & Nydevik, I. (2002) Neglect and anosognosia after first-ever
stroke: incidence and relationship to disability. Journal of Rehabilitation Medicine, 34, 215–220.
Arango, C., Adami, H., Sherr, J.D., Thaker, G.K. & Carpenter, W.T. (1999) Relationship of awareness
of dyskinesia in schizophrenia to insight into mental illness. American Journal of Psychiatry,
156, 1097–1099.
Arduini, L., Kalyvoka, A., Stratta, P., Rinaldi, O., Daneluzzo, E. & Rossi, A. (2003) Insight and
neuropsychological function in patients with schizophrenia and bipolar disorder with psych-
otic features. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 48, 338–341.
Arndt, E. (1905) Zur Analyse des Krankheitsbewusstseins bei Psychosen. Centralblatt für
Nervenheilkunde und Psychiatrie, 16, 773–797.
Aschaffenburg, G. (1915) Allgemeine Symptomatologie der Psychosen. Krankheitsgefühl und
Krankheitseinsicht. In Handbuch der Psychiatrie, Ed. G. Aschaffenburg. Leipzig: Franz
Deuticke, pp. 367–371.
Auchus, A.P., Goldstein, F.C., Green, J. & Green, R.C. (1994) Unawareness of cognitive impairments
in Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychiatry Neuropsychology, and Behavioral Neurology, 7, 25–29.
Azam, É.E. (1892) Double consciousness. In A Dictionary of Psychological Medicine, Vol. 1, Ed.
D. Hack Tuke. London: J. & A. Churchill, pp. 401–406.
Babinski, M.J. (1914) Contribution à l’étude des troubles mentaux dans l’hémiplégie organique
cérébrale (anosognosie). Revue Neurologique, 27, 845–848.
Baddeley, A. (1987) Working Memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Baier, M., DeShay, E., Owens, K., Robinson, M., Lasar, K., Peterson, K. & Bland, R.S. (2000) The
relationship between insight and clinical factors for persons with schizophrenia. Archives of
Psychiatric Nursing, 14, 259–265.
295 References
Baillarger, J.G.F. (1853) Essai sur une classification des différents genres de folie. Annales Médico-
Psychologiques, 5, 545–566.
Ballard, C.G., Chithiramohan, R.N., Handy, S., Bannister, C., Davis, R. & Todd, N.B. (1991) Infor-
mation reliability in dementia sufferers. International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 6, 313–316.
Baron-Cohen, S. (1995) Mindblindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Barrett, A.M., Eslinger, P.J., Ballentine, N.H. & Heilman, K.M. (2005) Unawareness of cognitive
deficits (cognitive anosognosia) in probably AD and control subjects. Neurology, 64, 693–699.
Bartkó, G., Herczeg, I. & Zádor, G. (1988) Clinical symptomatology and drug compliance in
schizophrenic patients. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 77, 74–76.
Bauer, R.M. (1984) Autonomic recognition of names and faces in prosopagnosia: a neuropsycho-
logical application of the guilty knowledge test. Neuropsychologia, 22, 457–469.
Bauer, R.M. (1993) Agnosia. In Clinical Neuropsychology, Eds. K.M. Heilman & E. Valenstein, 3rd
edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 215–278.
Bauer, R.M., Tobias, B. & Valenstein, E. (1993) Amnesic disorders. In Clinical Neuropsychology,
Eds. K.M. Heilman & E. Valenstein, 3rd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 523–602.
Bear, D.M. (1983) Hemispheric specialization and the neurology of emotion. Archives of
Neurology, 40, 195–202.
Beaumont, J.G., Kenealy, P.M. & Rogers, M.J.C. (Eds) (1999) The Blackwell Dictionary of
Neuropsychology. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
Beck, A.T., Ward, C.H., Mendelson, M., Mock, J. & Erbaugh, J. (1961) An inventory for measur-
ing depression. Archives of General Psychiatry, 4, 561–571.
Bedford, A. & Foulds, G. (1978) Personality Deviance Scale (Manual). Windsor, Berkshire: NFER
Publishing Company.
Benton, A. & Tranel, D. (1993) Visuoperceptual, visuospatial, and visuoconstructive disorders.
In Clinical Neuropsychology, Eds. K.M. Heilman & E. Valenstein, 3rd edn. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 165–213.
Berrios, G.E. (1992) Phenomenology, psychopathology and Jaspers: a conceptual history. History
of Psychiatry, 3, 303–327.
Berrios, G.E. (1993) European views on personality disorders: a conceptual history. Comprehensive
Psychiatry, 34, 14–30.
Berrios, G.E. (1994a) Historiography of mental symptoms and diseases. History of Psychiatry,
5, 175–190.
Berrios, G.E. (1994b) Delusions: selected historical and clinical aspects. In The Neurological
Boundaries of Reality, Ed. E.M.R. Critchley. London, UK: Farrand, pp. 251–267.
Berrios, G.E. (1996) The History of Mental Symptoms. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Berrios, G.E. (2000) The history of psychiatric concepts. In Contemporary Psychiatry: Foundations
of Psychiatry, Vol. 1, Eds. F. Henn, N. Sartorius, H. Helmchen & H. Lauter. Heidelberg: Springer,
pp. 1–30.
Berrios, G.E. & Marková, I.S. (2001) Psychiatric disorders mimicking dementia. In Early-Onset
Dementia. A Multidisciplinary Approach, Ed. J.R. Hodges. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
pp. 104–123.
Berrios, G.E. & Marková, I.S. (2002) Conceptual issues. In Biological Psychiatry, Eds.
H. D’haenen, J.A. den Boer & P. Willner. Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd., pp. 3–24.
296 References
Berrios, G.E. & Marková, I.S. (2003) The self and psychiatry: a conceptual history. In The Self in
Neuroscience and Psychiatry, Eds. T. Kircher & A. David. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press, pp. 9–39.
Berrios, G.E. & Porter, R. (Eds) (1995) A History of Clinical Psychiatry. The Origin and History of
Psychiatric Disorders. London, UK: Athlone Press.
Berrios, G.E., Marková, I.S. & Olivares, J.M. (1995) Retorno a los síntomas mentales: hacia una
nueva metateoría. Psiquitría Biológica, 2, 13–24.
Berti, A. & Rizzolatti, G. (1992) Visual processing without awareness: evidence from unilateral
neglect. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 4, 345–351.
Berti, A., Làdavas, E., Stracciari, A., Giannarelli, C. & Ossola, A. (1998) Anosognosia for motor
impairment and dissociations with patients’ evaluation of the disorder: theoretical consider-
ations. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 3, 21–44.
Bibring, E. (1954) Psychoanalysis and the dynamic psychotherapies. Journal of the American
Psychoanalytic Association, 2, 745–770.
Billod, E. (1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec conscience. Annales Médico-Psychologiques,
3, 264–281.
Billod, E. (1882) Des aliénés avec conscience de leur état. In Des Maladies Mentales et Nerveuses.
Paris: Masson, pp. 492–512.
Birchwood, M., Smith, J., Drury, V., Healy, J., Macmillan, F. & Slade, M.A. (1994) A self-report
insight scale for psychosis: reliability, validity and sensitivity to change. Acta Psychiatrica
Scandinavica, 89, 62–67.
Bisiach, E. & Geminiani, G. (1991) Anosognosia related to hemiplegia and hemianopia. In
Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 17–39.
Bisiach, E., Vallar, G., Perani, D., Papagno, C. & Berti, A. (1986) Unawareness of disease follow-
ing lesions of the right hemisphere: anosognosia for hemiplegia and anosognosia for hemi-
anopia. Neuropsychologia, 24, 471–482.
Blonder, L.X. & Ranseen, J.D. (1994) Awareness of deficit following right hemisphere stroke.
Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology, and Behavioral Neurology, 7, 260–266.
Blum, H.P. (1979) The curative and creative aspects of insight. Journal of the American
Psychoanalytic Association, 27, 41–69.
Blum, H.P. (1992) Psychic change: the analytic relationship(s) and agents of change.
International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 73, 255–265.
Bogetto, F. & Ladu, M.A. (1989) Evaluation of the change in psychotherapy: an experimental
study. European Journal of Psychiatry, 3, 171–177.
Bologna, S.M. & Camp, C.J. (1997) Covert versus overt self-recognition in late stage Alzheimer’s
disease. Journal of the International Neuropsychological Society, 3, 195–198.
Boring, E.G. (1953) A history of introspection. Psychological Bulletin, 50, 169–189.
Bourgeois, M., Swendsen, J., Young, F., Amador, X., Pini, S., Cassano, G.B., Lindenmayer, J-P.,
Hsu, C., Alphs, L., Meltzer, H.Y. & The InterSePT Study Group (2004) Awareness of disorder
and suicide risk in the treatment of schizophrenia: results of the International Suicide
Prevention Trial. American Journal of Psychiatry, 161, 1494–1496.
Boutroux, E. (1908) De l’influence de la philosophie Écossaise sur la philosophie Française. In
Études d’Histoire de la philosophie. Paris: Felix Alcan.
297 References
Carveth, D.L. (1998) Is there a future in disillusion? Insight psychotherapy in the new millen-
nium. Journal of the Melanie Klein and Object Relations, 16, 555–587.
Cassidy, F., McEvoy, J.P., Yang, Y.K. & Wilson, W.H. (2001) Insight is greater in mixed than in
pure manic episodes of bipolar I disorder. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 189,
398–399.
Cautela, J.H. (1965) Desensitization and insight. Behavior Research and Therapy, 3, 59–64.
Cermak, L.S., Talbot, N., Chandler, K. & Wolbarst, L.R. (1985) The perceptual priming phenom-
ena in amnesia. Neuropsychologia, 23, 615–622.
Chen, E.Y.H., Kwok, C.L., Chen, R.Y.L. & Kwong, P.P.K. (2001) Insight changes in acute psychotic
episodes. A prospective study of Hong Kong Chinese patients. Journal of Nervous and Mental
Disease, 189, 24–30.
Chung, K.F., Chen, E.Y.H., Lam, L.C.W., Chen, R.Y.L. & Chan, C.K.Y. (1997) How are psychotic
symptoms perceived? A comparison between patients, relatives and the general public.
Australia & New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry, 31, 756–761.
Clare, L. (2003) Managing threats to self: awareness in early stage Alzheimer’s disease. Social
Science & Medicine, 57, 1017–1029.
Clare, L. (2004) The construction of awareness in early-stage Alzheimer’s disease: a review of
concepts and models. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 43, 155–175.
Clare, L., Wilson, B.A., Carter, G., Roth, I. & Hodges, J.R. (2002) Assessing awareness in early-
stage Alzheimer’s disease: development and piloting of the Memory Awareness Rating Scale.
Neuropsychological Rehabilitation, 12, 341–362.
Clare, L., Marková, I.S., Verhey, F. & Kenny, G. (2005) Awareness in dementia: a review of assess-
ment methods and measures. Aging & Mental Health, 9, 394–413.
Collins, A.A., Remington, G.J., Coulter, K. & Birkett, K. (1997) Insight, neurocognitive function
and symptom clusters in chronic schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research, 27, 37–44.
Condillac, E.B., Abbé de (1746/1924) Essai sur l’Origine des Connaissances Humaines. Publié avec
notice biographique et bibliographique par R. Lenoir. Paris: Librairie Armand Colin.
Conrad, K. (1958) Die Beginnende Schizophrenie. Stuttgart: Georg Thieme Verlag.
Coons, W.H. (1957) Interaction and insight in group psychotherapy. Canadian Journal of
Psychology, 11, 1–8.
Cooper, R. (2004) What is wrong with the DSM? History of Psychiatry, 15, 5–25.
Cooter, R.J. (1979) Phrenology and British alienists c1825–1845, part I & part II. Medical History,
20, 1–21, 135–151.
Correa, D.D., Graves, R.E. & Costa, L. (1996) Awareness of memory deficit in Alzheimer’s disease
patients and memory-impaired older adults. Aging, Neuropsychology and Cognition, 3,
215–228.
Cotrell, V. & Wild, K. (1999) Longitudinal study of self-imposed driving restrictions and deficit
awareness in patients with Alzheimer’s disease. Alzheimer Disease and Associated Disorders, 13,
151–156.
Critchley, M. (1953) The Parietal Lobes. London: Arnold.
Crits-Christoph, P., Barber, J.P., Miller, N.E. & Beebe, K. (1993) Evaluating insight. In
Psychodynamic Treatment Research, Eds. N.E. Miller, L. Luborsky, J.P. Barber & J.P. Docherty.
New York: BasicBooks, Harper Collins, pp. 407–422.
299 References
Crosson, B., Barco, P.P., Velozo, C.A., Bolesta, M.M., Cooper, P.V., Werts, D. & Brobeck, T.C.
(1989) Awareness and compensation in postacute head injury rehabilitation. Journal of Head
Trauma Rehabilitation, 4, 46–54.
Csikszentmihalyi, M. & Sawyer, K. (1995) Creative insight: the social dimension of a solitary
moment. In The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: MIT Press, pp. 329–363.
Cuesta, M.J. & Peralta, V. (1994) Lack of insight in schizophrenia. Schizophrenic Bulletin, 20, 359–366.
Cuesta, M.J., Peralta, V., Caro, F. & de Leon, J. (1995) Is poor insight in psychotic disorders asso-
ciated with poor performance on the Wisconsin card sorting test? American Journal of
Psychiatry, 152, 1380–1382.
Cuesta, M.J., Peralta, V. & Zarzuela, A. (1998) Psychopathological dimensions and lack of insight
in schizophrenia. Psychological Reports, 83, 895–898.
Cuesta, M.J., Peralta, V. & Zarzuela, A. (2000) Reappraising insight in psychosis. Multi-scale lon-
gitudinal study. British Journal of Psychiatry, 177, 233–240.
Cuffel, B.J., Alford, J., Fischer, E.P. & Owen, R.R. (1996) Awareness of illness in schizophrenia and
outpatient treatment adherence. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 184, 653–659.
Cummings, J.L., Ross, W., Absher, J., Gornbein, J. & Hadjiaghai, L. (1995) Depressive symptoms
in Alzheimer disease: assessment and determinants. Alzheimer Disease and Associated Disorders,
9, 87–93.
Currin, J. (2000) What are the essential characteristics of the analytic attitude? Insight, the use of
enactments and relationship. Journal of Clinical Psychoanalysis, 9, 75–91.
Cutting, J. (1978) Study of anosognosia. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 41,
548–555.
Dagonet, M.H. (1881) Conscience et aliénation mentale. Annales Médico-Psychologiques, 5,
368–397, 6, 19–32.
Dalla Barba, G., Parlato, V., Iavarone, A. & Boller, F. (1995) Anosognosia, intrusions and ‘frontal’
functions in Alzheimer’s disease and depression. Neuropsychologia, 33, 247–259.
Danielczyk, W. (1983) Various mental behavioral disorders in Parkinson’s disease, primary degen-
erative senile dementia, and multiple infarction dementia. Journal of Neural Transmission,
56, 161–176.
David, A.S. (1990) Insight and psychosis. British Journal of Psychiatry, 156, 798–808.
David, A. & Kemp, R. (1997) Five perspectives on the phenomenon of insight in psychosis.
Psychiatric Annals, 27, 791–797.
David, A.S. & Cutting, J.C. (Eds) (1994) The Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia. Hove, UK:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
David, A.S., Buchanan, A., Reed, A. & Almeida, O. (1992) The assessment of insight in psychosis.
British Journal of Psychiatry, 161, 599–602.
David, A.S., van Os, J., Jones, P., Harvey, I., Foerster, A. & Fahy, T. (1995) Insight and psychotic
illness – cross-sectional and longitudinal associations. British Journal of Psychiatry, 167,
621–628.
Davidoff, S.A., Forester, B.P., Ghaemi, S.N. & Bodkin, J.A. (1998) Effect of video self-observation
on development of insight in psychotic disorders. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 186,
697–700.
300 References
Davidson, J.E. (1995) The suddenness of insight. In The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg &
J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, pp. 125–155.
Davidson, J.E. & Sternberg, R.J. (1986) What is insight? Educational Horizon, 64, 177–179.
Davies, W.G. (1873) Consciousness and ‘unconscious cerebration’. Journal of Mental Science,
19, 202–217.
De Bettignies, B.H., Mahurin, R.K. & Pirozzolo, F.J. (1990) Insight for impairment in independ-
ent living skills in Alzheimer’s disease and multi-infarct dementia. Journal of Clinical and
Experimental Neuropsychology, 12, 355–363.
Debowska, G., Grzywa, A. & Kucharska-Pietura, K. (1998) Insight in paranoid schizophrenia –
its relationship to psychopathology and premorbid adjustment. Comprehensive Psychiatry,
39, 255–260.
Deckel, A.W. & Morrison, D. (1996) Evidence of a neurologically based ‘denial of illness’ in
patients with Huntington’s disease. Archives of Clinical Neuropsychology, 11, 295–302.
De Jonghe, F., Rijnierse, P. & Janssen, R. (1992) The role of support in psychoanalysis. Journal of
the American Psychoanalytic Association, 40, 475–499.
Delasiauve, L.J.F. (1853) De la monomanie au point de vue psychologique et légal. Annales
Médico-Psychologiques, 5, 353–371.
Delasiauve, L.J.F. (1861) Des diverses formes mentales. Journal de Médecine Mentale, 1, 4–14.
Delasiauve, L.J.F. (1863) Délire partiel diffus ou pseudo-monomanie. Journal de Médecine
Mentale, 3, 80–106.
Delasiauve, L.J.F. (1865) Des diverses formes mentales, folies partielles. Journal de Médecine
Mentale, 5, 11–20.
Delasiauve, L.J.F. (1866) Discussion sur la folie raisonnante. Annales Médico-Psychologiques,
7, 426–431.
Delasiauve, L.J.F. (1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec consciences. Annales Médico-
Psychologiques, 3, 103–109, 126–130, 290–291, 307–309.
Dening, T.R. & Berrios, G.E. (1992) The Hachinski ischaemic score: a reevaluation. International
Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 7, 585–589.
Derouesné, C., Thibault, S., Lagha-Pierucci, S., Baudouin-Madec, V., Ancri, D. & Lacomblez, L.
(1999) Decreased awareness of cognitive deficit in patients with mild dementia of the
Alzheimer’s type. International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 14, 1019–1030.
Descartes, R. (1648/1991) Conversation with Burman, 16th April 1648. In The Philosophical
Writings of Descartes, Vol. III, Trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch & A. Kenny. The
Correspondence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Despine, P. (1875) De la Folie au point de vue Philosophique ou plus spécialement psychologique.
Paris: Savy.
Dickerson, F.B., Boronow, J.J., Ringel, N. & Parente, F. (1997) Lack of insight among outpatients
with schizophrenia. Psychiatric Services, 48, 195–199.
Dilthey, W. (1976) Selected Writings. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Dittman, J. & Schüttler, R. (1990) Disease consciousness and coping strategies of patients with
schizophrenic psychosis. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 82, 318–322.
Dixon, M., King, S. & Steiger, H. (1998) The contribution of depression and denial towards
understanding the unawareness of symptoms in schizophrenic outpatients. British Journal of
Medical Psychology, 71, 85–97.
301 References
Dominowski, R.L. & Dallob, P. (1995) Insight and problem solving. In The Nature of Insight, Eds.
R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, pp. 33–62.
Doyle, M., Flanagan, S., Browne, S., Clarke, M., Lydon, D., Larkin, E. & O’Callaghan, C. (1999)
Subjective and external assessments of quality of life in schizophrenia: relationship to insight.
Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 99, 466–472.
Drake, R.J. & Lewis, S.W. (2003) Insight and neurocognition in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia
Research, 62, 165–173.
Drake, R.J., Pickles, A., Bentall, R.P., Kinderman, P., Haddock, G., Tarrier, N. & Lewis, S.W. (2004)
The evolution of insight, paranoia and depression during early schizophrenia. Psychological
Medicine, 34, 285–292.
Duke, L., Seltzer, B., Seltzer, J.E. & Vasterling, J.J. (2002) Cognitive components of deficit aware-
ness in Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychology, 16, 359–369.
Dunbar, K. (1995) How scientists really reason: scientific reasoning in real-world laboratories.
In The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
pp. 365–395.
Duncker, K. (1945) On problem-solving, Trans. L.S. Lees. Psychological Monographs, 58, whole
no. 270.
Dymond, R.F. (1948) A preliminary investigation of the relation of insight and empathy. Journal
of Consulting Psychology, 12, 228–233.
Dywan, C.A., McGlone, J. & Fox, A. (1995) Do intracarotid barbiturate injections offer a way to
investigate hemispheric models of anosognosia? Journal of Clinical and Experimental
Neuropsychology, 17, 431–438.
Edelman, G.M. (2003) Naturalizing consciousness: a theoretical framework. Proceedings of the
National Academic Sciences, 100, 5520–5524.
Ehrenfels, C. von (1890) Ueber ‘Gestaltqualitäten’. Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche
Philosophie, 14, 242–292.
Eisen, J.L., Phillips, K.A., Baer, L., Beer, D.A., Atala, K.D. & Rasmussen, S.A. (1998) The Brown
assessment of beliefs scale: reliability and validity. American Journal of Psychiatry, 155,
102–108.
Eisen, J.L., Rasmussen, S.A., Phillips, K.A., Price, L.H., Davidson, J., Lydiard, R.B., Ninan, P. &
Piggott, T. (2001) Insight and treatment outcome in obsessive-compulsive disorder. Comprehen-
sive Psychiatry, 42, 494–497.
Eisen, J.L., Phillips, K.A., Coles, M.E. & Rasmussen, S.A. (2004) Insight in obsessive compulsive
disorder and body dysmorphic disorder. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 45, 10–15.
Ellen, P. & Pate, J.L. (1986) Is insight merely response chaining?: a reply to Epstein. The
Psychological Record, 36, 155–160.
Elliott, R., Shapiro, D.A., Firth-Cozens, J., Stiles, W.B., Hardy, G.E., Llewelyn, S.P. & Margison, F.R.
(1994) Comprehensive process analysis of insight events in cognitive-behavioral and
psychodynamic-interpersonal psychotherapies. Journal of Counselling Psychology, 41, 449–463.
Endicott, J., Spitzer, R.L., Fleiss, J.L. & Cohen, J. (1976) The global assessment scale. Archives of
General Psychiatry, 33, 766–771.
Eskey, A. (1958) Insight and prognosis. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 14, 426–429.
Esquirol, E. (1819) Monomanie. In Dictionnaire Des Sciences Médicales, Vol. 34, Eds. Adelon,
Alibert, Barbier et al. Paris: Panckoucke, pp. 114–125.
302 References
Esquirol, E. (1838) Des Maladies Mentales Considérés Sous Les Rapports Médical, Hygiénique Et
Médico-Légal, 2 volumes. Paris: Baillière.
Etchegoyen, R.H. (1993) Psychoanalytic technique today: a personal view. Journal of Clinical
Psychoanalysis, 2, 529–540.
Exner, J.E. & Murillo, L. (1975) Early prediction of post-hospitalization relapse. Journal of
Psychiatric Research, 12, 231–237.
Fabre Dr. (Ed) (1840) Dictionnaire des Dictionnaires de Medicine Français et Etrangers. Paris:
Béthune et Plon.
Falret, J.P. (1866) Discussion sur la folie raisonnante. Annales Médico-Psychologiques, 7, 382–426.
Falret, J.P. (1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec conscience. Annales Médico-Psychologiques, 3,
120–121, 126.
Feher, E.P., Mahurin, R.K., Inbody, S.B., Crook, T.H. & Pirozzolo, F.J. (1991) Anosognosia in
Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and Behavioral Neurology, 4, 136–146.
Feher, E.P., Larrabee, G.J. & Crook, T.H. (1992) Factors attenuating the validity of the Geriatric
Depression Scale in a dementia population. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 40,
906–909.
Feher, E.P., Larrabee, G.J., Sudilovsky, A. & Crook, T.H. (1994) Memory self-report in Alzheimer’s
disease and in age-associated memory impairment. Journal of Geriatrics, Psychiatry and
Neurology, 7, 58–65.
Feldman, M.J. & Bullock, D.H. (1955) Some factors related to insight. Psychological Reports,
1, 143–152.
Fenichel, O. (1945) The Psychoanalytic Theory of Neurosis. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, Inc.
Fennig, S., Everett, E., Bromet, E.J., Jandorf, L., Fennig, S.R., Tanenberg-Karant, M. &
Craig, T.J. (1996) Insight in first-admission psychotic patients. Schizophrenia Research, 22,
257–263.
Ferris, S.H., Hofeldt, G.T., Carbone, G., Masciandaro, P., Troetel, W.M. & Imbimbo, B.P. (1999)
Suicide in two patients with a diagnosis of probable Alzheimer disease. Alzheimer Disease and
Associated Disorders, 13, 88–90.
Fingarette, H. (1969) Self-deception. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Finke, R.A. (1995) Creative insight and preinventive forms. In The Nature of Insight, Eds.
R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 255–280.
Fiore, S.M. & Schooler, J.W. (1998) Right hemisphere contributions to creative problem solving:
converging evidence for divergent thinking. In Right Hemisphere Language Comprehension.
Perspectives from Cognitive Neuroscience, Eds. M. Beeman & C. Chiarello. Mahwah, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 349–371.
Fisher, S. & Greenberg, R.P. (1977) The Scientific Credibility of Freud’s Theories and Therapy. New
York: Harvester Press.
Flashman, L.A., McAllister, T.W., Andreasen, N.C. & Saykin, A.J. (2000) Smaller brain size
associated with unawareness of illness in patients with schizophrenia. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 157, 1167–1169.
Flashman, L.A., McAllister, T.W., Johnson, S.C., Rick, J.H., Green, R.L. & Saykin, A.J. (2001)
Specific frontal lobe subregions correlated with unawareness of illness in schizophrenia: a pre-
liminary study. Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 13, 255–257.
303 References
Foa, E.B. (1979) Failure in treating obsessive-compulsives. Behaviour Research and Therapy,
17, 169–176.
Foa, E.B. & Kozak, M.J. (1995) DSM-IV field trial: obsessive-compulsive disorder. American
Journal of Psychiatry, 152, 90–96.
Foa, E.B., Abramowitz, J.S., Franklin, M.E. & Kozak, M.J. (1999) Feared consequences, fixity of
belief and treatment outcome in patients with obsessive-compulsive disorder. Behavior
Therapy, 30, 717–724.
Folstein, M.F., Folstein, S.E. & McHugh, P.R. (1975) ‘Mini-mental state’: a practical method for
grading the cognitive state of patients for the clinician. Journal of Psychiatric Research, 12,
189–198.
Foucault, M. (1971) Madness and Civilization, Trans. R. Howard. London: Routledge.
Fournet, (no initials) (1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec conscience. Annales Médico-
Psychologiques, 3, 121–125.
Francis, J.L. & Penn, D.L. (2001) The relationship between insight and social skill in persons with
severe mental illness. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 189, 822–829.
Frank, K.A. (1993) Actions, insight and working through. Outline of an integrative approach.
Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 3, 535–577.
Freud, A. (1981) Insight. Its presence and absence as a factor in normal development. In The
Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, Vol. 36, Eds. A.J. Solnit, R.S. Eissler, A. Freud, M. Kris &
P.B Neubauer. New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 241–249.
Freud, S. (1900) Preface to the 3rd (revised) English edition to the interpretation of dreams. In
The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. IV. Ed.
J. Strachey, 1954. London: Hogarth Press.
Freud, S. (1973a) Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, Trans. J. Strachey, 1963, Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books Ltd.
Freud, S. (1973b) New Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, Trans. J. Strachey, 1964,
Harmondsworth: Penguin Books Ltd.
Freudenreich, O., Deckersbach, T. & Goff, D.C. (2004) Insight into current symptoms of schizo-
phrenia. Association with frontal cortical function and affect. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica,
110, 14–20.
Friedman, R.S. & Förster, J. (2000) The effects of approach and avoidance motor actions on the
elements of creative insight. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 477–492.
Garety, P.A. & Hemsley, D.R. (1994) Delusions. Investigations into the Psychology of Delusional
Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gasquoine, P. (1992) Affective state and awareness of sensory and cognitive effects after closed
head injury. Neuropsychology, 6, 187–196.
Gasquoine, P.G. & Gibbons, T.A. (1994) Lack of awareness of impairment in institutionalized,
severely, and chronically disabled survivors of traumatic brain injury: a preliminary investiga-
tion. Journal of Head Trauma Rehabilitation, 9, 16–24.
Gedo, P.M. & Schaffer, N.D. (1989) An empirical approach to studying psychoanalytic process.
Psychoanalytic Psychology, 6, 277–291.
Gelder, M., Gath, D., Mayou, R. & Cowen, P. (1996) Oxford Textbook of Psychiatry, 3rd edn.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
304 References
Gelso, C.J., Hill, C.E. & Kivlighan, D.M. (1991) Transference, insight and the counselor’s inten-
tions during a counselling hour. Journal of Counseling and Development, 69, 428–433.
Gelso, C.J., Kivlighan, D.M., Wine, B., Jones, A. & Friedman, S.C. (1997) Transference, insight
and the course of time-limited therapy. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 44, 209–217.
Georget, E. (1820) De la Folie. Considérations sur cette maladie. Paris: Crevot.
Geschwind, N. (1965) Disconnexion syndromes in animals and man. Brain, 88, 237–294,
585–644.
Ghaemi, S.N. (2003) The Concepts of Psychiatry. A Pluralistic Approach to the Mind and Mental
Illness. Baltimore and London: John Hopkins Press.
Ghaemi, S.N., Stoll, A.L. & Pope, H.G. (1995) Lack of insight in bipolar disorder. Journal of
Nervous and Mental Disease, 183, 464–467.
Ghaemi, S.N., Hebben, N., Stoll, A.L. & Pope, H.G. (1996) Neuropsychological aspects of lack of
insight in bipolar disorder: a preliminary report. Psychiatry Research, 65, 113–120.
Ghaemi, S.N., Sachs, G.S., Baldassano, C.F. & Truman, C.J. (1997) Insight in seasonal affective
disorder. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 38, 345–348.
Gialanella, B. & Mattioli, F. (1992) Anosognosia and extrapersonal neglect as predictors of
functional recovery following right hemisphere stroke. Neuropsychological Rehabilitation,
2, 169–178.
Gick, M.L. & Holyoak, K.J. (1980) Analogical problem solving. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 306–355.
Gick, M.L. & Holyoak, K.J. (1983) Schema induction and analogical transfer. Cognitive
Psychology, 15, 1–38.
Gick, M.L. & Lockhart, R.S. (1995) Cognitive and affective components of insight. In The Nature
of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 197–228.
Gil, R., Arroyo-Anllo, E.M., Ingrand, P., Gil, M., Neau, J.P., Ornon, C. & Bonnaud, V. (2001) Self-
consciousness and Alzheimer’s disease. Acta Neurologica Scandinavica, 104, 296–300.
Gillett, G. (1994) Insight, delusion, and belief. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 1, 227–236.
Gilmore, R.L., Heilman, K.M., Schmidt, R.P., Fennell, E.M. & Quisling, R. (1992) Anosognosia
during Wada testing. Neurology, 42, 925–927.
Giovannetti, T., Libon, D.J. & Hart, T. (2002) Awareness of naturalistic action errors in demen-
tia. Journal of the International Neuropsychological Society, 8, 633–644.
Girard de Gailleux (1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec conscience de leur état. Annales Médico-
Psychologiques, 3, 466–471.
Glisky, E.L., Schacter, D.L. & Tulving, E. (1986) Computer learning by memory-impaired patients:
acquisition and retention of complex knowledge. Neuropsychologia, 24, 313–328.
Gloor, P., Olivier, A., Quesney, L.F., Andermann, F. & Horowitz, S. (1982) The role of the limbic
system in experiential phenomena of temporal lobe epilepsy. Annals of Neurology, 12, 129–144.
Glucksman, M.L. (1993) Insight, empathy, and internalization: elements of clinical change.
Journal of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis, 21, 163–181.
Godfrey, G.P.D., Partridge, F.M., Knight, R.G. & Bishara, S. (1993) Course of insight disorder and
emotional dysfunction following closed head injury: a controlled cross-sectional follow-up
study. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology, 15, 503–515.
Goldberg, D.P. & Hillier, V.F. (1979) A scaled version of the General Health Questionnaire.
Psychological Medicine, 9, 139–145.
305 References
Goldberg, E. & Barr, W.B. (1991) Three possible mechanisms of unawareness of deficit. In
Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 152–175.
Goldberg, R.W., Green-Paden, L.D., Lehman, A.F. & Gold, J.M. (2001) Correlates of insight in
serious mental illness. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 189, 137–145.
Goldstein, J. (1987) Console and Classify. The French Psychiatric Profession in the Nineteenth
Century. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Gordon, J. (1815) The doctrines of Gall and Spurzheim. Edinburgh Review, 25, 227–268.
Graf, P. & Schacter, D.L. (1985) Implicit and explicit memory for new associations in normal
and amnesic subjects. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition,
11, 501–518.
Green, J., Goldstein, F.C., Sirockman, B.E. & Green, R.C. (1993) Variable awareness of deficits in
Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and Behavioral Neurology, 6, 159–165.
Greenfeld, D., Strauss, J.S., Bowers, M.B. & Mandelkern, M. (1989) Insight and interpretation of
illness in recovery from psychosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 15, 245–252.
Greenfeld, D.G., Anyon, W.R., Hobart, M., Quinlan, D. & Plantes, M. (1991) Insight into illness
and outcome in anorexia nervosa. International Journal of Eating Disorders, 10, 101–109.
Grenyer, B.F.S. & Luborsky, L. (1996) Dynamic change in psychotherapy: mastery of interper-
sonal conflicts. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 64, 411–416.
Grimm, J. & Grimm, W. (1862) Deutsches Wörterbuch, Vol. 12. Leipzig: S. Hirzel.
Gruber, H.E. (1995) Insight and affect in the history of science. In The Nature of Insight, Eds.
R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 397–431.
Grut, M., Jorm, A.F., Fratiglioni, L., Forsell, Y., Viitanen, M. & Winblad, B. (1993) Memory com-
plaints of elderly people in a population survey: variation according to dementia stage and
depression. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 41, 1295–1300.
Guislain, J. (1852) Leçons Orales sur les Phrénopathies, ou Traité Théorique et Pratique des Maladies
Mentales. Gand: Hebbelynck.
Gustafson, L. & Nilsson, L. (1982) Differential diagnosis of presenile dementia on clinical
grounds. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 65, 194–209.
Guy, W. & Ban, T.A. (1982) The AMDP-System. Manual for the Assessment and Documentation of
Psychopathology. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Hachinski, V.C., Iliff, L.D., Zilhka, E., Du Boulay, G.H., McAllister, V.L., Marshall, J., Russell,
R.W.R. & Symon, L. (1975) Cerebral blood flow in dementia. Archives of Neurology, 32, 632–637.
Haight, M.R. (1980) A Study of Self-deception. Brighton: Harvester Press.
Hameroff, S.R., Kaszniak, A.W. & Scott, A.C. (Eds) (1996) Toward a Science of Consciousness.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hamilton, M. (1967) Development of a rating scale for primary depressive illness. British Journal
of Social and Clinical Psychology, 6, 278–296.
Hamlyn, D.W. (1977) Self-knowledge. In The Self: Psychological and Philosophical Issues, Ed.
T. Mischel. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hankoff, L.D., Engelhardt, D.M., Freedman, N., Mann, N. & Margolis, R. (1960a) Denial of ill-
ness in schizophrenic outpatients: the effects of psychopharmacological treatment. Archives
of General Psychiatry, 3, 657–664.
306 References
Hankoff, L.D., Engelhardt, D.M. & Freedman, N. (1960b) Placebo response in schizophrenic out-
patients. Archives of General Psychiatry, 2, 33–42.
Hart, T., Sherer, M., Whyte, J., Polansky, M. & Novack, T.A. (2004) Awareness of behavioral, cog-
nitive, and physical deficits in acute traumatic brain injury. Archives of Physical Medicine and
Rehabilitation, 85, 1450–1456.
Hartlage, L.C. (1970) Subprofessional therapists’ use of reinforcement versus traditional psy-
chotherapeutic techniques with schizophrenics. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology,
34, 181–183.
Hartmann, G.W. (1931) The concept and criteria of insight. Psychological Review, 38, 242–253.
Hartmann, G.W. (1932) Insight and the context of Gestalt theory. American Journal of
Psychology, 44, 576–578.
Harwood, D.G. & Sultzer, D.L. (2002) Life is not worth living: hopelessness in Alzheimer’s dis-
ease. Journal of Geriatrics Psychiatry and Neurology, 15, 38–43.
Harwood, D.G., Sultzer, D.L. & Wheatley, M.V. (2000) Impaired insight in Alzheimer’s disease:
association with cognitive deficits, psychiatric symptoms and behavioural disturbances.
Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and Behavioral Neurology, 13, 83–88.
Hatcher, R.L. (1973) Insight and self-observation. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic
Association, 21, 377–398.
Healton, E.B., Navarro, C., Bressman, S. & Brust, J.C.M. (1982) Subcortical neglect. Neurology,
32, 776–778.
Heilman, K.M. (1991) Anosognosia: possible neuropsychological mechanisms. In Awareness of
Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 53–62.
Heilman, K.M., Watson, R.T. & Valenstein, E. (1993) Neglect and related disorders. In Clinical
Neuropsychology, Eds. K.M. Heilman & E. Valenstein, 3rd edn. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 279–336.
Heindel, W.C., Salmon, D.P., Shults, C.W., Walicke, P.A. & Butters, N. (1989) Neuropsychological
evidence for multiple implicit memory systems: a comparison of Alzheimer’s, Huntington’s
and Parkinson’s disease patients. Journal of Neuroscience, 9, 582–587.
Heinrichs, E.L., Cohen, B.P. & Carpenter, W.T. (1985) Early insight and the management of
schizophrenic decompensation. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 173, 133–138.
Henley, R. (1999) Distinguishing insight from intuition. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, 287–290.
Hering, E. (1870/1920) On memory as a universal function of organised matter. Lecture trans-
lated in S. Butler Unconscious Memory (1880/1920). London: A.C. Fifield, pp. 63–86.
Hermann, D.J. (1982) Know the memory: the use of questionnaires to assess and study memory.
Psychological Bulletin, 92, 434–452.
Hier, D.B., Mondlock, J. & Caplan, L.R. (1983a) Behavioral abnormalities after right hemisphere
stroke. Neurology, 33, 337–344.
Hier, D.B., Mondlock, J. & Caplan, L.R. (1983b) Recovery of behavioral abnormalities after right
hemisphere stroke. Neurology, 33, 345–350.
Hodges, J.R. (1994) Cognitive Assessment for Clinicians. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hoffbauer, J.C. (1808/1827) Médecine Légale relative aux Aliénés et aux Sourds-muets, Trans.
A.M. Chambeyron, Notes E. Esquirol & J.M.G. Itard, 3rd edn. Paris: JB. Baillière.
307 References
Horton, P.C. (1976) Personality disorder and parietal lobe dysfunction. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 133, 782–785.
Howorth, P. & Saper, J. (2003) The dimensions of insight in people with dementia. Aging and
Mental Health, 7, 113–122.
Hutchinson, E.D. (1941) The nature of insight. Psychiatry Journal for the Study of Interpersonal
Processes, 4, 31–43.
Insel, T.R. & Akiskal, H.S. (1986) Obsessive-compulsive disorder with psychotic features: a phe-
nomenologic analysis. American Journal of Psychiatry, 143, 1527–1533.
Ippolito, M.F. & Tweney, R.D. (1995) The inception of insight. In The Nature of Insight, Eds.
R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 433–462.
Iqbal, Z., Birchwood, M., Chadwick, P. & Trower, P. (2000) Cognitive approach to depression and
suicidal thinking in psychosis. 2. Testing the validity of a social ranking model. British Journal
of Psychiatry, 177, 522–528.
Ireland, W.W. (1875) Can unconscious cerebration be proved? Journal of Mental Science, 21, 366–387.
Isaak, M.I. & Just, M.A. (1995) Constraints on thinking in insight and invention. In The Nature
of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 281–325.
Jacoby, L.L. & Kelley, C. (1992) Unconscious influences of memory: dissociations and auto-
maticity. In The Neuropsychology of Consciousness, Eds. A.D. Milner & M.D. Rugg. London:
Academic Press, pp. 201–233.
Jacoby, L.L. & Witherspoon, D. (1982) Remembering without awareness. Canadian Journal of
Psychology, 36, 300–324.
Janet, P. (1904) L’amnésie et la dissociation des souvenirs par l’émotion. Journal de Psychologie,
5, 417–453.
Jaspers, K. (1913) Allgemeine Psychopathologie, 1st edn. Berlin: Springer.
Jaspers, K. (1948) Allgemeine Psychopathologie, 5th edn. Berlin: Springer.
Jehkonen, M., Ahonen, J-P., Dastidar, P., Laippala, P. & Vilkki, J. (2000) Unawareness of deficits
after right hemispheric stroke: double-dissociations of anosognosias. Acta Neurologica
Scandinavica, 102, 378–384.
Johnson, S. & Orrell, M. (1995) Insight and psychosis: a social perspective. Psychological
Medicine, 25, 515–520.
Johnson, S. & Orrell, M. (1996) Insight, psychosis and ethnicity: a case-note study. Psychological
Medicine, 26, 1081–1084.
Jørgensen, P. (1995) Recovery and insight in schizophrenia. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 92,
436–440.
Jorm, A.F., Christensen, H., Henderson, A.S., Korten, A.E., Mackinnon, A.J. & Scott, R. (1994)
Complaints of cognitive decline in the elderly: a comparison of reports by subjects and
informants in a community survey. Psychological Medicine, 24, 365–374.
Joyce, A. & Stoker, J. (2000) Insight and the nature of therapeutic action in the psychoanalysis of
4- and 5-year-old children. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 81, 1139–1154.
Kageyama, J. (1984) Sur l’histoire de la monomanie. L’Evolution Psychiatrique, 49, 155–162.
Kahn, R.L. & Fink, M. (1959) Personality factors in behavioral response to electroshock therapy.
Journal of Neuropsychiatry, 1, 45–49.
Kaplan, C.A. & Simon, H.A. (1990) In search of insight. Cognitive Psychology, 22, 374–419.
308 References
Kaplan, R.F., Meadows, M.E., Cohen, R.A., Bromfield, E.B. & Ehrenberg, B.L. (1993) Awareness
of deficit after the sodium amobarbital (Wada) test. Journal of Clinical and Experimental
Neuropsychology, 15 (Abstract), 383.
Kaszniak, A.W. & Christenson, G.D. (1996) Self-awareness of deficit in patients with Alzheimer’s
disease. In Toward a Science of Consciousness. The First Tucson Discussions and Debates, Eds.
S.R. Hameroff, A.W. Kaszniak & A.C. Scott. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 227–242.
Kay, S.R., Fiszbein, A. & Opler, L.A. (1987) The positive and negative syndrome scale (PANSS)
for schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 13, 261–276.
Keane, M. (1989) Modelling problem solving in Gestalt ‘insight’ problems. The Irish Journal of
Psychology, 10, 201–215.
Keane, M.M., Gabrieli, J.D.E., Fennema, A.C., Growden, J.H. & Corkin, S. (1991) Evidence for a
dissociation between perceptual and conceptual priming in Alzheimer’s disease. Behavioral
Neurosciences, 105, 326–342.
Kellogg, W.N. (1938) An eclectic view of some theories of learning. Psychological Review, 45,
165–184.
Kemp, R. & David, A. (1996) Psychological predictors of insight and compliance in psychotic
patients. British Journal of Psychiatry, 169, 444–450.
Kemp, R.A. & Lambert, T.J.R. (1995) Insight in schizophrenia and its relationship to psy-
chopathology. Schizophrenia Research, 18, 21–28.
Kennedy, H. (1979) The role of insight in child analysis: a developmental viewpoint. Journal of
the American Psychoanalytic Association, 27, 9–28.
Keshavan, M.S., Rabinowitz, J., DeSmedt, G., Harvey, P.D. & Schooler, N. (2004) Correlates of
insight in first episode psychosis. Schizophrenia Research, 70, 187–194.
Kim, Y., Sakamoto, K., Kamo, T., Sakamura, Y. & Miyaoka (1997) Insight and clinical correlates
in schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 38, 117–123.
Kivlighan, D.M., Multon, K.D. & Patton, M.J. (2000) Insight and symptom reduction in time-
limited psychoanalytic counseling. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 47, 50–58.
Kiyak, H.A., Teri, L. & Borson, S. (1994) Physical and functional health assessment in
normal aging and in Alzheimer’s disease: self-reports vs family reports. The Gerontologist,
34, 324–330.
Koffka, K. (1925/1980) The Growth of the Mind, 2nd edn. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction
Books.
Koffka, K. (1935/1963) Principles of Gestalt Psychology. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World Inc.
Köhler, W. (1924/1957) The Mentality of Apes, Trans. E. Winter, 1925, 2nd edn. Harmondsworth,
Middlesex: Penguin Books Ltd.
Kohut, H. (1977) The Restoration of the Self. New York: International Universities Press.
Koltai, D.C., Welsh-Bohmer, K.A. & Schmeckel, D.E. (2001) Influence of anosognosia on treat-
ment outcome among dementia patients. Neuropsychological Rehabilitation, 11, 455–475.
Korsakoff, S.S. (1889) Étude médico-psychologique sur une forme des maladies de la mémoire.
Revue Philosophique, 28, 501–530.
Koss, E., Patterson, M.B., Ownby, R., Stuckey, J.C. & Whitehouse, P.J. (1993) Memory evaluation
in Alzheimer’s disease, caregivers’ appraisals and objective testing. Archives of Neurology,
50, 92–97.
309 References
Kotler-Cope, S. & Camp, C.J. (1995) Anosognosia in Alzheimer’s disease. Alzheimer Disease and
Associated Disorders, 9, 52–56.
Kraepelin, E. (1913/1919) Dementia Praecox and Paraphrenia, Trans. R.M. Barclay. Edinburgh:
E. & S. Livingstone.
Krafft-Ebing, R. (1893) Lehrbuch der Psychiatrie, 5th edn. Stuttgart: F. Enke.
Kris, E. (1956) On some vicissitudes of insight in psychoanalysis. International Journal of
Psycho-Analysis, 37, 445–455.
Kuriansky, J.B., Gurland, B.J. & Fleiss, J.L. (1976) The assessment of self-care capacity in geriatric
psychiatric patients by objective and subjective methods. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 32,
95–102.
Lam, D. & Wong, G. (1997) Prodromes, coping strategies, insight and social functioning in bipo-
lar affective disorders. Psychological Medicine, 27, 1091–1100.
Lam, L.C., Chan, C.K. & Chen, E.Y. (1996) Insight and general public attitude on psychotic
experiences in Hong Kong. International Journal of Social Psychiatry, 42, 10–17.
Lamar, M., Lasarev, M.R. & Libon, D.J. (2002) Determining levels of unawareness in dementia
research. Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 14, 430–437.
Lange, K. (1906) Über Apperzeption. Leipzig: R. Voigtländers Verlag.
Langer, K.G. & Padrone, F.J. (1992) Psychotherapeutic treatment of awareness in acute rehabili-
tation of traumatic brain injury. Neuropsychological Rehabilitation, 2, 59–70.
Larøi, F., Fannemel, M., Rønneberg, U., Flekkøy, K., Opjordsmoen, S., Dullerud, R. & Haakonsen, M.
(2000) Unawareness of illness in chronic schizophrenia and its relationship to structural brain
measures and neuropsychological tests. Psychiatry Research, 100, 49–58.
Larrabee, G.J., West, R.L. & Crook, T.H. (1991) The association of memory complaint with
computer-simulated everyday memory performance. Journal of Clinical and Experimental
Neuropsychology, 13, 466–478.
Legrand du Saulle, H. (1864) La Folie devant les Tribunaux. Paris: Savy.
Lehmkuhl, U. (1989) Wie läßt sich Einsicht vermitteln? Zur Methode und zur Wirkung von
Deutungen. Zeitschrift für Individualpsychologie, 14, 227–233.
Lelliott, P.T., Noshirvani, H.F., Baþoðlu, M., Marks, I.M. & Monteiro, W.O. (1988) Obsessive-
compulsive beliefs and treatment outcome. Psychological Medicine, 18, 697–702.
Lélut, F. (1837) Qu’est-ce que la Phrenologie? Bruxelles: Établissement Encyclographique.
Lélut, F. (1843) Rejet de l’organologie phrénologique de Gall, et de ses successeurs. Paris: Masson.
Levenson, E. (1998) Awareness, insight and learning. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 34,
239–249.
Levin, H.S., High, W.M., Goethe, K.E., Sisson, R.A., Overall, J.E., Rhoades, H.M., Eisenberg,
H.M., Kalisky, Z. & Gary, H.E. (1987) The neurobehavioural rating scale: assessment of the
behavioural sequelae of head injury by the clinician. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and
Psychiatry, 50, 183–193.
Levine, H.B. (1994) The analyst’s participation in the analytic process. International Journal of
Psycho-Analysis, 75, 665–676.
Levine, D.N., Calvanio, R. & Rinn, W.E. (1991) The pathogenesis of anosognosia for hemiplegia.
Neurology, 41, 1770–1781.
Lewis, A. (1934) The psychopathology of insight. Journal of Medical Psychology, 14, 332–348.
310 References
Lysaker, P.H., Bryson, G.J., Lancaster, R.S., Evans, J.D. & Bell, M.D. (2002) Insight in schizophre-
nia: associations with executive function and coping style. Schizophrenia Research, 59, 41–47.
Lysaker, P.H., Lancaster, R.S., Davis, L.W. & Clements, C.A. (2003) Patterns of neurocognitive deficits
and unawareness of illness in schizophrenia. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 191, 38–44.
MacKenzie, T.B., Robiner, W.N. & Knopman, D.S. (1989) Differences between patient and
family assessments of depression in Alzheimer’s disease. American Journal of Psychiatry, 146,
1174–1178.
MacPherson, R. & Collis, R. (1992) Tardive dyskinesia. Patients’ lack of awareness of movement
disorder. British Journal of Psychiatry, 160, 110–112.
MacPherson, R., Jerrom, B. & Hughes, A. (1996) Relationship between insight, educational back-
ground and cognition in schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 168, 718–722.
McAndrews, M.P., Glisky, E.L. & Schacter, D.L. (1987) When priming persists: long-lasting
implicit memory for a single episode in amnesic patients. Neuropsychologia, 25, 497–506.
McCabe, R., Quayle, E., Beirne, A. & Duane, M.A. (2000) Is there a role for compliance in the
assessment of insight in chronic schizophrenia? Psychology, Health and Medicine, 5, 173–178.
McCabe, R., Quayle, E., Beirne, A. & Duane, M.M.A. (2002) Insight, global neuropsychological
functioning and symptomatology in chronic schizophrenia. Journal of Nervous and Mental
Disease, 190, 519–525.
McDaniel, K.D., Edland, S.D., Heyman, A. & the CERAD Clinical Investigators (1995)
Relationship between level of insight and severity of dementia in Alzheimer disease. Alzheimer
Disease and Associated Disorders, 9, 101–104.
McEvoy, J.P. (1998) The relationship between insight in psychosis and compliance with medica-
tions. In Insight and Psychosis, Eds. X.F. Amador & A.S. David, 1st edn. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 289–306.
McEvoy, J.P., Freter, S., Everett, G., Geller, J.L., Appelbaum, P., Apperson, L.J. & Roth, L. (1989a)
Insight and the clinical outcome of schizophrenic patients. Journal of Nervous and Mental
Disease, 177, 48–51.
McEvoy, J.P., Apperson, L.J., Appelbaum, P.S., Ortlip, P., Brecosky, J., Hammill, K., Geller, J.L. &
Roth, L. (1989b) Insight in schizophrenia. Its relationship to acute psychopathology. Journal of
Nervous and Mental Disease, 177, 43–47.
McEvoy, J.P., Appelbaum, P.S., Apperson, L.J., Geller, J.L. & Freter, S. (1989c) Why must some
schizophrenic patients be involuntarily committed? The role of insight. Comprehensive
Psychiatry, 30, 13–17.
McEvoy, J.P., Freter, S., Merritt, M. & Apperson, L.J. (1993a) Insight about psychosis among out-
patients with schizophrenia. Hospital and Community Psychiatry, 44, 883–884.
McEvoy, J.P., Schooler, N.R., Friedman, E., Steingard, S. & Allen, M. (1993b) Use of psychopath-
ology vignettes by patients with schizophrenia or schizoaffective disorder and by mental health
professionals to judge patients’ insight. American Journal of Psychiatry, 150, 1649–1653.
McEvoy, J.P., Hartman, M., Gottlieb, D., Goodwin, S., Apperson, L.J. & Wilson, W. (1996)
Common sense, insight and neuropsychological test performance in schizophrenia patients.
Schizophrenia Bulletin, 22, 635–641.
McGlashan, T.H. & Carpenter, W.T. (1981) Does attitude toward psychosis relate to outcome?
American Journal of Psychiatry, 138, 797–801.
312 References
McGlashan, T.H. & Miller, G.H. (1982) The goals of psychoanalysis and psychoanalytic psy-
chotherapy. Archives of General Psychiatry, 39, 377–388.
McGlone, J., Gupta, S., Humphrey, D. & Oppenheimer, T. (1990) Screening for early dementia
using memory complaints from patients and relatives. Archives of Neurology, 47, 1189–1193.
McGlynn, S.M. & Kaszniak, A.W. (1991a) When metacognition fails: impaired awareness of
deficit in Alzheimer’s disease. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 3, 183–189.
McGlynn, S.M. & Kaszniak, A.W. (1991b) Unawareness of deficits in dementia and schizophre-
nia. In Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, pp. 84–110.
McGlynn, S.M. & Schacter, D.L. (1989) Unawareness of deficits in neuropsychological syn-
dromes. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology, 11, 143–205.
McGorry, P. & McConville, S.B. (1999) Insight in psychosis: an elusive target. Comprehensive
Psychiatry, 40, 131–142.
McKenna, P.J. (1994) Schizophrenia and Related Syndromes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McKhann, G., Drachman, D., Folstein, M., Katzman, R., Price, D. & Stadlan, E.M. (1984) Clinical
diagnosis of Alzheimer’s disease: report of the NINCDS-ADRDA work group under the aus-
pices of the Department of Health and Human Services Task Force on Alzheimer’s disease.
Neurology, 34, 939–944.
McLoughlin, D.M., Cooney, C., Holmes, C. & Levy, R. (1996) Carer informants for dementia
sufferers: carer awareness of cognitive impairment in an elderly community-resident sample.
Age and Ageing, 25, 367–371.
Makkreel, R.A. (1992) Dilthey. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Mangham, C.A. (1981) Insight. Pleasurable affects associated with insight and their origins in
infancy. In The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, Vol. 36. Eds. A.J. Solnit, R.S. Eissler, A. Freud,
M. Kris & P.B. Neubauer. New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 271–277.
Mangone, C.A., Hier, D.B., Gorelick, P.B., Ganellen, R.J., Langenberg, P., Boarman, R. &
Dollear, W.C. (1991) Impaired insight in Alzheimer’s disease. Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry
and Neurology, 4, 189–193.
Mann, J.H. & Mann, C.H. (1959) Insight as a measure of adjustment in three kinds of group
experience. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 23, 91.
Marcel, A.J. & Bisiach, E. (Eds) (1988) Consciousness in Contemporary Science. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Marder, S.R., Mebane, A., Chien, C., Winslade, W.J., Swann, E. & Van Putten, T. (1983) A com-
parison of patients who refuse and consent to neuroleptic treatment. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 140, 470–472.
Marková, I.S. & Berrios, G.E. (1992a) The meaning of insight in clinical psychiatry. British
Journal of Psychiatry, 160, 850–860.
Marková, I.S. & Berrios, G.E. (1992b) The assessment of insight in clinical psychiatry: a new
scale. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 86, 159–164.
Marková, I.S. & Berrios, G.E. (1995a) Insight in clinical psychiatry revisited. Comprehensive
Psychiatry, 36, 367–376.
Marková, I.S. & Berrios, G.E. (1995b) Insight in clinical psychiatry: a new model. Journal of
Nervous and Mental Disease, 183, 743–751.
313 References
Marková, I.S. & Berrios, G.E. (1995c) Mental symptoms: are they similar phenomena? The prob-
lem of symptom heterogeneity. Psychopathology, 28, 147–157.
Marková, I.S. & Berrios, G.E. (2000) Insight into memory deficits. In Memory Disorders in
Psychiatric Practice, Eds. G.E. Berrios & J.R. Hodges. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
Marková, I.S. & Berrios, G.E. (2001) The ‘object’ of insight assessment: relationship to insight
‘structure’. Psychopathology, 34, 245–252.
Marková, I.S., Roberts, K.H., Gallagher, C., Boos, H., McKenna, P.J. & Berrios, G.E. (2003)
Assessment of insight in psychosis: a re-standardization of a new scale. Psychiatry Research,
119(1–2), 81–88.
Marková, I.S., Berrios, G.E. & Hodges, J.R. (2004) Insight into memory function. Neurology,
Psychiatry and Brain Research, 11, 115–126.
Marks, K.A., Fastenau, P.S., Lysaker, P.H. & Bond, G.R. (2000) Self-appraisal of illness question-
naire (SAIQ): relationship to researcher-rated insight and neuropsychological function in
schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research, 45, 203–211.
Martin, A.R. (1952) The dynamics of insight. American Journal of Psychoanalysis, 12, 24–38.
Maudsley, H. (1885) Responsibility in Mental Disease. London: Kegan Paul & Trench.
Maudsley, H. (1895) The Pathology of Mind. London: Macmillan & Co.
Maudsley, H. (1916) Organic to Human Psychological and Sociological. London: Macmillan & Co.
Maury, A.L.F (1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec consciences. Annales Médico-Psychologiques,
3, 119–120.
Mayer, R.E. (1995) The search for insight: grappling with Gestalt psychology’s unanswered ques-
tions. In The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, pp. 3–32.
Mead, G.H. (1934) Mind, Self and Society. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
Mead, G.H. (1936) Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century. Chicago and London:
University of Chicago Press.
Mercier, C.A. (1892) Consciousness. In A Dictionary of Psychological Medicine, Vol. 1, Ed.
D. Hack Tuke. London: J. & A. Churchill, pp. 249–262.
Mesulam, M-M. (1986) Frontal cortex and behavior. Annals of Neurology, 19, 320–325.
Metcalfe, J. (1986a) Feeling of knowing in memory and problem solving. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 12, 288–294.
Metcalfe, J. (1986b) Premonitions of insight predict impending error. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 12, 623–634.
Metcalfe, J. (1998) Insight and metacognition. In Metacognition and Cognitive Neuropsychology,
Eds. G. Mazzoni & T.O. Nelson. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 181–197.
Metcalfe, J. & Shimamura, A.P. (1994) Metacognition. Knowing about Knowing. Cambridge: MIT
Press.
Metcalfe, J. & Wiebe, D. (1987) Intuition in insight and noninsight problem solving. Memory &
Cognition, 15, 238–246.
Michalakeas, A., Skoutas, C., Charatambous, A., Peristeris, A., Marinos, V., Keramari, E. &
Theologou, A. (1994) Insight in schizophrenia and mood disorders and its relation to psy-
chopathology. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 90, 46–49.
314 References
Michon, A., Deweer, B., Pillon, B., Agid, Y. & Dubois, B. (1992) Anosognosia and frontal dys-
function in SDAT. Neurology (Suppl. 3), 42, 221.
Michon, A., Deweer, B., Pillon, B., Agid, Y. & Dubois, B. (1994) Relation of anosognosia to frontal
lobe dysfunction in Alzheimer’s disease. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry,
57, 805–809.
Migliorelli, R., Tesón, A., Sabe, L., Petracca, G., Petracchi, M., Leiguarda, R. & Starkstein, S.E. (1995)
Anosognosia in Alzheimer’s disease: a study of associated factors. Journal of Neuropsychiatry and
Clinical Sciences, 7, 338–344.
Miller, E. & Lewis, P. (1977) Recognition memory in elderly patients with depression and
dementia: a signal detection analysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 86, 84–86.
Milner, A.D. & Rugg, M.D (Eds) (1992) The Neuropsychology of Consciousness. London:
Academic Press Ltd.
Mintz, A.R., Dobson, K.S. & Romney, D.M. (2003) Insight in schizophrenia: a meta-analysis.
Schizophrenia Research, 61, 75–88.
Mintz, A.R., Addington, J. & Addington, D. (2004) Insight in early psychosis: a 1-year follow-up.
Schizophrenia Research, 67, 213–217.
Mohamed, S., Fleming, S., Penn, D.L. & Spaulding, W. (1999) Insight in schizophrenia: its relation-
ship to measures of executive functions. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 187, 525–531.
Moore, O., Cassidy, E., Carr, A. & O’Callaghan, E. (1999) Unawareness of illness and its relation-
ship with depression and self-deception in schizophrenia. European Psychiatry, 14, 264–269.
Morgan, R., Luborsky, L., Crits-Christoph, P., Curtis, H. & Solomon, J. (1982) Predicting the out-
comes of psychotherapy by the Penn Helping Alliance rating method. Archives of General
Psychiatry, 39, 397–402.
Morel, B.A. (1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec conscience. Annales Médico-Psychologiques,
3, 110–119.
Morris, L. (1972) The Discovery of the Individual, 1050–1200. New York: Harper and Row.
Moulin, C.J.A., Perfect, T.J. & Jones, R.W. (2000) Global predictions of memory in Alzheimer’s
disease: evidence for preserved metamemory monitoring. Aging, Neuropsychology and
Cognition, 7, 230–244.
Mullen, R., Howard, R., David, A. & Levy, R. (1996) Insight in Alzheimer’s disease. International
Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 11, 645–651.
Mutsatsa, S.H., Joyce, E.M., Hutton, S.B., Webb, E., Gibbins, H., Paul, S. & Barnes, T.R.E. (2003)
Clinical correlates of early medication adherence: West London first episode schizophrenia
study. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 108, 439–446.
Myerson, P.G. (1960) Awareness and stress: post-psycho-analytic utilization of insight. International
Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 41, 147–156.
Myerson, P.G. (1965) Modes of insight. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 13,
771–792.
Myslobodsky, M.S. (1986) Anosognosia in tardive dyskinesia: ‘tardive dysmentia’ or ‘tardive
dementia’? Schizophrenia Bulletin, 12, 1–6.
Neary, D., Snowden, J.S., Bowen, D.M., Sims, N.R., Mann, D.M.A., Benton, J.S., Northen, B.,
Yates, P.O. & Davison, A.N. (1986) Neuropsychological syndromes in presenile dementia due
to cerebral atrophy. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 49, 163–174.
315 References
Neubauer, P.B. (1979) The role of insight in psychoanalysis. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic
Association, 27, 29–40.
Neundorfer, M.M. (1997) Awareness of variability in awareness. Alzheimer Disease and Associated
Disorders, 11, 121–122.
Niederehe, G. (1988) TRIMS behavioral problem checklist (BPC). Psychopharmacology Bulletin,
24, 771–773.
Nisbett, R.E. & Wilson, T.D. (1977) Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental
processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231–259.
O’Connor, R. & Herrman, H. (1993) Assessment of contributions to disability in people
with schizophrenia during rehabilitation. Australia and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry,
27, 595–600.
O’Connor, L.E., Edelstein, S., Berry, J.W. & Weiss, J. (1994) Changes in the patient’s level of
insight in brief psychotherapy: two pilot studies. Psychotherapy, 31, 533–544.
O’Mahoney, P.D. (1982) Psychiatric patient denial of mental illness as a normal process. British
Journal of Medical Psychology, 55, 109–118.
Oddy, M., Coughlan, T., Tyerman, A. & Jenkins, D. (1985) Social adjustment after closed head
injury: a further follow-up seven years after injury. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and
Psychiatry, 48, 564–568.
Ogden, R.M. (1932) Insight. American Journal of Psychology, 44, 350–356.
Ohlsson, S. (1984a) Restructuring revisited. I. Summary and critique of the Gestalt theory of
problems solving. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 25, 65–78.
Ohlsson, S. (1984b) Restructuring revisited. II. An information processing theory of restructur-
ing and insight. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 25, 117–129.
Olmos-de-Paz, T. (1990) Working-through and insight in child psychoanalysis. Melanie Klein
and Object Relations, 8, 99–112.
Orange, W. (1892) Criminal responsibility. In A Dictionary of Psychological Medicine, Vol. 1, Ed.
D. Hack Tuke. London: J. & A. Churchill, pp. 294–320.
Orrell, M.W. & Sahakian, B.J. (1991) Dementia of frontal lobe type. Psychological Medicine, 21,
553–556.
Osgood, C.E. (1964) Method and Theory in Experimental Psychology. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Ott, B.R. & Fogel, B.S. (1992) Measurement of depression in dementia: self vs clinician rating.
International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 7, 899–904.
Ott, B.R., Lafleche, G., Whelihan, W.M., Buongiorno, G.W., Albert, M.S. & Fogel, B.S. (1996a)
Impaired awareness of deficits in Alzheimer disease. Alzheimer Disease and Associated
Disorders, 10, 67–76.
Ott, B.R., Noto, R.B. & Fogel, B.S. (1996b) Apathy and loss of insight in Alzheimer’s disease: A
SPECT imaging study. Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 8, 41–46.
Paillard, J., Michel, F. & Stelmack, G. (1983) Localization without content. A tactile analogue of
‘blind sight’. Archives of Neurology, 40, 548–551.
Pallanti, S., Quercioli, L., Pazzagli, A., Rossi, A., Dell’Osso, L., Pini, S. & Cassano, G.B. (1999)
Awareness of illness and subjective experience of cognitive complaints in patients with bipolar I
and bipolar II disorder. American Journal of Psychiatry, 156, 1094–1096.
316 References
Pini, S., Cassano, G.B., Dell’Osso, L. & Amador, X.F. (2001) Insight into illness in schizophrenia,
schizoaffective disorder and mood disorder with psychotic features. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 158, 122–125.
Plato (1892) Alcibiades, I. In The Dialogues of Plato, vol. II, Ed. & Trans. B. Jowett. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Plato (1987) Charmides. In Plato, Early Socratic Dialogues, Trans. D. Watt. Harmondsworth:
Penguin Press.
Poland, W.S. (1988) Insight and the analytic dyad. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 57, 341–369.
Pollock, G.H. (1981) Reminiscences and insight. In The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, Vol. 36,
Eds. A.J. Solnit, R.S. Eissler, A. Freud, M. Kris & P.B. Neubauer. New Haven: Yale University
Press, pp. 289–305.
Porter, R. (1987) A Social History of Madness. London: Phoenix Giant, Orion Books Ltd.
Porter, R. (1990) Mind-Forg’d Manacles. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books Ltd.
Price, B.H. & Mesulam, M. (1985) Psychiatric manifestation of right hemisphere infarctions.
Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 173, 610–614.
Prichard, J.C. (1835) A Treatise on Insanity and other Disorders Affecting the Mind. London:
Sherwood, Gilbert and Piper.
Prigatano, G.P. (1991) Disturbances of self-awareness of deficit after traumatic brain injury. In
Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 111–126.
Prigatano, G.P. (1996) Behavioral limitations TBI patients tend to underestimate: a replication
and extension to patients with lateralized cerebral dysfunction. Clinical Neuropsychologist, 10,
191–201.
Prigatano, G.P. & Altman, I.M. (1990) Impaired awareness of behavioral limitations after trau-
matic brain injury. Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, 71, 1058–1064.
Prigatano, G.P. & Schacter, D.L. (Eds) (1991) Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Prigatano, G.P., Fordyce, D.J., Zeiner, H.K., Roueche, J.R., Pepping, M. & Wood, B.C. (1986)
Neuropsychological Rehabilitation After Brain Injury. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press.
Prigatano, G.P., Ogano, M. & Amakusa, B. (1997) A cross-cultural study on impaired self-
awareness in Japanese patients with brain dysfunction. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and
Behavioral Neurology, 10, 135–143.
Pulver, S.E. (1992) Psychic change: insight or relationship. International Journal of Psychoanalysis,
73, 199–206.
Pyne, J.M., Bean, D. & Sullivan, G. (2001) Characteristics of patients with schizophrenia who do
not believe they are mentally ill. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 189, 146–153.
Rachman, S.J. & Hodgson, R.J. (1980) Obsessions and Compulsions. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
Reber, A.S. (1993) Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge. An Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Reder, L.M. (1996) Implicit Memory and Metacognition. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Redlich, F.C. & Dorsey, J.F. (1945) Denial of blindness by patients with cerebral disease. Archives
of Neurology and Psychiatry, 53, 407–417.
318 References
Reed, B.R., Jagust, W.J. & Coulter, L. (1993) Anosognosia in Alzheimer’s disease: relationships to
depression, cognitive function, and cerebral perfusion. Journal of Clinical and Experimental
Neuropsychology, 15, 231–244.
Reid, T. (1785/1994) The Works of Thomas Reid, Ed. W. Hamilton (1863). Bristol: Thoemmes Press.
Reid, J.R. & Finesinger, J.E. (1952) The role of insight in psychotherapy. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 108, 726–734.
Reifler, B.V., Larson, E. & Hanley, R. (1982) Coexistence of cognitive impairment and depression
in geriatric outpatients. American Journal of Psychiatry, 139, 623–626.
Reisberg, B., Ferris, S.H., de Leon, M.J. & Crook, T. (1982) The global deterioration scale
for assessment of primary degenerative dementia. American Journal of Psychiatry, 139,
1136–1139.
Reisberg, B., Gordon, B., McCarthy, M., Ferris, S.H. & deLeon, M.J. (1985) Insight and denial
accompanying progressive cognitive decline in normal aging and Alzheimer’s disease. In
Geriatric Psychiatry: Ethical and Legal Issues, Ed. B. Stanley. Washington, DC: American
Psychiatric Press, pp. 38–79.
Rhee, D. (1990) The Tao, psychoanalysis and existential thought. Psychotherapy and Psycho-
somatics, 53, 21–27.
Richfield, J. (1954) An analysis of the concept of insight. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 23, 390–408.
Riley, K.C. (1988) Measurement of dissociation. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 176,
449–450.
Ritter, J. (1972) Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft.
Ritti, A. (1879) Folie avec conscience. In Dictionnaire Encyclopédique des Sciences Médicales,
Vol. 39, Ed. A. Dechambre. Paris: Masson, pp. 307–320.
Roback, H.B. (1971) The comparative influence of insight and non-insight psychotherapies on
therapeutic outcome: a review of the experimental literature. Psychotherapy: Theory, Research
and Practice, 8, 23–25.
Roback, H.B. (1972) Experimental comparison of outcomes in insight- and non-insight-
oriented therapy groups. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 38, 411–417.
Roback, H.B. (1974) Insight: a bridging of the theoretical and research literatures. The Canadian
Psychologist, 15, 61–88.
Roback, H.B. & Abramowitz, S.I. (1979) Insight and hospital adjustment. Canadian Journal of
Psychiatry, 24, 233–236.
Robert, P.H., Clairet, S., Benoit, M., Koutaich, J., Bertogliati, C., Tible, O., Caci, H., Borg, M.,
Brocker, P. & Bedoucha, P. (2002) The apathy inventory: assessment of apathy and awareness
in Alzheimer’s disease, Parkinson’s disease and mild cognitive impairment. International
Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 17, 1099–1105.
Rohde, K., Peskind, E.R. & Raskind, M.A. (1995) Suicide in two patients with Alzheimer’s dis-
ease. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 43, 187–189.
Rose, G. (1878) Neues Wörterbuch der Französischen und Deutschen Sprache. Berlin: Schreiter.
Rossell, S-L., Coakes, J., Shapleske, J., Woodruff, P.W. & David, A.S. (2003) Insight: its relation-
ship with cognitive function, brain volume and symptoms in schizophrenia. Psychological
Medicine, 33, 111–119.
319 References
Roth, M. (1949) Disorders of the body image caused by lesions of the right parietal lobe. Brain,
72, 89–111.
Roth, N. (1944) Unusual types of anosognosia and their relation to the body image. Journal of
Nervous and Mental Disease, 100, 35–43.
Rubens, A.B. & Garrett, M.F. (1991) Anosognosia of linguistic deficits in patients with neuro-
logical deficits. In Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 40–52.
Rubenstein, L.Z., Schairer, C., Wieland, G.D. & Kane, R. (1984) Systematic biases in functional
status assessment of elderly adults: effects of different data sources. Journal of Gerontology, 39,
686–691.
Rubinštejn, S.L. (1960) O Myslení A Spôsobech Jeho Vyskumu. Bratislava: Slovenske Pedagogické
Nakladatelstvo.
Rugg, M.D. (1995) Memory and consciousness: a selective review of issues and data. Neuro-
psychologia, 33, 1131–1141.
Rullier (1815) Faculté. In Dictionnaire Des Sciences Médicales, Vol. 14, Eds. Adelon, Alard, Alibert
et al. Paris: Panckoucke, pp. 389–420.
Russo, R. & Spinnler, H. (1994) Implicit verbal memory in Alzheimer’s disease. Cortex, 30,
359–375.
Ryle, G. (1949/1990) The Concept of Mind. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Rymer, S., Salloway, S., Norton, L., Malloy, P., Correia, S. & Monast, D. (2002) Impaired aware-
ness, behaviour disturbance and caregiver burden in Alzheimer disease. Alzheimer Disease and
Associated Disorders, 16, 248–253.
Samoilov, A., Goldfried, M.R. & Shapiro, D.A. (2000) Coding system for therapeutic focus on
action and insight. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 68, 513–514.
Sampson, H. (1991) Experience and insight in the resolution of transferences. Contemporary
Psychoanalysis, 27, 200–207.
Sanz, M., Constable, G., Lopez-Ibor, I., Kemp, R. & David, A.S. (1998) A comparative study of
insight scales and their relationship to psychopathological and clinical variables. Psychological
Medicine, 28, 437–446.
Sargent, H.D. (1953) The Insight Test. New York: Grune & Stratton.
Sayer, N.A., Sackeim, H.A., Moeller, J.R., Prudic, J., Devanand, D.P., Coleman, E.A. & Kiersky, J.E.
(1993) The relations between observer-rating and self-report of depressive symptomatology.
Psychological Assessment, 5, 350–360.
Schacter, D.L. (1987) Implicit memory: history and current status. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 13, 501–518.
Schacter, D.L. (1990) Toward a cognitive neuropsychology of awareness: implicit knowledge and
anosognosia. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology, 12, 155–178.
Schacter, D.L. (1991) Unawareness of deficit and unawareness of knowledge in patients with
memory disorders. In Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano &
D.L. Schacter. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 127–151.
Schacter, D.L. (1992) Consciousness and awareness in memory and amnesia: critical issues.
In The Neuropsychology of Consciousness, Eds. A.D. Milner & M.D. Rugg. London: Academic
Press, pp. 179–200.
320 References
Schacter, D.L. (1995) Implicit memory: a new frontier for cognitive neuroscience. In The
Cognitive Neurosciences, Ed. M.S. Gazzaniga. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 815–824.
Schacter, D.L. (1999) Implicit vs explicit memory. In The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive
Sciences, Eds. R.A. Wilson & F.C. Keil. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 394–395.
Schacter, D.L., Chiu, C.-Y.P. & Ochsner, K.N. (1993) Implicit memory: a selective review. Annual
Review of Neuroscience, 16, 159–182.
Schmukler, A.G. (1999) Use of insight in child analysis. Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, 54,
339–355.
Schneck, M.K., Reisberg, B. & Ferris, S.H. (1982) An overview of current concepts in Alzheimer’s
disease. American Journal of Psychiatry, 139, 165–173.
Schooler, J.W., Ohlsson, S. & Brooks, K. (1993) Thoughts beyond words: when language over-
shadows insight. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 122, 166–183.
Schooler, J.W., Fallshore, M. & Fiore, S.M. (1995) Epilogue: putting insight into perspective. In
The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
pp. 559–587.
Schwartz, R.C. (1998a) Symptomatology and insight in schizophrenia. Psychological Reports, 82,
227–233.
Schwartz, R.C. (1998b) Insight and illness in chronic schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry,
39, 249–254.
Schwartz, R.C. (2001) Self-awareness in schizophrenia: its relationship to depressive symp-
tomatology and broad psychiatric impairments. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 189,
401–403.
Schwartz, R.C. & Petersen, S. (1999) The relationship between insight and suicidality among
patients with schizophrenia. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 187, 376–378.
Segal, H. (1962) The curative factors in psychoanalysis. International Journal of Psychoanalysis,
43, 212–217.
Segal, H. (1991) Psychoanalyse et thérapeutique. Revue Francoise de Psychoanalyse, 55, 365–376.
Seifert, C.M., Meyer, D.E., Davidson, N., Patalano, A.L. & Yaniv, I. (1995) Demystification
of cognitive insight: opportunistic assimilation and the prepared-mind perspective. In
The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
pp. 65–124.
Seltzer, B., Vasterling, J.J. & Buswell, A. (1995a) Awareness of deficit in Alzheimer’s disease: asso-
ciation with psychiatric symptoms and other disease variables. Journal of Clinical Geropsychology,
1, 79–87.
Seltzer, B., Vasterling, J.J., Hale, M.A. & Khurana, R. (1995b) Unawareness of memory deficit
in Alzheimer’s disease: relation to mood and other disease variables. Neuropsychiatry, Neuro-
psychology and Behavioral Neurology, 8, 176–181.
Seltzer, B., Vasterling, J.J., Yoder, J. & Thompson, K.A. (1997) Awareness of deficit in Alzheimer’s
disease: relation to caregiver burden. The Gerontologist, 37, 20–24.
Sevush, S. (1999) Relationship between denial of memory deficit and dementia severity in
Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and Behavioral Neurology, 12, 88–94.
Sevush, S. & Leve, N. (1993) Denial of memory deficit in Alzheimer’s disease. American Journal
of Psychiatry, 150, 748–751.
321 References
Sevy, S., Nathanson, K., Visweswaraiah, H. & Amador, X. (2004) The relationship between
insight and symptoms in schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 45, 16–19.
Shaw, T.C. (1909) The clinical value of consciousness in disease. Journal of Mental Science, 55,
401–410.
Shengold, L. (1981) Insight as metaphor. In The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, Vol. 36, Eds.
A.J. Solnit, R.S. Eissler, A. Freud, M. Kris & P.B. Neubauer. New Haven: Yale University Press,
pp. 289–305.
Sherer, M., Bergloff, P., Boake, C., High, W. & Levin, E. (1998a) The awareness questionnaire:
factor analysis structure and internal consistency. Brain Injury, 12, 63–68.
Sherer, M., Boake, C., Levin, E., Silver, B.V., Ringholz, G. & High, W.M. (1998b) Characteristics
of impaired awareness after traumatic brain injury. Journal of the International Neuropsychological
Society, 4, 380–387.
Sherer, M., Hart, T. & Nick, T.G. (2003a) Measurement of impaired self-awareness after trau-
matic brain injury: a comparison of the patient competency rating scale and the awareness
questionnaire. Brain Injury, 17, 25–37.
Sherer, M., Hart, T., Nick, T.G., Whyte, J., Thompson, R.N. & Yablon, S.A. (2003b) Early impaired
self-awareness after traumatic brain injury. Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation,
84, 168–176.
Shimamura, A.P. (1986) Priming effects in amnesia: evidence for a dissociable memory function.
Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 38A, 619–644.
Shimamura, A.P. (1994) The neuropsychology of metacognition. In Metacognition.
Knowing about Knowing, Eds. J. Metcalfe & A.P. Shimamura. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp.
253–276.
Shimamura, A.P. & Squire, L.R. (1986) Memory and metamemory: a study of the feeling-
of-knowing phenomenon in amnesic patients. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
Memory and Cognition, 12, 452–460.
Shimamura, A.P., Salmon, D.P., Squire, L.R. & Butters, N. (1987) Memory dysfunction and word
priming in dementia and amnesia. Behavioral Neuroscience, 101, 347–351.
Small, I.F., Messina, J.A. & Small, J.G. (1964) The meaning of hospitalization: a comparison of
attitudes of medical and psychiatric patients. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 139,
575–580.
Small, J.G., Small, I.F. & Hayden, M.P. (1965) Prognosis and changes in attitude. Journal of
Nervous and Mental Disease, 140, 215–217.
Small, M. & Ellis, S. (1996) Denial of hemiplegia: an investigation into the theories of causation.
European Neurology, 36, 353–363.
Smith, C.A., Henderson, V.W., McCleary, C.A., Murdock, G.A. & Buckwalter, J.G. (2000)
Anosognosia and Alzheimer’s disease: the role of depressive symptoms in mediating impaired
insight. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology, 22, 437–444.
Smith, S.M. (1995) Getting into and out of mental ruts: a theory of fixation, incubation and
insight. In The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, pp. 229–251.
Smith, T.E., Hull, J.W. & Santos, L. (1998) The relationship between symptoms and insight in
schizophrenia: a longitudinal perspective. Schizophrenia Research, 33, 63–67.
322 References
Smith, T.E., Hull, J.W., Goodman, M., Hedayat-Harris, A., Willson, D.F., Israel, L.M. & Munich, R.L.
(1999) The relative influences of symptoms, insight and neurocognition on social adjustment in
schizophrenia and schizoaffective disorder. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 187,
102–108.
Smith, T.E., Hull, J.W., Israel, L.M. & Willson, D.F. (2000) Insight, symptoms and neurocognition
in schizophrenia and schizoaffective disorder. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 26, 193–200.
Snaith, R.P., Constantopoulos, A.A., Jardine, M.Y. & McGuffin, P. (1978) A clinical scale for the
self-assessment of irritability. British Journal of Psychiatry, 132, 164–171.
Snow, A.L., Norris, M.P., Doody, R., Molinari, V.A., Orengo, C.A. & Kunik, M.E. (2004) Dementia
deficits scale. Rating self-awareness of deficits. Alzheimer Disease and Associated Disorders, 18,
22–31.
Snow, A.L., Kunik, M.E., Molinari, V.A., Orengo, C.A., Doody, R., Graham, D.P. & Norris, M.P.
(2005) Accuracy of self–reported depression in persons with dementia. Journal of the
American Geriatrics Society, 53, 389–396.
Société Médico-Psychologique (1866) Discussion sur la folie raisonnante, Annales Médico-
Psychologiques, 7, 382–431.
Société Médico-Psychologique (1869/1870) Discussion sur les aliénés avec conscience. Annales
Médico-Psychologiques, 3, 100–109, 110–130, 264–293, 304–310, 466–486.
Soskis, D.A. & Bowers, M.B. (1969) The schizophrenic experience. A follow-up study of attitude
and posthospital adjustment. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 149, 443–449.
Souchay, C., Isingrini, M. & Gil, R. (2002) Alzheimer’s disease and feeling-of-knowing in
episodic memory. Neuropsychologia, 40, 2386–2396.
Spoerl, H.D. (1936) Faculties versus traits: Gall’s solution. Personality and Character, 4,
216–231.
Starkstein, S.E., Fedoroff, J.P., Price, T.R., Leiguarda, R. & Robinson, R.G. (1992) Anosognosia in
patients with cerebrovascular lesions. A study of causative factors. Stroke, 23, 1446–1453.
Starkstein, S.E., Fedoroff, J.P., Price, T.R. & Robinson, R.G. (1993a) Denial of illness scale. A relia-
bility and validity study. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology, and Behavioral Neurology, 6, 93–97.
Starkstein, S.E., Fedoroff, J.P., Price, T.R., Leiguarda, R. & Robinson, R.G. (1993b) Neuro-
psychological deficits in patients with anosognosia. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and
Behavioral Neurology, 6, 43–48.
Starkstein, S.E., Vázquez, S., Migliorelli, R., Tesón, A., Sabe, L. & Leiguarda, R. (1995a) A single-
photon emission computed tomographic study of anosognosia in Alzheimer’s disease. Archives
of Neurology, 52, 415–420.
Starkstein, S.E., Migliorelli, R., Manes, F., Tesón, A., Petracca, G., Chemerinski, E., Sabe, L. &
Leiguarda, R. (1995b) The prevalence and clinical correlates of apathy and irritability in
Alzheimer’s disease. European Journal of Neurology, 2, 540–546.
Starkstein, S.E., Sabe, L., Chemerinski, E., Jason, L. & Leiguarda, R. (1996) Two domains of
anosognosia in Alzheimer’s disease. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 61,
485–490.
Starkstein, S.E., Chemerinski, E., Sabe, L., Kuzis, G., Petracca, G., Tesón, A. & Leiguarda, R.
(1997a) Prospective longitudinal study of depression and anosognosia in Alzheimer’s disease.
British Journal of Psychiatry, 171, 47–52.
323 References
Starkstein, S.E., Sabe, L., Cuerva, A.G., Kuzis, G. & Leiguarda, R. (1997b) Anosognosia and pro-
cedural learning in Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and Behavioral
Neurology, 10, 96–101.
Startup, M. (1996) Insight and cognitive deficits in schizophrenia: evidence for a curvilinear rela-
tionship. Psychological Medicine, 26, 1277–1281.
Startup, M. (1997) Awareness of own and others’ schizophrenic illness. Schizophrenia Research,
26, 203–211.
Steiner, J. (1994) Patient-centered and analyst-centered interpretations: some implications of
containment and countertransference. Psychoanalytic Inquiry, 14, 406–422.
Stengel, E. & Steele, G.D.F. (1946) Unawareness of physical disability (anosognosia). Journal of
Mental Science, 92, 379–388.
Sternbach, O. (1989) Problems of insight in psychoanalysis. Modern Psychoanalysis, 14, 163–170.
Sternberg, R.J. & Davidson, J.E. (Eds) (1995) The Nature of Insight. London: MIT Press.
Strachey, J. (1934) The nature of the therapeutic action of psycho-analysis. International Journal
of Psychoanalysis, 15, 127–159.
Stuss, D.T. (1991) Disturbance of self-awareness after frontal system damage. In Awareness of
Deficit After Brain Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 63–83.
Stuss, D.T. & Benson, D.F. (1986) The Frontal Lobes. New York: Raven Press.
Sunderland, A., Harris, J.E. & Baddeley, A.D. (1983) Do laboratory tests predict everyday
memory? A neuropsychological study. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22,
341–357.
Sunderland, A., Harris, J.E. & Gleave, J. (1984) Memory failures in everyday life following severe
head injury. Journal of Clinical Neuropsychology, 6, 127–142.
Swanson, C.L., Freudenreich, O., McEvoy, J.P., Nelson, L., Kamaraju, L. & Wilson, W.H. (1995)
Insight in schizophrenia and mania. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 183, 752–755.
Takai, A., Uematsu, M., Ueki, H., Sone, K. & Kaiya, H. (1992) Insight and its related factors
in chronic schizophrenic patients: a preliminary study. European Journal of Psychiatry, 6,
159–170.
Taylor, K.E. & Perkins, R.E. (1991) Identity and coping with mental illness in long-stay psychiatric
rehabilitation. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 30, 73–85.
Teri, L. & Wagner, A.W. (1991) Assessment of depression in patients with Alzheimer’s disease:
concordance among informants. Psychology and Aging, 6, 280–285.
Theml, T. & Romero, B. (2001) Selbstbeurteilung von Aufmerksamkeitsdefiziten bei Alzheimer-
Kranken mit sehr leichter Demenz. Zeitschrift für Neuropsychologie, 12, 151–159.
Thompson, K.N., McGorry, P.D. & Harrigan, S.M. (2001) Reduced awareness of illness in first-
episode psychosis. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 42, 498–503.
Tolor, A. & Reznikoff, M. (1960) A new approach to insight: a preliminary report. Journal of
Nervous and Mental Disease, 130, 286–296.
Townsend, J.M. (1975) Cultural conceptions and mental illness: a controlled comparison of
Germany and America. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 160, 409–421.
Tranel, D. & Damasio, A.R. (1988) Non-conscious face recognition in patients with face agnosia.
Behavioural Brain Research, 30, 235–249.
324 References
Wallerstein, R.S. (1983) Some thoughts about insight and psychoanalysis. Israel Journal of
Psychiatry and Related Sciences, 20, 33–43.
Warrington, E.K. & Weiskrantz, L. (1968) New method of testing long-term retention with spe-
cial reference to amnesic patients. Nature, 217, 972–974.
Warrington, E.K. & Weiskrantz, L. (1974) The effect of prior learning on subsequent retention in
amnesic patients. Neuropsychologia, 12, 419–428.
Warrington, E.K. & Weiskrantz, L. (1982) Amnesia: a disconnection syndrome? Neuropsychologia,
20, 233–248.
Watson, R.T. & Heilman, K.M. (1979) Thalamic neglect. Neurology, 29, 690–694.
Wciórka, J. (1988) A clinical typology of schizophrenic patients’ attitudes towards their illness.
Psychopathology, 21, 259–266.
Weiler, M.A., Fleisher, M.M. & McArthur-Campbell, D. (2000) Insight and symptom change in
schizophrenia and other disorders. Schizophrenia Research, 45, 29–36.
Weinstein, E.A. (1991) Anosognosia and denial of illness. In Awareness of Deficit After Brain
Injury, Eds. G.P. Prigatano & D.L. Schacter. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 240–257.
Weinstein, E.A. & Kahn, R.L. (1955) Denial of Illness: Symbolic and Physiological Aspects.
Springfield: Charles C. Thomas.
Weinstein, E.A., Friedland, R.P. & Wagner, E.E. (1994) Denial/unawareness of impairment and
symbolic behavior in Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology and Behavioral
Neurology, 7, 176–184.
Weisberg, R.W. (1992) Metacognition and insight during problem solving: comment on
Metcalfe. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 18, 426–431.
Weisberg, R.W. (1995) Prolegomena to theories of insight in problem solving: a taxonomy of
problems. In The Nature of Insight, Eds. R.J. Sternberg & J.E. Davidson. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, pp. 157–196.
Weisberg, R.W. & Alba, J.W. (1982) Problem solving is not like perception: more on Gestalt the-
ory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 111, 326–330.
Weiskrantz, L. (1988) Some contributions of neuropsychology of vision and memory to the
problem of consciousness. In Consciousness in Contemporary Science, Eds. A.J. Marcel &
E. Bisiach. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 183–199.
Weiskrantz, L. (1990) Blindsight. A Case Study and Implications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wertheimer, M. (1945/1961) Productive Thinking, Ed. M. Wertheimer, enlarged edition. London:
Tavistock Publications.
White, R., Bebbington, P., Pearson, J., Johnson, S. & Ellis, D. (2000) The social context of insight
in schizophrenia. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology, 35, 500–507.
Whitman, J.R. & Duffey, R.F. (1961) The relationship between type of therapy received and a
patient’s perception of his illness. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 133, 288–292.
Willingham, D.B. & Preuss, L. (1995) The death of implicit memory. Psyche, 2(15), http://
psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v2/psyche-2-15-willingham.html
Wilson, M. (1998) Otherness within: aspects of insight in psychoanalysis. Psychoanalytic
Quarterly, 67, 54–77.
Wilson, T.D. & Dunn, E.W. (2004) Self-knowledge: its limits, value, and potential for improve-
ment. Annual Review of Psychology, 55, 493–518.
326 References
Wing, J.K., Cooper, J.E. & Sartorius, N. (1974) Measurement and Classification of Psychiatric
Symptoms. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
World Health Organization (1973) Report of the International Pilot Study of Schizophrenia.
Geneva: WHO.
World Health Organization (1992) The ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioural
Disorders. Geneva: WHO.
Wundt, W. (1886) Éléments de Psychologie Physiologique, Trans. É. Rouvier, 1880, 2nd edn. Paris:
Félix Alcan.
Yen, C-F., Chen, C-S., Yeh, M-L., Yang, S-J., Ke, J-H. & Yen, J-Y. (2003) Changes in insight in
manic episodes and influencing factors. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 44, 404–408.
Young, D.A., Davila, R. & Scher, H. (1993) Unawareness of illness and neuropsychological per-
formance in chronic schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research, 10, 117–124.
Young, D.A., Zakzanis, K.K., Bailey, C., Davila, R., Griese, J., Sartory, G. & Thom, A. (1998)
Further parameters of insight and neuropsychological deficit in schizophrenia and other
chronic mental disease. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 186, 44–50.
Zanetti, O., Vallotti, B., Frisoni, G.B., Geroldi, C., Bianchetti, A., Pasqualetti, P. & Trabucchi, M.
(1999) Insight in dementia: when does it occur? Evidence for a nonlinear relationship between
insight and cognitive status. Journal of Gerontology Series B – Psychological Sciences & Social
Sciences, 54, 100–106.
Zilboorg, G. (1952) The emotional problem and the therapeutic role of insight. Psychoanalytic
Quarterly, 21, 1–24.
Index
‘Aha’ experience 40, 43, 47, 48, 63 compliance with treatment 66, 71, 78,
amnesic syndrome 44, 133, 134, 136, 139, 122–124, 207
144, 146–148, 191, 230, 235, 257 Condillac, E.B. 7, 8, 10, 298
anorexia nervosa 89, 102, 119 Conrad, K. 31, 32, 298
anosognosia 103, 110–142, 144, 148–155, conscience personelle 18, 19
165, 166, 185, 200, 208, 211, 221, 222, conscious awareness system 138, 265
236, 240, 244, 288 consciousness 5, 6, 13, 18–20, 22–25, 30, 32,
Anton, G. 129, 294 34, 35, 50, 131, 136, 145, 146, 149
apperception 7, 32, 34 Cousin, V. 19
Arndt, E. 28, 33, 245, 294 creative insight 41
Aschaffenburg, G. 28, 29, 33, 294
Assessment and Documentation of Dagonet, M.H. 20–23, 33, 299
Psychopathology (AMDP) – insight deductive insight 55
items 73, 79, 80, 85, 93, 94, 98, 104, 112, Delasiauve, L.J.F. 9, 11, 12, 14, 15, 17, 300
117, 120 dementia 27, 44, 65, 128–130, 133, 140,
associationism 10, 34, 37, 38 151–193, 220–225, 235, 239, 257, 264
awareness questionnaire 135, 143 Alzheimer’s disease 162, 166, 167, 189,
191, 192, 258
Babinski, M.J. 129, 294 frontal lobe dementia 166
Baillarger, J.G.F. 14, 22, 295 Huntington’s disease 154, 158, 166, 167,
behaviourism 35 191, 192
Billod, E. 15–17, 32, 33, 296 Parkinson’s disease 158, 166
bipolar affective disorder 80, 83, 86, 95, 97, Pick’s disease 166
99, 100–108, 112, 114, 116, 117, 120, 220, vascular dementia 167, 258
235, 281 denial 65, 69, 120, 124, 125, 129, 130, 134,
blindsight 147, 148 140–144, 152–154, 158, 165, 166, 187,
blindtouch 147, 148 200, 244, 246, 247, 265, 288
body dysmorphic disorder 101, 117, 119 denial of illness questionnaire 88
Brentano, F. 6, 219, 297 depression 92, 94, 95, 100, 108, 114, 116, 117,
Brown Assessment of Beliefs Scale (BABS) 120–122, 143, 157, 161, 162, 165, 183,
90, 100–102, 117, 119 185–189, 193, 220, 257
327
328 Index
mania 27, 29, 31, 94, 99, 101, 105, 112, prognosis 66, 78, 87–90, 201, 286, 289
115–117, 119–121, 125, 190 prosopagnosia 147–149
Maudsley, H. 11, 24–26, 32, 313
Maury, A.L.F. 15, 313 reflecting mirror 56
memory insight questionnaire (MIQ) Reid, T. 10, 318
257–259, 262, 263 right hemisphere 47, 137, 154, 186, 190, 221
metacognition 43–45, 65, 145, 148, 149, 152,
153, 163, 209 scale to assess unawareness of mental
Morel, B.A. 15, 16, 22, 32, 314 disorder (SUMD) 71–73, 79–83, 85–87,
90, 92, 93, 95–100, 102, 105–109,
negative-positive dichotomy 238–239, 111–114, 116, 117, 124, 125
248, 268 schedule for assessing insight (SAI) 71,
neutral insight 51, 229 79–86, 92, 94–97, 99–109, 112–114, 116,
117, 124
‘object’ of insight 41, 45, 129, 156–160, 165, schizoaffective disorder 80, 83, 86, 92, 93,
183, 190, 193, 196, 197, 215, 219–242, 95–117, 124, 221, 235
247–257, 265–269, 271, 273, 274, 277, schizophrenia 31, 32, 59, 77, 80, 83, 86,
281, 283, 284, 286–290, 292 91–117, 121–125, 201, 204, 208,
obsessive-compulsive disorder 19, 27, 89, 90, 220–222, 235, 239, 268, 272, 281,
101, 117–119, 220, 272 283–285, 290
ostensive insight 52, 58, 63, 229, 246 seasonal affective disorder 96, 120
self-appraisal of illness questionnaire (SAIQ)
Parant, V. 22, 23, 25, 33, 245, 316 73, 82, 83, 108, 109
parietal region 137, 139 self-consciousness 6, 7, 130, 152, 155,
partial insight 67, 158 232
patient competency rating scale (PCRS) self-consciousness questionnaire 159
135 self-deception 121, 125, 210
patient’s experience of hospitalization (PEH) Spurzheim, J.G. 10, 11, 22
73 subjective-objective dichotomy 237–238,
phrenology 10, 32 241, 248, 268
Pick, A. 13, 27, 28, 30, 33, 245, 316 suicidality 122, 191
Pico della Mirandola, G. 5, 316
Pinel, Ph. 8–10, 13, 316, 317 temporal lobe 110, 139
Plato 5, 317 transference 54, 56, 58
Positive and Negative Syndrome Scale trial-and-error learning 36, 42
(PANSS) – insight item 72, 79, 80, 82, 83,
86, 93, 95–102, 105–114, 117, 123, 124 unconscious processes 48–53, 56, 57, 62–65,
Present State Examination (PSE) – insight 142, 145, 152, 199, 210, 246
items 67, 72, 79–83, 85, 92, 94, 104, 107,
112, 116 Verstehen 6, 32, 34
Prichard, J.C. 8, 10, 24, 317
problem-solving 37–42, 44, 47 Wertheimer, M. 36, 38, 39, 325
productive thinking 38, 42 Wundt, W. 7, 34, 326