Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

2 Predicate Logic

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 39

Part II: Predicate Logic

Copyright © McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written consent of McGraw-Hill Education.
Summary
 Predicate Logic (First-Order Logic (FOL), Predicate
Calculus)
 The Language of Quantifiers
 Logical Equivalences
 Nested Quantifiers
 Translation from Predicate Logic to English
 Translation from English to Predicate Logic
Section Summary
 Predicates
 Variables
 Quantifiers
 Universal Quantifier
 Existential Quantifier
 Negating Quantifiers
 De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
 Translating English to Logic
Propositional Logic Not Enough
 If we have:
“All men are mortal.”
“Socrates is a man.”

 Does it follow that “Socrates is mortal?”

 Can’t be represented in propositional logic. Need a


language that talks about objects, their properties, and
their relations.
Introducing Predicate Logic
 Predicate logic uses the following new features:
 Variables: x, y, z
 Predicates: P(x), M(x)
 Quantifiers (to be covered later):

 Propositional functions are a generalization of


propositions.
 They contain variables and a predicate, e.g., P(x)
 Variables can be replaced by elements from their
domain.
Propositional Functions
 Propositional functions become propositions (and have truth
values) when their variables are each replaced by a value from
the domain (or bound by a quantifier, as we will see later).
 The statement P(x) is said to be the value of the propositional
function P at x.
 For example, let P(x) denotes “x > 0” and the domain be the
integers. Then:
P(-3) is false.
P(0) is false.
P(3) is true.
 Often the domain is denoted by U. So in this example U is the
integers.
Examples of Propositional
Functions
 Let “x + y = z” be denoted by R(x, y, z) and U (for all three variables) be the
integers. Find these truth values:
R(2,-1,5)
Solution: F
R(3,4,7)
Solution: T
R(x, 3, z)
Solution: Not a Proposition

 Now let “x - y = z” be denoted by Q(x, y, z), with U as the integers. Find these
truth values:
Q(2,-1,3)
Solution: T
Q(3,4,7)
Solution: F
Q(x, 3, z)
Solution: Not a Proposition
Compound Expressions
 Connectives from propositional logic carry over to predicate
logic.
 If P(x) denotes “x > 0,” find these truth values:
P(3) ∨ P(-1) Solution: T
P(3) ∧ P(-1) Solution: F
P(3) → P(-1) Solution: F
P(3) → ¬P(-1) Solution: T
 Expressions with variables are not propositions and therefore do
not have truth values. For example,
P(3) ∧ P(y)
P(x) → P(y)
 When used with quantifiers (to be introduced next), these
expressions (propositional functions) become propositions.
Quantifiers Charles Peirce (1839-1914)

 We need quantifiers to express the meaning of English words


including all and some:
 “All men are Mortal.”
 “Some cats do not have fur.”

 The two most important quantifiers are:


 Universal Quantifier, “For all,” symbol: 
 Existential Quantifier, “There exists,” symbol: 

 We write as in x P(x) and x P(x).


 x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for every x in the domain (or domain
of discourse or universe of discourse).
 x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for some x in the domain.
 The quantifiers are said to bind the variable x in these
expressions.
Universal Quantifier
 x P(x) is read as “For all x, P(x)” or “For every x, P(x)”

Examples:
1) If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then x P(x) is
false.

2) If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the positive integers, then


x P(x) is true.

3) If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then


 x P(x) is false.
Existential Quantifier
 x P(x) is read as “For some x, P(x)”, or as “There is an
x such that P(x),” or “For at least one x, P(x).”

Examples:
1. If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then x P(x) is
true. It is also true if U is the positive integers.

2. If P(x) denotes “x < 0” and U is the positive integers, then


x P(x) is false.

3. If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then


x P(x) is true.
Uniqueness Quantifier
 !x P(x) means that P(x) is true for one and only one x
in the universe of discourse.

 This is commonly expressed in English in the


following equivalent ways:
 “There is a unique x such that P(x).”
 “There is one and only one x such that P(x)”

 Examples:
1. If P(x) denotes “x + 1 = 0” and U is the integers, then
!x P(x) is true.
2. But if P(x) denotes “x > 0,” then !x P(x) is false.
Thinking about Quantifiers
 When the domain of discourse is finite, we can think of
quantification as looping through the elements of the domain.
 To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
 If at every step P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true.
 If at a step P(x) is false, then x P(x) is false and the loop
terminates.
 To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
 If at some step, P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true and the loop
terminates.
 If the loop ends without finding an x for which P(x) is true, then x
P(x) is false.
 Even if the domains are infinite, we can still think of the
quantifiers this fashion, but the loops will not terminate in some
cases.
Properties of Quantifiers
 The truth value of x P(x) and x P(x) depend on both the
propositional function P(x) and on the domain U.
 Examples:
1. If U is the positive integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then x P(x) is true, but x P(x) is false.
2. If U is the negative integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then both x P(x) andx P(x) are true.
3. If U consists of 3, 4, and 5, and P(x) is the statement
“x > 2”, then both x P(x) and x P(x) are true. But if P(x)
is the statement “x < 2”, then both x P(x) andx P(x) are
false.
Precedence of Quantifiers
 The quantifiers  and  have higher precedence than
all the logical operators.

 For example, x P(x) ∨ Q(x) means (x P(x))∨ Q(x).

 x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)) means something different.

 Unfortunately, often people write x P(x) ∨ Q(x) when


they mean x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)).
Translating from English to Logic
Example 1: Translate the following sentence into predicate
logic: “Every student in this class has taken a course in
Discrete Mathematics.”
Solution:
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1: If U is all students in this class, define a
propositional function D(x) denoting “x has taken a course in
Discrete Mathematics” and translate as x D(x).
Solution 2: But if U is all people, also define a propositional
function S(x) denoting “x is a student in this class” and
translate as x (S(x)→ D(x)).
x (S(x) ∧ D(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
All people are students in this class and have studied Discrete
Mathematics.
Translating from English to Logic
Example 2: Translate the following sentence into predicate
logic: “Some student in this class has taken a course in
Discrete Mathematics.”
Solution:
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1: If U is all students in this class, translate as
x D(x)
Solution 2: But if U is all people, then translate as
x (S(x) ∧ D(x))
x (S(x)→ D(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
This will be true when there is someone not in the
class.
Equivalences in Predicate Logic
 Statements involving predicates and quantifiers are
logically equivalent if and only if they have the same
truth value
 for every predicate substituted into these statements
and
 for every domain of discourse used for the variables in
the expressions.

 The notation S ≡T indicates that S and T are logically


equivalent.
 Example: x ¬¬S(x) ≡ x S(x)
Thinking about Quantifiers as
Conjunctions and Disjunctions
 If the domain is finite, a universally quantified proposition is
equivalent to a conjunction of propositions without quantifiers
and an existentially quantified proposition is equivalent to a
disjunction of propositions without quantifiers.

 If U consists of the integers 1,2, and 3:

 Even if the domains are infinite, you can still think of the
quantifiers in this fashion, but the equivalent expressions
without quantifiers will be infinitely long.
Negating Quantified Expressions
 Consider x D(x)
“Every student in your class has taken a course in Discrete
Mathematics.”
Here D(x) is “x has taken a course in Discrete Mathematics”
and the domain is students in your class.

 Negating the original statement gives “It is not the case


that every student in your class has taken Discrete
Mathematics.” This implies that “There is a student in your
class who has not taken Discrete Mathematics.”

Symbolically ¬x D(x) and x ¬D(x) are equivalent


Negating Quantified Expressions
(continued)
 Now Consider x D(x)
“There is a student in this class who has taken a course in
Discrete Mathematics.”
Where D(x) is “x has taken a course in Discrete Mathematics.”

 Negating the original statement gives “It is not the case


that there is a student in this class who has taken Discrete
Mathematics.” This implies that “Every student in this class
has not taken Discrete Mathematics.”

Symbolically ¬ x D(x) and  x ¬D(x) are equivalent


De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
 The rules for negating quantifiers are:

 The reasoning in the table shows that:

 These are important. You will use these.


Translation from English to Logic
Examples:
1. “Some student in this class has visited London.”
Solution: Let L(x) denotes “x has visited London” and
S(x) denotes “x is a student in this class,” and U be all
people. There is a person x having the properties
x (S(x) ∧ L(x)) that x is a student in this class and x has
visited London.
2. “Every student in this class has visited Paris or
London.”
Solution: Add P(x) denoting “x has visited Paris.”
x (S(x)→ (L(x) ∨ P(x))) For every person x, if x is a student in this
Class, then x has visited London or x has
visited Paris.
System Specification Example
 Predicate logic is used for specifying properties that systems must
satisfy.
 For example, translate into predicate logic:
 “Every mail message larger than one megabyte will be compressed.”
 “If a user is active, at least one network link will be available.”

 Decide on predicates and domains (left implicit here) for the variables:
 Let L(m, y) be “Mail message m is larger than y megabytes.”
 Let C(m) denote “Mail message m will be compressed.”
 Let A(u) represent “User u is active.”
 Let S(n, x) represent “Network link n is in state x.

 Now we have:
MorePredicate Calculus Definitions
 The scope of a quantifier is the part of an assertion in
which variables are bound by the quantifier.

Example: x has wide scope

Example: x has narrow scope


Section Summary
 Nested Quantifiers
 Order of Quantifiers
 Translating from Nested Quantifiers into English
 Translating Mathematical Statements into Statements
involving Nested Quantifiers.
 Translated English Sentences into Logical Expressions.
 Negating Nested Quantifiers.
Nested Quantifiers
 Nested quantifiers are often necessary to express the
meaning of sentences in English as well as important
concepts in Computer Science and Mathematics.
Example: “Every real number has an additive inverse”
x y(x + y = 0)
where the domains of x and y are the real numbers.

 We can also think of nested propositional functions:


x y(x + y = 0) can be viewed as x Q(x) where Q(x) is
y P(x, y) where P(x, y) is (x + y = 0).
Thinking of Nested Quantification
 Nested Loops
 To see if xy P (x,y) is true, loop through the values of x :
 At each step, loop through the values for y.
 If for some pair of x and y, P(x,y) is false, then x y P(x,y) is false and
both the outer and inner loop terminate.
x y P(x,y) is true if the outer loop ends after stepping through
each x.

 To see if x y P(x,y) is true, loop through the values of x:


 At each step, loop through the values for y.
 The inner loop ends when a pair x and y is found such that P(x, y) is
true.
 If no y is found such that P(x, y) is true the outer loop terminates as x
y P(x,y) has been shown to be false.
x y P(x,y) is true if the outer loop ends after stepping through
each x.

 If the domains of the variables are infinite, then this process can
not actually be carried out.
Order of Quantifiers
Examples:
1. Let P(x,y) be the statement “x + y = y + x.” Assume
that U is the real numbers. Then xyP(x,y) and
yxP(x,y) have the same truth value.

2. Let Q(x,y) be the statement “x + y = 0.” Assume that


U is the real numbers. Then x yQ(x,y) is true, but
yxQ(x,y) is false.
Questions on Order of Quantifiers
Example 1: Let U be the real numbers,
Define P(x,y) : x × y = 0
What is the truth value of the following:
1. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
2. xyP(x,y)
Answer: True
3. xy P(x,y)
Answer: True
4. xy P(x,y)
Answer: True
Questions on Order of Quantifiers
Example 2: Let U be the real numbers,
Define P(x,y) : x / y = 1
What is the truth value of the following:
1. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
2. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
3. xy P(x,y)
Answer: False
4. xy P(x,y)
Answer: True
Quantifications of Two Variables
Statement When True? When False
P(x,y) is true for every There is a pair x, y for
pair x,y. which P(x,y) is false.

For every x there is a y for There is an x such that


which P(x,y) is true. P(x,y) is false for every y.
There is an x for which For every x there is a y for
P(x,y) is true for every y. which P(x,y) is false.
There is a pair x, y for P(x,y) is false for every
which P(x,y) is true. pair x,y
Translating Nested Quantifiers into
English
Example 1: Translate the statement
x (C(x )∨ y (C(y ) ∧ F(x, y)))
where C(x) is “x has a computer,” and F(x,y) is “x and y are
friends,” and the domain for both x and y consists of all students
in your class.
Solution: Every student in your class has a computer or has a
friend who has a computer.
Example 2: Translate the statement
xy z ((F(x, y)∧ F(x,z) ∧ (y ≠z))→¬F(y,z))
Solution: There is a student none of whose friends are also
friends with each other.
Translating Mathematical
Statements into Predicate Logic
Example : Translate “The sum of two positive integers is always
positive” into a logical expression.

Solution:
1. Rewrite the statement to make the implied quantifiers and
domains explicit:
“For every two integers, if these integers are both positive, then the sum of
these integers is positive.”
2. Introduce the variables x and y, and specify the domain, to obtain:
“For all positive integers x and y, x + y is positive.”
3. The result is:
x y ((x > 0)∧ (y > 0)→ (x + y > 0))
where the domain of both variables consists of all integers
Translating English into Logical
Expressions Example
Example: Use quantifiers to express the statement “There is
a woman who has taken a flight on every airline in the
world.”
Solution:
1. Let P(w,f) be “w has taken f ” and Q(f,a) be “f is a flight on
a.”
2. The domain of w is all women, the domain of f is all flights,
and the domain of a is all airlines.
3. Then the statement can be expressed as:
w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
Questions on Translation from
English
Choose the obvious predicates and express in predicate logic.
Example 1: “Brothers are siblings.”
Solution: x y (B(x,y) → S(x,y))
Example 2: “Siblinghood is symmetric.”
Solution: x y (S(x,y) → S(y,x))
Example 3: “Everybody loves somebody.”
Solution: x y L(x,y)
Example 4: “There is someone who is loved by everyone.”
Solution: y x L(x,y)
Example 5: “There is someone who loves someone.”
Solution: x y L(x,y)
Example 6: “Everyone loves himself”
Solution: x L(x,x)
Negating Nested Quantifiers
Example 1: Recall the logical expression developed one slide back:
w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
Part 1: Use quantifiers to express the statement that “There does not exist a
woman who has taken a flight on every airline in the world.”
Solution: ¬w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
Part 2: Now use De Morgan’s Laws to move the negation as far inwards as
possible.
Solution:
1. ¬w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
2. w ¬ a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for 
3. w  a ¬ f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for 
4. w  a f ¬ (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for 
5. w  a f (¬ P(w,f ) ∨ ¬ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for ∧.
Part 3: Can you translate the result back into English?
Solution:
“For every woman there is an airline such that for all flights, this woman has
not taken that flight or that flight is not on this airline.”

You might also like