Virtue Ethics Aristotle
Virtue Ethics Aristotle
Virtue Ethics Aristotle
OBJECTIVES:
At the end of lecture handout 12, the student will be able to:
INTRODUCTION/OVERVIEW
Aristotle’s ethics has been given the highest regard by Philosophers since time immemorial,
There are three general descriptions that can be said about Aristotle’s ethics: self-
realizationism ,eudaimonistic, and aretaic.
A telos is an end or purpose.
Aristotle does not agree with Plato’s belief in a separate realm of forms. Instead he believes
that rational beings can discover the essences of things and that a being’s essence is its
potential fulfillment.
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics argues that all human beings seek happiness but in
different ways.
True happiness is tied to the purpose or end of human life.
Reason employed in achieving happiness leads to moral and intellectual virtues.
Living in accordance with reason is viewed as vital in self realization or developing one’s
potential.
Aristotle believes that ethics is an inquiry to human good and that wise persons seek an
end that is self-sufficient, final and attainable over one’s life.
Aristotle’s idea of happiness should also be understood in the sense of human flourishing.
This flourishing is attained by the habitual practice of moral and intellectual excellence or
virtues.
Aristotle employs the word hexis to refer to moral virtue. The denotation of this word is an
active state, a condition in which something must actively hold itself in action.
Actions done within reasonable manner means it is not done to excess or deficiency.
Actions done in excess and deficiency are called vice. Virtue lies neither in the vice of
deficiency nor in the vice of excess. It lies in the middle of both. Therefore moral virtue is
the golden mean between the two less desirable extremes.
Aristotle’s Ethics
Most virtue ethics theories take their inspiration from Aristotle who
declared that a virtuous person is someone who has ideal character traits.
Aristotle was born in a small colony of Stagira in Greece. That was
fifteen years after the death of Socrates, the teacher of Plato. His father was
Nichomachus, who happened to be the court of physician during the reign of King
Amyntas. Because of this affiliation, Aristotle became the tutor of Alexander the Great,
who was the grandson of the King. When Aristotle’s father died, he left Stagira and went
to Athens to join the Academy, a famous school of Plato, and became student of Plato
for twenty years. He joined the school at the age of seventeen. His known works that
are related to moral philosophy are: Nicomachean Ethics (NE), Eudemian Ethics(EE)
and the Magna Moralia.
Three general descriptions, which are interrelated, can be used to depict
Aristotle’s ethics. First, his ethical system may be termed “self-realization.” In his
philosophy, when someone acts in line with his nature or end (telos) and thus realizes
his full potentials, he does moral and will be happy. Aristotle’s view is also a type known
as eudaimonistic. As such, it focuses on happiness (eudaimonia), or the good for man,
and how to obtain it. Finally, his moral philosophy is aretaic, or virtue-based. Whereas
act-oriented ethics is focused mainly on what we should do, a virtue ethics is interested
basically in what we should be, that is, the character or the sort of person we should
struggle to become.
3. Virtue as Habit
Aristotle’s idea of happiness should also be understood in the sense of
human flourishing. This flourishing is attained by the habitual practice of moral and
intellectual excellences, or ‘virtues’.
Moral virtue, for Aristotle, is the only practical road to effective action.
The virtuous person, who has a good character, sees truly, judges rightly, and acts
morally.
INTRODUCTION/OVERVIEW
Thomas Aquinas is an Italian philosopher and theologian who ranks among the
most important thinkers of the medieval time period.
Central to the Aquinas ethics is his typology of laws. For him law means an
ordinances of reason for the common good promulgated by someone who has care
of the community.
Obedience to law is viewed as participating in or being in conformity with the pattern
or form.
There is an eternal law which is accessible to human reason because man is part of
the eternal order, part of this law pertains to human conduct
There are laws that refer to all positive laws. It is exact and forceful provisions of
human law and are very helpful.
Human laws that against natural laws are not real laws, and people are not obliges
to obey those unjust laws.
There is a type of law that complements all other types of laws and is disclosed
through sacred text or scriptures and the church which is also directed toward man’s
eternal end.
Man has natural inclinations to some specific goods.
All actions are directed towards ends and that happiness is the final end.-Aquinas
Aquinas defines virtue as” a good habit bearing on activity or a good faculty habit.
Aquinas believes that all actions are directed towards ends and that happiness is
the final end.
Happiness in not equated with pleasure, material possessions, honor or and
sensual good but consists in activities in accordance with virtue.
The autonomous person plays a major role in acquired habits as they involve
consistent and deliberate effort to do an act time and again and despite
obstructions.
Natural law is the aspect of the eternal law which is accessible to human
reason. Because mankind is part of the eternal order, there is a portion of the
eternal law that relates specifically to human conduct. This is the moral law,
the law or order to which people are subject by their nature ordering them to
do good and avoid evil.
Human law refers to the positive laws. Because natural law is too broad to
provide particular guidance, the human law’s precise, positive rules of
behavior are supposed to spell out what the natural law prescribes. This
human law includes the civil and criminal laws, though only those formulated in
the light of practical reason and moral laws. Human laws that are against
natural law are not real laws, and people are not obliged to obey those unjust
laws.
End stands for the agent’s intention. An act might be unjust through its intention.
To intend to direct oneself against a good is clearly immoral. Aquinas gives
murder, lying, and blasphemy as instantiations of this ill will. Correspondingly, a
bad intention can spoil a good act, like giving of alms out of vainglory.
Nonetheless, an intention, no matter how good it may be, cannot redeem a bad
act. For Aquinas theft is intrinsically bad. Hence, stealing to give the poor, as in
the case pf Robin Hood, is an unjust act. In this view, converting to a particular
religion, say Christianity, merely for material gains is an unjust act.
Happiness, Moral Virtues, and Theological Virtues
Aquinas believes that all actions are directed towards ends and that
happiness is the final end. He also thinks that happiness is not equated with pleasure,
material possessions, honor, or any sensual good, but consists in activities in
accordance with virtue. A person needs a moral character cultivated through the habits
of choice to realize real happiness.
Aquinas defines virtue as “a good habit bearing on activity” or a good
faculty-habit. Habits are firm dispositions or “hard to eradicate” qualities that dispose us
to act in a particular manner. Notice that not all habits are virtue, but only those that
incline us towards our good or end.
Aquinas differentiates between acquired and infused habits. The
autonomous will of a person plays a major role in acquired habits as they involve
consistent deliberate effort to do an act time and again and despite obstructions. The
infused virtues, on the other hand, are independent of this process as they are directly
instilled by God in our faculties. These virtues are thus divine gifts which elevate the
activities of those who received them.
Aquinas mentions at least two kinds of infused virtues:
Moral virtues have as their object not God Himself, but activities that are less
virtuous and inferior to the final end. To this kind belong the four basic virtues-
(prudence, fortitude, temperance, and justice)
Theological virtues are concerned directly with God. They provide us with true
knowledge and desire of God and of His will. The virtues of (1) faith which makes
us recognize and believe in the true God, (2) hope makes us wish to be with Him,
and (3) love makes us desire and adore Him. Unlike Aristotle’s virtues, Christian
virtues are not applications of the golden mean between extremes. We ought to
exercise these virtues according to what God demands of us and according to
our capacity as individuals.