Virtue Ethics
Virtue Ethics
Virtue Ethics
CHAPTER V
INTRODUCTION
Real is outside the realm of any human sensory Real is found within our everyday encounter with
experience but can somehow be grasped by one’s objects in the world.
intellect. What makes nature intelligible is its character of having
both form and matter.
Truth and good is in the forms and ideas of Truth and good cannot exist apart from the object and
transcendent. are not independent of our experience.
VIRTUE ETHICS
The particular act of goodness that one does in the world is more important than
any conception of the good that is outside and beyond the realm of experience.
Aristotle’s ethical theory engaging the good in our day-to-day living.
HAPPINESS AND ULTIMATE PURPOSE
ARISTOTLE:
Every act that a person does is directed toward a
particular purpose, aim, or what the Greeks called telos.
There is a purpose where one does something, and for
Aristotle a person’s action manifests a good that she
aspires for.
Aristotle is aware that one does an act not only to achieve
a particular purpose but also believes such purpose can be
utilized for a higher goal or activity, which then can be
used to achieve an even higher purpose and so on.
In other words, the different goods that one pursues form
a hierarchy of teloi.
HAPPINESS AND ULTIMATE PURPOSE
With the condition that there is a hierarchy of telos. Aristotle then asks about the highest
purpose, which is the ultimate good of human being. Aristotle discusses the general criteria
in order for one to recognize the highest good of a man.
Highest good criteria:
1. Final
2. Self-sufficient
According to Aristotle, older individuals would agree that the highest purpose and the
ultimate good of a man is happiness, or for the Greeks, eudaimonia.
Happiness for Aristotle is the only self-sufficient aim that one can aspire for. No amount of
wealth or power can be more fulfilling than having achieved the condition of happiness. One
can imagine a life of being wealthy, powerful and experiencing pleasurable feelings and yet,
such life is still not satisfying without happiness.
HAPPINESS AND ULTIMATE PURPOSE
For Socrates, moral goodness is already within the realm of intellectual excellence. Knowing
the good implies the ability to perform morally virtues acts. For Aristotle, however having
intellectual excellence does not necessarily mean that one already has the capacity of doing
the good. Knowing the good that needs to be done is different from knowing the good that
one needs to accomplish.
VIRTUE AS EXCELLENCE
Rational faculty of a person tells us that she is capable of achieving
two kinds of virtue: moral and intellectual. In discussing moral
virtue, Aristotle says that it is attained by the means of habit. A
morally virtues man for Aristotle is someone who is habitually
determines the good and does the right actions. Moral virtue is
acquired through habit.
Being morally good is a process of getting used to doing the proper
act. The saying “practice makes perfect” can be applied to this
aspect of person.
A moral person habitually chooses the good and consistently does
good deeds. It is in this constant act of choosing and doing the good
that a person is able to form her character.
The Filipino term pag-uugali precisely reflects the meaning of moral
character. One can have mabuting pag-uugali (good character) or
masamang pag-uugali (bad character).
MORAL VIRTUE AND MESOTES
Developing a practical wisdom involves learning from experiences. Knowledge is not inherent to a
person. Knowing the right thing to do when one is confronted by a choice is not easy. One needs to
develop this knowledge by exercising the faculty of practical reason in her daily life.
In attaining practical wisdom, we may intentionally make mistakes on how reason is applied to a
particular moral choice or action. But through this mistakes , we will be able to sustain practical
wisdom to help steer another’s ability to know morally right choices and actions. In other words,
we will be able to mature and grow in the capacity of knowing what to do and living a morally
upright life.
This is why when it comes to life choices, one can seek the advice of elders in the community,
those who gained rich life experiences and practical wisdom, because they would be able to assist
someone’s deliberation.
MORAL VIRTUE
AND MESOTES
When practical wisdom guides the conduct of making
morally right choices and actions, what does it identify
as the proper and right thing to do?
- The answer is MESOTES. Mesotes determine
whether the act applied is not excessive or deficient.
The rightness or wrongness of feelings, passions, and abilities lies in the degree of their application
in a given situation. It is right to get angry at an offensive remark, but it is not right to get angry at
everyone just because you were offended by someone.
A morally virtues person targets mesotes . Mesotes determines whether the act applied is not
excessive or deficient. Targeting the middle entails being immersed in a moral circumstance,
understanding the experience, and eventually developing the knowledge of identifying the proper
way or the mean to address a particular situation.
MORAL VIRTUE AND
MESOTES
Moral virtue, according to Aristotle, is a state of
character which habitually acts according to the middle
measure that practical wisdom identifies as the moral
choice that should be acted upon, given the concrete
situation that presents to the person. The goal of virtue
ethics is to promote the maturity of the character of the
person. Building a good character is a task and
responsibility of a person.
MORAL VIRTUE AND MESOTES
The virtuous person learns from her experiences and therefore develops the capacity to
know the proper way of carrying out her feelings, passions, and actions.
The rational faculties of this person, especially practical wisdom, aid in making a virtuous
person develop a habit of doing good. A moral person in this sense is also someone who is
wise.
Habit is not simply borne out and repetitive and non-thought-of activities in a person. Habits
for Aristotle are products of the constant application of reason in the person’s action.
MORAL VIRTUE AND MESOTES
In the study mentioned wherein children are beginning to consider violence “as a way to
solve problems”, it seems apparent that they would like to think that there is somehow a
“good” in an unjust act since it can become a problem-solver.
If violence becomes a tool by which difficult situations are addressed, then it can be
constructed by children of bearing some positive value. As an act, violence, in itself, is bad.
A person cannot employ violence as if it were a virtue or a middle measure in between vices
of being “deficient” in violence or being “excessive” of the same act.