Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Metamorphoses of citizenship

2011, History of European Ideas

History of European Ideas 37 (2011) 209–210 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect History of European Ideas journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/histeuroideas Editorial Metamorphoses of citizenship Christophe Salvat a,b a b Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, GREQAM, France Robinson College, Cambridge, United Kingdom In memory of Emile Perreau-Saussine. ‘Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override. For this reason justice denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared by others. It does not allow that the sacrifices imposed on a few are outweighed by the larger sum of advantages enjoyed by many. Therefore in a just society the liberties of equal citizenship are taken as settled’ (J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Revised Edition, 1999, 3). In the Kantian well-ordered society imagined by Rawls, we are all equal citizens, all members of a free and democratic State. Citizenship is granted by birth and one only loses it by death. Political, social or moral individual merits are irrelevant when it comes to the principles of justice: all citizens are equally protected by universal rights. According to this view, in a civil society all individuals are citizens but out of it citizenship is an impossibility. In reality, however, citizenship has often proved to be a selective condition in civil societies: until the very recent past equal citizenship could hardly be taken as ‘settled’ in occidental societies. Social, religious, sexual and racial criteria have drawn sharp lines between the insiders and the outsiders of civil society. Birth, wealth, social status, education, religion, language, sex, race, age, and nationality have alternatively or simultaneously been used in man’s history to determine who was entitled to be a full member of the civil society and who was not (with very different consequences in terms of political rights notably). But, at the same time, none of these ‘objective’ criteria (or a combination of them) can fully characterize the idea of citizenship. The progress of democracy over the last two centuries certainly contributed to the extension of citizenship. The importance of liberal philosophers such as John Stuart Mill in Victorian England played a decisive role in the enfranchisement and legal recognition of women and the working classes. Citizenship has become even more inclusive in the 20th century thanks to decolonisation and movements for racial equality lead by such protagonists as Martin Luther King. Equal citizenship is of very recent existence and had often to be fiercely crusaded for. In France, for instance, women only won the right to vote in 1944 because of the prominent role they played during WWII. South Africa’s victory against apartheid, E-mail address: cs495@cam.ac.uk. 0191-6599/$ – see front matter ß 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2010.10.012 which was established after the 1948 election only to be abandoned in 1994, has come with a heavy price for the Black population and its political leaders. Citizenship is not, however, reducible to nationality or to enfranchisement. There is almost always a subjective element in it, a mark of personal achievement, which functions as a moral or a political dubbing from the community and which, therefore, can be used for discriminating purposes. Article 2 of the Reich Citizen Law (known as the Nuremberg Laws) promulgated by Hitler in 1935, for instance, reads that ‘A citizen of the Reich may be only that subject who is German or kindred blood, and who, through his behaviour, shows that he is both desirous and personally fit to serve loyally the German people and the Reich.’ Being of German or Aryan origin is indeed a condition to citizenship, but all subjects of ‘German or kindred blood’ are not necessarily entitled to it. Because they were not ‘fit to serve loyally’ their country, homosexuals, political opponents and disabled people were thus sent, along with the Jews and gypsies, to the Nazi concentration camps. Other forms of civil exclusion have survived the democratisation of our societies. The Fifteenth Amendment of the US constitution, allowing people of colour, the right to vote dates from 1870 but racial segregation was, for instance, only officially declared unconstitutional in 1970. Homosexuality, legalised in most western countries in the 1970s, is still criminalized and severely punished (including labour camps and death) in a number of Muslim countries. According to a survey published in 2007 by the International Gay and Lesbian Association, 40 out of Africa’s 53 countries had laws against homosexuality, some of which had been inherited from their former Christian colons. This is not exclusive to Islam however. In 2002, only 36 states of the USA had repealed their sodomy laws. The U.S. Supreme Court decision Lawrence v. Texas then invalidated the remaining ones. Overall, and despite some noticeable backward steps, one can reasonably conclude that citizenship has become much more equal over the last few centuries. Equal citizenship is surely not ‘settled’ yet but it has become natural to think of it as a natural fact. In 2008, a group of intellectual historians and historians met in Cambridge to discuss citizenship from their own perspectives. The results of some of these stimulating discussions are presented in this special issue. My attention has been caught, in particular, by the social and moral (rather than strictly political) difficulties and resistances met during this process. Bestowing citizenship to a new category of individuals can have very unsettling effects on the 210 C. Salvat / History of European Ideas 37 (2011) 209–210 long-established categories of citizens, who lose de facto their relative specificity. It is indeed never easy to recognise and welcome as your equal those who had been previously considered unworthy to fully belong to the civic community and it often announces (or follows) a social transformation of the society. Catherine Larrère shows that Rousseau’s reason to exclude women from citizenship does not (at least not exclusively) rely on misogyny but on a simple rationale: by accepting women in the public sphere one would irremediably attain to the specificity of the male condition, characterized for Rousseau by courage, civic virtue and heroism. At the core of Rousseau’s political philosophy lays a romantic belief that republics are based on male qualities, which are epitomized by Greek mythical figures. I personally believe that the physical and moral corruption of his masculine ideal – had it been real – signs off for Rousseau the possibility of establishing a republic in modern civilisation. The question is then not whether Rousseau was defending or not women’s condition but if his republican ideal could suffer a feminisation of citizenship. Similarly, bestowing citizenship to members of a minority religion (or of no religion at all) in a deeply religious country comes up against insuperable difficulties. Not only can this affect the authority of the State (which is an expression of God’s will) but it can also undermine the foundations of the current citizenry, which is in large part united through its common faith. Granting citizenship to someone, unlike granting nationality or enfranchisement, has value of moral recognition from the community. It means: ‘you are worthy enough to be one of us’. In the case of 19thcentury Italy, remarkably studied in this issue by Eugenio Biagini, most of the states took care to exclusively limit citizenship to the members of the Roman Catholic Church, sometimes, adds Biagini, to the point where the spiritual intolerance of their constitutions was unrivalled, even by the Pope himself. The short-lived Roman Republic (1849), dreamed by Mazzini, has been of course a noticeable exception, but, to some extent, its failure shows that, despite the influence of thriving republican movements, the Italian society was not ready yet to open up to dissenting Churches. Because most of these restrictions to equal citizenship have been lifted today within western countries, liberals seem confident that the movement towards universal citizenship is on the right track: if one looks back at the progress achieved over the last two centuries, it is – they say – reasonable to hope that we shall all be citizens of the world one day. Has Rousseau then lost his case against Diderot (and Kant)? In a sense yes, but one can argue that the extension of the legal conditions of citizenship is not paramount to a universalization of citizenship. Take the example of the European construction continuously advocated since the 18th century. In many cases, originals plans to extend citizenship to European non-nationals were often balanced out by strong social criteria. European citizenship remained exclusive. This is admirably illustrated by the discussions of the pro-European Association Internationale pour le Progrès des Sciences Sociales, studied here by Christian Müller, which reactivated the republican distinction between active and passive citizens. ‘Respectability, earnestness, education, economic independence, moral yet rational conduct, and masculinity’ were then considered as necessary for applying to a European or trans-national citizenship. Europe will perhaps become a full political entity one day. It will not be an easy process, and the result might sensibly differ from its actual form, but a united Europe will, I think, eventually supersede the Nations it originated from, and similar movements will follow elsewhere in the world. One would be wrong, however, to see in it the advent of universal citizenship. Citizenship can become worldwide but it will never be unconditional. New forms of civil rewards (and hence discriminations or persecutions) will inevitably appear. They already do. As the last resort, the State is the only authority able to name who is a citizen and who is not, who is under its protection and who is not. There is a difference between having the feeling of being a citizen of a country (of Europe or even of the world) and being legally recognised as such. Absence of recognition, reckons Arendt, amounts to persecution. Amongst those who do not benefit today from any civil recognition are refugees. Having been suddenly (and usually unjustly) deprived of their original citizenship without having necessarily gained a proper civil status in their new country, refugees often live in a civil no man’s land. Regaining citizenship is, for them, not only a matter of dignity but of safeness. Amongst different possible solutions to restore their citizenship, repatriation (when possible) offers, explains Katy Long, interesting perspectives as it engages both parts into a new social contract. To conclude this short introduction, I would like to thank all the participants for the quality of their research and for the conviviality of the meeting. I also wish to thank Robinson College and the Centre for History and Economics in Cambridge for their generous financial and organizational support as well as the editor of this journal for the interest he has shown for this project and for his patience throughout the process of the present publication. Finally, it is with immense sadness that I end this conclusion. We all share a sorrow for Emile Perreau-Saussine, who contributed to this workshop, and who was sadly and unexpectedly taken from us last year. None were prepared for his untimely departure and he will be severely missed. This special issue is dedicated to him.