Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Manent and Perreau Saussine on MacIntyre's Aristotelianism

2019, Perspectives on Political Science

Perspectives on Political Science ISSN: 1045-7097 (Print) 1930-5478 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/vpps20 Manent and Perreau-Saussine on MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism Nathan J. Pinkoski To cite this article: Nathan J. Pinkoski (2019) Manent and Perreau-Saussine on MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism, Perspectives on Political Science, 48:2, 125-135, DOI: 10.1080/10457097.2018.1563402 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/10457097.2018.1563402 Published online: 18 Jan 2019. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 49 View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=vpps20 PERSPECTIVES ON POLITICAL SCIENCE 2019, VOL. 48, NO. 2, 125–135 https://doi.org/10.1080/10457097.2018.1563402 REGULAR ARTICLE Manent and Perreau-Saussine on MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism Nathan J. Pinkoski Department of Politics, Princeton University, Princeton, New Jersey, USA ABSTRACT This essay examines Pierre Manent’s and Emile Perreau-Saussine’s critique of Alasdair MacIntyre. Both criticize MacIntyre’s neo-Aristotelianism as an apolitical Aristotelianism, arguing that it is a deficient because it neglects Aristotle’s question of the best regime. In examining MacIntyre’s narrative biography of Justice O’Connor in Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, I show the merit of this critique, in that it obscures what the applications of MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism are in the modern polity. While MacIntyre is not without a strong reply to their objections, I conclude that the deeper, unresolved disagreement MacIntyre has with Manent and Perreau-Saussine is over how to characterize modernity. The purpose of this essay is to develop a little-known critique of Alasdair MacIntyre’s thought, made by  Emile Perreau-Saussine in his 2005 book Alasdair MacIntyre: une biographie intellectuelle, and by Pierre Manent in the preface he wrote to that book.1 For Perreau-Saussine and Manent, MacIntyre develops an ‘apolitical’ Aristotelianism, which does not actually provide guidance for political action.2 This is because he lacks an engagement with the Aristotelian question of the best regime. My aim in this essay is primarily to outline and elevate this critique, arguing that it locates a central vulnerability in MacIntyre’s neo-Aristotelianism. To demonstrate its validity, I apply this critique to MacIntyre’s narrative biography of Justice Sandra Day O’Connor in Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity. As Perreau-Saussine and Manent argue, MacIntyre’s neoAristotelianism has scant resources for guiding action within the modern polity. By elevating this critique, however, I do not pretend that MacIntyre is without a strong reply. Rather, I conclude that the character of his reply discloses the deep—and yet unresolved—disagreement, between MacIntyre on the one hand and Manent and Perreau-Saussine on the other, over the character of modernity. Revolutionary Aristotelianism or Apolitical Aristotelianism? In Alasdair MacIntyre: une biographie intellectuelle, Perreau-Saussine and Pierre Manent charge MacIntyre CONTACT Nathan J. Pinkoski ß 2019 Taylor & Francis Group, LLC pinkoski@princeton.edu with an apolitical Aristotelianism, a charge originating from three conclusions they make about MacIntyre’s interpretation of Aristotle. First, they conclude that MacIntyre’s Aristotle examines human beings as more of a social animal than a political animal. MacIntyre focuses on the moral practices disclosed in sub-political communities—fishing villages, guilds, and monasteries—and contrasts them to the deficient form found in the modern political order, the liberal nation-state.3 Second, MacIntyre makes the core of practical life the virtues and practices of the artisan or professional, not the virtues of the man engaged in civic life.4 Third, MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism is an Aristotelianism of the official opposition; he is silent on why liberalism is so strong politically, does not offer an alternative to liberal governance, and so practically concedes governance to liberalism.5 MacIntyre’s only published discussion of these charges primarily addresses the first two of these conclusions. For MacIntyre, what makes human beings more than animals restricted to a ‘social’ sphere of family and household relationships is that they have a conception of the achievement of goods, as well as of the final or ultimate good. ‘The political dimension of human life,’ MacIntyre writes, ‘receives its expression in those institutionalized forms of deliberation through which human agents are able to direct themselves, and to educate others as to how to direct themselves towards the achievement of those goods and that [final] good.’6 Fishing villages, guilds, and monasteries are engaged in institutionalized forms of Department of Politics, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ 08544, USA. 126 N. J. PINKOSKI deliberation directed toward the achievement of goods. These communities are therefore not social and sub-political, but social and political. For MacIntyre, rational political agents and rational social agents are engaged in the same kind of practice, oriented toward the good. Although MacIntyre departs from Aristotle in favorably treating the practices of artisans and craftsmen, he holds that Aristotle unjustifiably denigrated the practices of artisans and craftsmen.7 By orienting his enquiry around what it means to be a rational social agent, MacIntyre dissolves demarcations between artisans and craftsmen on the one hand, and citizens on the other. He argues for a continuous link between individual, social, and political reasoning. MacIntyre makes the basis of political life the practices of rational agents, including artists or craftsmen, because he holds ‘that the right place to begin political enquiry … is by asking what it is for human beings to act as reflective, practically rational agents and what kind of social order is necessary if they are to engage in shared deliberation about their common goods.’8 In this, the modern liberal state does not provide. It is a political form that cannot give a complete expression to the political dimension of human lives. It restricts effective citizenship to its elites. It does not foster the institutions which would allow ordinary citizens to identify their shared needs and deliberate together about how to achieve the common good.9 For these reasons, MacIntyre opposes the politics of the modern liberal state with his ‘revolutionary’ Aristotelian understanding of political life. Claiming to be radically political and politically radical, MacIntyre’s reconstruction of the politics of the Aristotelian tradition focuses on the basic level of practice.10 Rather than discussing institutions, MacIntyre sees the more important issue in specifying what kinds of political practices need to be encouraged; institutions come after practices. His goal is to subvert liberalism through strategies of Benedictinelike withdrawal and resistance, by fostering the kinds of practices that enable the right kind of character formation, habituation in the virtues, which would permit human agents to work together to achieve the good.11 There is no doubt that MacIntyre offers a powerful and unrelenting philosophical and political critique of liberalism. But one aspect his critique of liberalism does not address is whether he offers a political alternative to liberalism. For Perreau-Saussine and Manent, this is the nature of their third conclusion: MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism is of the official opposition, conceding government to liberalism. They observe that while MacIntyre’s project is to resist and subvert the liberal political regime, he offers no alternative to the liberal political regime. Perreau-Saussine and Manent claim that in spite of MacIntyre’s philosophical and political critique of liberalism and his avowed ‘revolutionary Aristotelianism,’ MacIntyre has acquiesced to the liberal political regime. Why? In his account of MacIntyre’s thought, PerreauSaussine broaches this issue by deploying the unique genre of a philosophical biography that MacIntyre develops. In MacIntyre’s genre of a philosophical biography, it is an error to separate the philosophical arguments from a philosopher’s biography. Instead, the details of biographical life play a role in understanding the narrative of the philosopher’s life, and therefore play a role in understanding why a particular philosopher develops the philosophical arguments they do. To write about a philosopher in MacIntyre’s genre is to explore the relationship between the philosopher’s life and the arguments the philosopher expresses in writing.12 Perreau-Saussine is audacious enough to apply MacIntyre’s genre to an intellectual biography of MacIntyre himself.13 As a part of that intellectual biography, he poses the question: why would MacIntyre, the unrelenting critic of liberalism, voluntarily choose to emigrate from Europe to that commercial republic most faithful to the idea of liberal Enlightenment, the United States of America?14 In Perreau-Saussine’s biography of MacIntyre, May 1968 exposed the internal contradictions of MacIntyre’s thinking, during his teaching at the University of Manchester. When met with students urging political revolution, MacIntyre criticized their political revolutionary actions and advised them to exercise moral moderation in favor of the mission of the university. These students then ridiculed MacIntyre by observing how his own writings, even from several days before, urged political revolution.15 MacIntyre had to choose between morality and political revolution. He chose morality. So he decided to retire from political involvement. A year later, in 1969, he moved to America. MacIntyre’s critique of liberalism, and of America, shifted in emphasis from a primarily political critique to a primarily philosophical critique.16 Once in America, he attacks liberalism for the kinds of philosophical attitudes it promulgates. But tellingly, MacIntyre does not present a political alternative to America. By migrating to the United States in 1969, MacIntyre acquiesces to the rule of liberalism exemplified by the United States. As PERSPECTIVES ON POLITICAL SCIENCE MacIntyre explicitly states, attempts to overthrow liberalism end in ‘terrorism or quasi terrorism.’17 Stalinism and other extremist ideologies are ruled out. MacIntyre is even willing to tolerate alliances with liberal states to defeat these ideologies.18 So with this move to America, Perreau-Saussine believes MacIntyre to henceforth consider liberal politics— exemplified by America—as the default ‘political solution’ for the present.19 MacIntyre’s critique of liberalism shifts from a political proposal for overthrowing liberalism to a critique of liberalism’s ‘generalization,’ the theoretical understanding of freedom informing liberalism.20 It is possible that Perreau-Saussine goes too far in giving a philosophical interpretation of MacIntyre’s biography (even if this is on MacIntyre’s own terms). Nevertheless, MacIntyre clearly argues in writing that all political traditions have failed in the present. Critically, both Marxism and Aristotelianism have failed as political traditions, providing no practical alternative to the political order of liberalism.21 MacIntyre takes care to note—a care that his critics who accuse him of longing for a nostalgic past fail to address—that the Aristotelian polis as a political form based on the exclusion of slaves, women, artisans, and non-Greeks from citizenship. While some neoAristotelian projects attempt to restructure the polis to remedy these exclusions, admitting slaves, women, artisans, and non-Greeks to participate fully in the life of the polis, this would be inconceivable to Aristotle.22 Moreover, attempted reconstructions of Aristotle’s polis fail to attend sufficiently to Aristotle’s own incoherence, since he simultaneously describes a human ergon, while excluding the vast majority of humans from realizing it.23 This exhaustion leaves no practical political alternative to the liberal regime at present. It is here to stay for the foreseeable future, and some of its features, particularly some distinct features of American liberalism, should be defended as part of the present’s default political solution. MacIntyre contends that the American model of free-speech jurisprudence is better than more restrictive Continental models. He defends the utility of state neutrality (the separation of the states from churches and other comprehensive visions of the good), and maintains that the liberal emphasis on toleration is an important value.24 For Perreau-Saussine, this is both a strength and weakness. As a strength, MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism leaves no place for flirtations with radical non-liberal alternatives: Stalinism and fascism must be rejected, as well as dreams for a restoration of an ancien regime, 127 Greek or otherwise.25 The weakness is that MacIntyre does not consider Aristotle’s Politics. By neglecting the analysis of the city, MacIntyre does not take up the theme central to Aristotle’s Politics: the question of the best regime.26 This weakness exposes the limits of MacIntyre’s examination of the moral perfection of practical life extant in social practices. The charge is not that MacIntyre errs in examining these aspects, but that he misses connecting it to a particular political form. As Manent and Perreau-Saussine read Aristotle, the analysis of man and the requirements of moral life points to the particular community he needs in order to realize his perfection. This is the city, the political community par excellence. Hence, to obtain a complete account of human perfection, it is necessary to transition from the Nicomachean Ethics to the Politics.27 The analysis of the city that takes place in the Politics points to different political forms, or regimes, into which the city can be arranged. This in turn poses the question of which regime is best for realizing human perfection. Perreau-Saussine’s charge that MacIntyre ‘radically depoliticizes’ Aristotle is a charge that while MacIntyre analyses man and the requirements of moral life (as they are realized in social practices), he stops short and does not relate it to a political form.28 MacIntyre’s concession that liberalism is the best political regime by default means he does not explicitly justify why it is the best regime. So in emphasizing how MacIntyre reluctantly acquiesces to the liberal political regime, Perreau-Saussine shows that MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism bypasses the question of the best regime, and thereby the work of the Politics. From Aristotle’s point of view, MacIntyre has no political science. For that reason, Perreau-Saussine writes: ‘with MacIntyre, one finds a ‘politics’ and a ‘philosophy;’ I am not certain that one finds a ‘political philosophy.’29 Practical Reasoning, The Problem of Guidance, and the Role of Narratives In brief, the accusation that MacIntyre has no political science or political philosophy is that MacIntyre is not providing practical advice on how to order the political regime or act within the modern polity. While other versions of this accusation have been made, Manent’s and Perreau-Saussine’s version bears directly on the Aristotelian understanding of phronesis or practical reasoning.30 If it is correct, it shows the limits of how MacIntyre’s research program claims to be 128 N. J. PINKOSKI an Aristotelian research program of practical reasoning.31 For Manent and Perreau-Saussine, and the Straussian understanding of Aristotelianism from which they draw, phronesis addresses the critical question of what action itself means, so that we can act well.32 This ‘problem of guidance’ is familiar to Aristotelian scholarship. The point of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle says, is not knowledge but action.33 Readers of the Nicomachean Ethics desire concrete advice about how to act.34 The point, Aristotle writes, is to teach us ‘to become good, since otherwise there would be no benefit from it. It is necessary to examine matters pertaining to actions, that is, how one ought to perform them.’35 To become good requires above all else the virtue of phronesis. Yet Aristotle importantly distinguishes two kinds of phronesis. On the one hand, there is ‘knowing what concerns oneself,’ and on the other, there is phronesis concerned with the city: the political science or political art. While these two kinds of phronesis have the same characteristic, their being is not the same.36 Political science, the kind to examine here, concerns itself with the legislative art on the one hand, and the narrow sense of ‘the political art’ on the other.37 If the task of those who practice the legislative art is to realize the human good, then it is necessary to know how to correct the laws and the rules that currently exist. The ultimate good depends on both kinds of phronesis, including political science, for its realization. It depends therefore on legal reasoning. Those who practice the legislative art, citizens, legislators and judges, shape the laws, and have an important role to play in helping others realize the ultimate good.38 Legislators and judges are seeking concrete advice on how to act. To provide that concrete advice, Aristotle in the Politics connects the legislative art to the political regime. He evaluates the laws by how successfully they conform to the orientation of the regime.39 The laws are designed to serve the regime. For example, consider how Aristotle evaluates the Spartan regime. Sparta has, in Aristotle’s analysis, deviated from the republican principles of the regime by passing bad laws over private property allowing for wealth to be concentrated in the hands of the few.40 The laws produce results that are the opposite of what the goals of the regime are supposed to be. This contradiction make it harder for its citizens to identify the principles governing the regime, so that conflicting principles have no resolution by reference to the regime’s principles. This prepares the way for arbitrary rule of one governing principle against another.41 Thankfully, students of the legislative art, including citizens, have Aristotle’s classical political science to help form the legislative aspect of their phronesis, and help them and their political community avoid arbitrary rule and become good. In this formation, the regime plays a central role. Those who practice the legislative art become good by gaining an awareness of the principles of the regime and directing their actions toward preserving it.42 This addresses Aristotle’s guidance for phronesis, but it only touches upon the problem of guidance. What advice is specific enough to actually be able to guide action? Aristotle uses particular examples to teach us what successful instances of the application of phronesis look like. But his examples are rare, no more than an outline sketch. In Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, MacIntyre fills in this gap in the Aristotelian research program by arguing that we need to acquire instruction in phronesis through learning the narratives of other rational agents. Narratives are important for four reasons. First is that for MacIntyre, our theoretical reasoning is not fully developed. The theoretical generalizations about practical reasoning are only understood adequately through attention to particular cases of practical reasoners. As After Virtue argues, understanding practical reasoning and the agents who engage in practical reasoning is to give due attention to their character as ‘story telling animals.’ The actions of practical reasoners are made intelligible through narratives.43 Once we understand the particular cases, we can apply the theoretical generalizations, but not before. Narratives teach us how to apply the theoretical generalizations to particular cases.44 The second reason is that just as our theoretical reasoning is not yet fully developed, so our practical reasoning is not yet fully developed. The study of particular agents exhibits the relevance of theoretical generalizations to agents engaged in practical reasoning. Narratives are only understood if we have the right theoretical generalizations.45 The third reason is that to learn theoretical and practical reasoning, we require narrative biographies of rational agents and political communities. MacIntyre’s biographies are intended to teach us the importance that the narratives of other rational agents have for understanding practical reasoning.46 Moreover, practical reasoning is not compartmentalized; it includes politics. We need ‘to examine instructive examples of the politics of local community … so as to learn what makes such politics effective and ineffective.’47 MacIntyre’s examples PERSPECTIVES ON POLITICAL SCIENCE attempt to show why effective politics require the virtues, and therefore the conception of practical reasoning offered by the Aristotelian tradition.48 The fourth reason bears upon the lessons of narratives. Some of MacIntyre’s examples, particularly where the politics of local communities are concerned, seem to be examples to emulate and imitate. Yet MacIntyre’s narrative biographies do not serve as hagiography. The study of his narratives indicates imperfections and ways his rational agents failed to realize the good in particular instances.49 A common lesson, MacIntyre suggests in his conclusion, is that all four lives he narrates were incomplete: they failed to achieve perfection.50 To summarize, then, MacIntyre provides narratives to assist in guiding us to the good, by providing particular instances to help us learn phronesis. In doing so, he develops Aristotle’s outline sketch, but in a different way from Perreau-Saussine and Manent. While both interpretations stress the importance of providing ethical guidance for action, the kind of interpretation to which Perreau-Saussine and Manent are closer emphasizes the role the theoretical principles informing the regime must play in guiding action, discerned in the reflections of the regime’s ordinary citizens. For them, MacIntyre omits providing this kind of reflection. While their Aristotelianism can provide guidance on how to act in the polity, MacIntyre’s narratives cannot. Is their assessment of MacIntyre correct? MacIntyre’s Biography of Justice O’Connor One narrative MacIntyre provides is that of Justice Sandra Day O’Connor. In his short biography of Justice O’Connor, MacIntyre considers her as a rational agent engaged in the ranking and ordering of goods. His biography is a brief account of how she ranked and ordered goods throughout her youth, her decision to pursue a legal career, in her decisions as a Supreme Court Justice, and finally in her decision to retire. Although MacIntyre does not explicitly divide his account along the lines Aristotle divides his account of phronesis, MacIntyre’s account does cover the same themes. The issue to bear in mind is whether MacIntyre’s account effectively addresses the problem of guidance. In one respect, MacIntyre’s biography of Justice O’Connor seems a decisive reproach to this claim that MacIntyre does not provide instruction in political science. Here is a biography of someone immersed in the legislative art, as MacIntyre is well aware. 129 Disclosing his intention in providing this biography, he writes: ‘I am concerned to ask what patterns of practical reasoning were exemplified in her choices to think and act as she did in arriving at her decisions on the United States Supreme Court, what it was about her as a rational agent that made her the judge that she was.’51 While a legal theorist might be concerned with how she reasoned with respect to particular legal precedents, MacIntyre hopes to connect her legal reasoning to the broader issue of phronesis and the human good. This hope aligns with the Aristotelian account of phronesis outlined above. The ultimate good depends on politics for its realization. It depends therefore on laws. Judges, as practitioners of legal reasoning, have an important role to play in helping others realize the ultimate good. By paying attention to details outside her legal judgements, MacIntyre describes the phronesis of Justice O’Connor as instances of the other kind of phronesis, distinct from political science: she knows what concerns herself. MacIntyre observes how she ranked the goods of her legal judgements beneath other goods. This is clear from her decision to retire from the Supreme Court at the age of seventy-five for the goods of family and married life.52 Moreover, she had cultivated a series of virtues since an early age: a ‘combination of patience, intelligence, a respect for others, and a certain quiet, but sometimes abrasive relentlessness in the advancement of her legal career and in her life in general is notable.’53 This relentlessness allowed her to gain what she wanted and overcome prejudice against women at various stages throughout her career.54 Although these aspects are favorable evaluations of Justice O’Connor, when MacIntyre turns to the other kind of phronesis, political science, his narrative becomes critical. MacIntyre’s criticisms address Justice O’Connor’s legal reasoning. MacIntyre’s charge is that in her legal reasoning, Justice O’Connor is helped, but ultimately limited, by the background narrative that informs her practical reasoning. The background narrative operating in the life of Justice O’Connor is one where the social order of the United States is engaged on a continuing, though uneven, progress toward democracy, liberty, and equality. That background narrative has beneficial, helpful aspects. It provides some of the resources for opposing discrimination against women, as well as racial discrimination. Yet MacIntyre criticizes this background narrative because it does not address the problems of the United States, stemming from its status as a modern liberal state: it is governed by a plutocracy that prevents effective 130 N. J. PINKOSKI participation in government and restricts the series of choices in elections to a select few.55 Implicit in MacIntyre’s charge is that Justice O’Connor failed to shape the laws in a manner that helped others realize the ultimate good. The critical problem with the way Justice O’Connor reasons is that she sets up a false opposition between theoretical, abstract reasoning on the one hand, and the particularities of social life on the other. In her decisions, Justice O’Connor fled from a ‘Grand Unified Theory,’ rejecting bedrock principles that could conflict with one another.56 Justice O’Connor criticized excessive theoretical abstraction in practical reasoning. For this reason, one sympathetic to an Aristotelian account of practical reasoning might be inclined to praise Justice O’Connor. Yet by criticizing theory, O’Connor breaks from Aristotelian practical reasoning.57 O’Connor’s problem is that she is ‘Burkean.’58 MacIntyre has no fondness for Burke; whenever he charges someone with Burkeanism, it is a sign something has gone wrong. For MacIntyre, Burkeans acknowledge the importance of tradition. Yet denying that theoretical reasoning helps constitute tradition, they elevate tradition while denigrating theoretical reasoning.59 MacIntyre’s criticism of Justice O’Connor relates to his criticism of contemporary Aristotelians. Contemporary Aristotelians, including Martha Nussbaum and Sarah Broadie, reject a ‘Grand End’ view of practical reasoning, where one first needs theoretical knowledge of the ultimate good to act correctly. They are correct in that it is mistaken to think that an agent’s choice shows the virtue of prudence only if it realizes the agent’s grand picture, ‘a true and acceptable account of the good.’60 Yet the camp of contemporary Aristotelians mistakenly argue that a genuine Aristotelian position takes the theoretical conception of the ultimate good as irrelevant to an agent’s practical reasoning. By contrast, MacIntyre argues that turning to a theoretical conception of the ultimate good helps justify the choices human agents make.61 He stresses the practical relevance to the agent of a theoretically grounded conception of the ultimate good.62 This conception of what is ultimately good and best for human beings is required to provide the adequate premises for sound practical reasoning. In the absence of these theoretical principles an agent cannot reason well. Moreover, these theoretical principles serve to supply stability of meaning and thereby objectivity, warding off various forms of ethical relativism.63 For MacIntyre, O’Connor’s legal reasoning is deficient because she does not refer to theoretical principles upon which her legal reasoning must be based. By rejecting theoretical principles, she is guilty of the same mistake as contemporary Aristotelians. But which specific theoretical principles should serve for legal reasoning? By what theoretical principles should O’Connor have made her legal judgements? MacIntyre does not address this. He is more interested in pointing out that she is limited by her political culture, a tradition that failed to understand adequately the role of theory in practical reasoning, than in answering these questions. He does not analyse a particular case and argue that she should have reasoned to a different conclusion than that which she did reach. Instead, MacIntyre observes a general deficiency. He has his eye on a certain good in legal reasoning that Justice O’Connor lacked: attention to the facts of financial, educational, political, and legal inequalities.64 This omission makes MacIntyre’s account paradoxical. He selects for a narrative biography, intended to guide us in phronesis, a life that is immersed in the modern liberal state. Justice O’Connor participates in the modern liberal state. Therefore, she is not someone who practices the forms of resistance that MacIntyre’s revolutionary Aristotelianism advocates. Yet MacIntyre criticizes her for failing to act in her legal judgements within the institutions of the modern liberal state in a way that was conducive to realizing equality. MacIntyre holds that Justice O’Connor should have acted differently (sometimes but not always). But he does not tell us how she should have done so and how she could have reached outcomes that attended to financial, educational, political, and legal inequalities. This is exactly what Perreau-Saussine and Manent identify as MacIntyre’s weakness. He can criticize from the opposing benches, but when it comes to the hard task of government, of identifying what equality is in a particular instance and how it can be pursued in a particular instance, he is silent. Justice O’Connor, on account of her inadequate legal reasoning, is a prisoner of her own political culture. There is no consideration of how she might have reasoned differently. In the absence of this account, MacIntyre effectively consigns those like Justice O’Connor to their prison. He tells them they are in prison, but provides no plan for their escape. He thus concedes governance of the liberal regime to Burkeans.65 MacIntyre does not provide us with the resources to be educated in the legislative aspect of phronesis. How would an account of the regime help? It is the account of the regime that provides an account of the PERSPECTIVES ON POLITICAL SCIENCE ends or purpose of the laws. It connects legislative reasoning to a set of theoretical principles that can then guide phronesis, so that one can act to realize the human good, whether individual or held together in common. In that way, awareness of what the regime is addresses the problem of guidance described above. With that in mind, we can consider the one case for which MacIntyre refers to O’Connor’s specific legal criticisms: Roe v. Wade, the 1973 Supreme Court decision that found first-trimester abortion to be an unqualified constitutional right. MacIntyre’s example is telling, as he selects the one judgement which, when opportunity presented O’Connor with a chance to revise or strike it down she–in spite of her disagreements with the substance of the judgement itself—decided to uphold it in Planned Parenthood v. Casey. As a judge on record against Roe v. Wade, yet upholding it as law, O’Connor dodged the issue of whether the principle behind it was right or wrong. A prisoner of her own culture, she clung unreflectively to tradition, just as one might expect of a Burkean. Yet if we apply Manent’s and Perreau-Saussine’s understanding of political science and prioritize the perspective of the citizen, this example shows that liberal and conservative citizens within that culture thought she had clear alternatives over how to act.66 Liberals and conservatives have a number of theoretical failings, but they do make a claim to the veracity of certain theoretical principles, as MacIntyre notes; moreover, it is their insistence on these principles that leads them to criticize Justice O’Connor.67 Presented in a manner familiar to a ‘naïve’ American citizen, the claim of each faction implicates the principle of equality to which MacIntyre refers. A ‘liberal’ critique of Roe v. Wade argues that the decision sets aside a woman’s capacity to make choices for the sake of technical limitations on privacy rights. Equality features here in women having access to choices that are also available to men. A ‘conservative’ critique of Roe v. Wade argues that by failing to protect the lives of the unborn, the decision asserts that some human lives are worth more than others, and denies legal protection to certain human lives, thereby cementing inequality. 68 The salient point here is that the labeling offered by the ‘naïve’ American citizen discloses an important similarity between the two factions. Both the conservative and the liberal criticisms argue that legal reasoning should take place from established theoretical principles. While both factions dispute which theoretical first principles hold true and how the law should enact these principles, they agree that there are 131 theoretical principles. They hold that those engaged in legal reasoning should recognize these theoretical principles, and those engaged in legal reasoning should act from these theoretical principles. For that reason, the liberal and conservative are closer to representing a genuine Aristotelian research program than either Justice O’Connor or the contemporary Aristotelians. However, both liberal and conservatives do not access these principles directly, leading to another Aristotelian feature of their reasoning. Both claim authority for their actions by referring to legal theoretical principles. In Aristotelian terms, they refuse to discount one kind of phronesis and set legal reasoning aside. From their reference to legal principles, they take an additional step. They evaluate the law—in this case, Roe v. Wade—by how successfully it conforms to the orientation of the regime. For both liberals and conservatives, the issue is resolvable by reference to what kind of theoretically permanent principles are supposed to govern the political regime of the United States. Like Aristotle’s judgement of the Spartan regime, it is by this standard that they judge the American regime. Now, the claim is not that liberals and conservatives are perfect Aristotelians. They reason as partisans, and as partisans, their reasoning is surely incomplete. Yet as partisans, they have a partial sense of what justice in the American regime should be, and argue for it. In that sense, their reasoning with respect to the American regime parallels the kind of judgement to which Aristotle reasons with respect to the Spartan regime. Yet unlike Aristotle, and unlike liberals and conservatives, MacIntyre does not provide an example as to how one should reason with respect to the American regime. MacIntyre’s silence on the specifics of how or where to identify the principles of the regime leaves one with no instruction in how to address this problem, and identify which decisions of O’Connor and other judges were to be welcomed and which were not to be welcomed. In practice, it is an embrace of the status quo. It leaves the legislative art affirming decisions that those with differing theoretical principles find disquieting. Exacerbating the problem of the Spartan regime, it heightens the sense that the governing principles are arbitrary. Moreover, it does not actually advance the human good for those living within the regime. What the liberals and conservatives grasp in these instances is that the question of what the law should be refers to the human good, held together in common. The law forms and shapes human action to 132 N. J. PINKOSKI better achieve the common good. The laws receive their meaning and direction from the theoretical principles provided by the kind of regime in which they operate. The legislative art successfully addresses the human good by how well its judgements correspond to the best regime for realizing the human good. Liberals and conservatives counter contemporary Aristotelianism and guide action, fulfilling an important aspiration of the Aristotelian research program. MacIntyre’s reticence over guiding one to act within the framework of the liberal regime prevents him from providing similar guidance. It is the ordinary liberal and conservative citizen who has intuited Aristotelianism in a way that is more helpful for guiding phronesis than MacIntyre explicitly provides. This is because they connect legal reasoning to the theoretical principles of the regime in which legal reasoning takes place. Liberals and conservatives might have deeper theoretical flaws, but the narrative of Justice O’Connor suggests that it is they, not MacIntyre, who are closer to overcoming Burkeanism in practical reasoning. It is they, not MacIntyre, who have a political science. A reluctance to discuss how to form and shape institutions, notably through reasoning about the laws, hinders the capacity of MacIntyre’s Aristotelian research program to guide action in the modern polity, leading to a perpetuation of the status quo. MacIntyre’s critical narrative of Justice O’Connor, then, vindicates an important aspect of the ‘apolitical’ Aristotelianism charge presented against MacIntyre by PerreauSaussine and Manent. Conclusion: Aristotelianism in the Conflicts of Modernity Although Manent’s and Perreau-Saussine’s critique of MacIntyre deserves wider consideration, my purpose in elevating it is not to conclude with another audacious refutation of MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism. First, MacIntyre himself acknowledges this limitation. His Aristotelianism emphasizes ‘the kind of reflective practice’ that is needed in the modern polity, rather than the actions required within the particular institutions of the modern polity, or which political institutions might better realize the human good.69 Like Marx, MacIntyre offers no ‘blueprint’ for the best regime.70 Providing a blueprint for the best regime beyond references to particular instances of excellent political practices could constrain practices to particular institutions. To provide a blueprint of political institutions in advance threatens to substitute the internal good of the practice for the external good of the institutions. Ultimately, if one acts for the sake of preserving the institution and not for the sake of pursuing the good internal to the practice, it implies a version of conservatism that MacIntyre is loath to adopt.71 Instead, to bring about a political order that realizes the common good, MacIntyre places the emphasis on nascent practices or even practices not yet born. This is how ‘hope’ directs us beyond what empirical facts seem to show.72 Second, it is more fruitful to consider how this dispute over the inapplicability of MacIntyre’s project to the modern polity discloses deeper disagreements over the nature of modernity and liberalism. For MacIntyre, any enquiry that starts from the opinions of ordinary citizens of the dominant cultural and social order, political partisans within the United States, is ‘taking for granted the categories’ (we can also say the institutions) ‘of the present day dominant cultural and social order.’73 It is therefore a misstep to start from the opinion of ordinary citizens. While MacIntyre’s frequent invocations of ‘plain persons’ as an exemplar of reflective practice sound like they might refer to the ordinary citizen, in actual fact they do not. MacIntyre’s considered position must be that the “average denizen of liberal-bourgeois societies is not a plain person,” making the plain person far rarer than a first reading of his work might indicate.74 The social culture of modernity, emotivism, has advanced too far. While many of MacIntyre’s critics think he aims to repeat or restore lost theories and practices of pre-modernity, MacIntyre actually seems to place us in a dramatically more difficult situation, where premodernity does not provide either the practical and theoretical resources necessary to overcome modernity. Therein lies the need for hope. For now, with Aristotelianism exhausted as a political tradition and trusting neither the dominant political institutions nor its inhabitants, the situation is genuinely aporetic. The Aristotelian political science, which would have to start from the opinions of the average denizens, is not possible in modernity. By contrast, Manent and Perreau-Saussine are much more sympathetic to the categorisations of modernity, and indeed defend them explicitly against erosions, which they think are intensified in late modernity.75 This leads to their second deep disagreement with MacIntyre: a “disagreement about the modern state.”76 Manent and Perreau-Saussine are sympathetic to the modern liberal state because they sympathize with its Enlightenment origins. For them, the origins of PERSPECTIVES ON POLITICAL SCIENCE modernity are an attempt to remedy the theologicopolitical problem. Manent defines the theologico-political problem in terms of the political effect of Christian revelation. Modern political development is only comprehensible as a history of the responses to the problems posed by the Church, which claimed to form the perfect political community; in this vision, God determines the best regime.77 Modernity is antitheological or anti-clerical in that it aims to curtail the power of the church over the temporal realm, taking the question of the best regime out of the hands of revelation.78 Defending liberalism as the settlement of this theologico-political problem, Manent and Perreau-Saussine argue for a regime that grants a certain autonomy to the temporal realm and primacy to the political, corresponding to the modern, liberal nation state. They trust the average denizen of the modern liberal state to provide some of the ‘common sense understanding of political things’ for navigating modernity and responding to challenges to the liberal regime. In modernity, therefore, an Aristotelian political science is possible.79 MacIntyre does not address the theologico-political problem.80 His account of the origins of modernity and the Enlightenment is an account of a philosophical project to reject Aristotelian reflective reasoning by rejecting teleology. The ambiguous theoretical basis of this project, individualism or voluntarism, culminates in the social culture of emotivism. Liberalism is complicit in that project, so it cannot be condoned. The choice we face in modernity is a choice for or against voluntarism.81 MacIntyre associates modernity with a philosophical error, and sees that error embodied in liberal social culture. Because MacIntyre is focused exclusively on justifiable practices of reflective reasoning, not sustained in modernity, the impulse of his thought is toward the rejection of the liberalism and suspicion of its denizens. What moderates Manent’s stance toward liberalism and elevates his view of its denizens is his account of modernity. But if Manent states the best case for understanding modernity in terms of the theologicopolitical problem and MacIntyre states the best case for understanding modernity in terms of the development of liberal individualism or voluntarism, it is not yet clear how each can learn from each other: how both the theologico-political problem and the critique of liberal individualism should feature and relate to each other in our understanding of modernity. At stake in this discussion would be the questions of our times: the due given to the perspective of the ordinary 133 citizen, our stance toward liberalism, and what kind of Aristotelianism is now possible. Notes  1. Emile Perreau-Saussine, Alasdair MacIntyre: une biographie intellectuelle (hereafter MBI) (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2005). I thank Roberta L. Bayer, Dominic Burbidge, Alexander Duff, Kelvin Knight, and Geoffrey T. Sigalet for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this essay. 2. Pierre Manent, ‘Preface,’ in MBI, 2. 3. Manent, ‘Preface,’ 2–3; c.f. MBI, 54, 123, 126, 128. 4. Manent, ‘Preface,’ 3; c.f. MBI, 43, 94–95, 126, 128. 5. Manent, ‘Preface,’ 5–6; c.f. MBI, 53, 59, 93, 164. 6. Alasdair MacIntyre, ‘Replies,’ Revue internationale de philosophie 204 (2013), 206. 7. Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (hereafter AV), 3rd Ed (South Bend: University of Notre Dame, 2007), 159; Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (London: Gerald Duckworth & Co. Ltd, 1988), 104. 8. MacIntyre, ‘Replies,’ 206–207. 9. MacIntyre, ‘Replies,’ 204. 10. Kelvin Knight, ‘Revolutionary Aristotelianism,’ in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, edited by Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 34. 11. AV, xvi, 263. Alasdair MacIntyre, ‘An Interview with Giovanna Borrado,’ in The MacIntyre Reader, Edited by Kelvin Knight (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998), 265; ‘How Aristotelianism Can Become Revolutionary: Ethics, Resistance, and Utopia,’ in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, edited by Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 12–13; Knight, ‘Revolutionary Aristotelianism,’ 30, 32-34; Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007), 179–89. 12. See Alasdair MacIntyre, The Tasks of Philosophy. Selected Essays, Vol. I. Cambridge: (Cambridge University Press, 2006), 132. For MacIntyre’s own selfunderstanding of what he had learned from living in the United States, see MacIntyre, ‘An Interview with Giovanna Borrado,’ 266. 13. C.f. Thomas D’Andrea, Tradition, Rationality, and Virtue. The Thought of Alasdair MacIntyre (Aldershot: Ashgate Press, 2006). He confines MacIntyre’s biography to an opening chapter. 14. MBI, 40, 124. 15. MBI, 30. 16. MBI, 91–92. 17. MacIntyre, ‘An Interview with Giovanna Borrado,’ 265. 18. MacIntyre, ‘Politics, Philosophy, and the Common Good,’ in The MacIntyre Reader, edited by Kelvin Knight (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998), 252. 19. MBI, 53. 134 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46. 47. 48. N. J. PINKOSKI MBI, 53. MBI, 47; See also AV, 255. MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, 105. Alasdair MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay on Desire, Practical Reasoning, and Narrative (hereafter ECM) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016), 86; see also MacIntyre, ‘Replies,’ 204. Alasdair MacIntyre, “Toleration and the Goods of Conflict,” Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Vol. II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 205, 207, 214, 220. This is also a weakness of Heideggerian appropriations of Aristotle. See Knight, Aristotelian Philosophy, 88101, 223. MBI, 54, 128. Perreau-Saussine draws from Leo Strauss, The City and Man ((Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), 48-49. Perreau-Saussine contrasts MacIntyre to Hannah Arendt: Arendt drops the Nicomachean Ethics, whereas MacIntyre drops the Politics. MBI, 54. MBI, 54. MBI, 128. Keith Breen, “The State, Compartmentalization and the Turn to Local Community: A Critique of the Political Thought of Alasdair MacIntyre,” The European Legacy 10:5 (2005), 485–501. AV, 146–47. Manent, Preface, 2; Leo Strauss, “An Epilogue,” in Liberalism Ancient and Modern (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), 205–206. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (hereafter EN), trans. by Robert Bartlett and Susan Collins (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011), 1095a5-6. Michael Pakaluk, Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: An Introduction (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005), 15, 210. EN 1103b26-30. EN 1142b24-25. See Leo Strauss, The City and Man, 23–24. €s, Le philosophe et la cite (Paris, See Bodeu 1982), 118–25. €s, ‘Law and Politics 1289a13-15. See also Richard Bodeu the Regime in Aristotle,’ in Essays on the Foundation of Aristotelian Political Science, Ed. by Carnes Lord and David O’Connor (Oxford: University of California Press, 1991), 239. €s, ‘Law and the Regime Politics 1270a18-19. See also Bodeu in Aristotle,’ 240. See also 1324b5-7, where the jumble of laws means their proponents aim at domination. €s, ‘Law and the Regime in Aristotle,’ 241–42. Bodeu Mary Nichols, Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle’s Politics (Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 1992), 123. AV, 216; ECM, 236–37. ECM, 311. ECM, 311. ECM, 244. MacIntyre, ‘Politics, Philosophy, and the Common Good,’ 252. ECM, 176-83, esp. 180, 181. See also MacIntyre, ‘How Aristotelianism Can Become Revolutionary, 17–19. 49. 50. 51. 52. 53. 54. 55. 56. 57. 58. 59. 60. 61. 62. 63. 64. 65. 66. 67. 68. 69. 70. 71. 72. 73. 74. C.f. Vasily Grossman’s double-life in the USSR, one common for every inhabitant of modern society. ECM, 248–49, 264. ECM, 314. ECM, 264. ECM, 264-65. ECM, 265. ECM, 266. ECM, 266. ECM, 268. ECM, 271–72. ECM, 271. See AV, 221-22; D’Andrea, ‘Tradition, Rationality, and Virtue,’ 65-66; Knight, ‘Aristotelian Philosophy,’ 132-33. Sarah Broadie, Ethics with Aristotle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 198. Cited in Alasdair MacIntyre, Ethics and Politics. Selected Essays, Vol. II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 22. MacIntyre characterizes Sarah Broadie as a ‘contemporary Aristotelian.’ She argues that MacIntyre subscribes to the ‘Grand End’ view. MacIntyre, Ethics and Politics, 36. MacIntyre, Ethics and Politics, 26. MacIntyre, The Tasks of Philosophy, 150, 52. ECM, 273. The critique of Justice O’Connor reveals her Burkeanism as a rupture with the practical reasoning of Aristotle. Her Burkean practical reasoning takes its standard of justification by rejecting theory in the name of social, or one might say historical, practice. It thereby disregards theoretical permanencies. In this respect, there is an aspect of MacIntyre’s critique of Burkeanism that aligns with a different critique of Burkeanism, where Burke’s apparent recovery of phronesis by emphasizing practice against theory is in fact a break from Aristotle and the classics. Burke thereby intensifies the crisis of historicism. See Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 311. Yet if MacIntyre concedes governance to Burkeans, he cannot overcome historicism. Strauss, “An Epilogue,” 206–207. ECM, 271–72. Michael Stokes Paulsen and Luke Paulsen, The Constitution: An Introduction (New York: Basic Books 2015), 270-76. C.f. Michael Stokes Paulsen, ‘The Worst Constitutional Decision of All Time,’ Notre Dame Law Review 78:4 (May 2003), 998–99. MacIntyre, “Replies”, 204. Knight, ‘Revolutionary Aristotelianism,’ 34. C.f. David Leopold, The Young Karl Marx: German Philosophy, Modern Politics, and Human Flourishing (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 27879; 288-93. Knight, ‘Revolutionary Aristotelianism,’ 25–27. MacIntyre, ‘How Aristotelianism Can Become Revolutionary,’ 19. MacIntyre, “Replies”, 206. Ronald Beiner, Political Philosophy: What it is and Why It Matters (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), 188. PERSPECTIVES ON POLITICAL SCIENCE 75. 76. 77. 78. 79. See Manent, Cours familier de philosophie politique (Paris: Gallimard, 2001), 23–37; Situation de la France (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 2015), 10-11, 84, 96; Perreau-Saussine, Catholicisme et democratie: une  histoire de la pensee politique (Paris: Les Editions du Cerf, 2011), 248–56. MacIntyre, “Replies,” 205. MBI, 115; Manent, Histoire intellectuelle du liberalisme (Paris: Pluriel 2011), 20–21, 34–35. MBI, 116. C.f. Leo Strauss, The City and Man, 11–12, 25; “An Epilogue,” 208-10. 80. 81. 135 MBI, 116-117, 126; see also Aristide Tessitore, “MacIntyre and Aristotle on the Foundation of Virtue,” in Aristotle and Modern Politics: The Persistence of Political Philosophy (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2002), 153. AV, 109–120; Christopher Lutz, Reading Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue (London: Continuum Press, 2012), 44–46. ORCID Nathan J. Pinkoski http://orcid.org/0000-0001-5082-5922