Abstract
This paper is a contribution to graded model theory, in the context of mathematical fuzzy logic. We study characterizations of classes of graded structures in terms of the syntactic form of their first-order axiomatization. We focus on classes given by universal and universal–existential sentences. In particular, we prove two amalgamation results using the technique of diagrams in the setting of structures valued on a finite MTL-algebra, from which analogues of the Łoś–Tarski and the Chang–Łoś–Suszko preservation theorems follow.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.Avoid common mistakes on your manuscript.
1 Introduction
Graded model theory is the generalized study, in mathematical fuzzy logic (MFL), of the construction and classification of graded structures. The field was properly started in Hájek and Cintula (2006) and has received renewed attention in recent years (Badia and Noguera 2018a; Bagheri and Moniri 2013; Cintula and Metcalfe 2013; Cintula et al. 2015; Costa and Dellunde 2017; Dellunde 2011, 2014). Part of the programme of graded model theory is to find non-classical analogues of results from classical model theory (e.g. Hodges 1993; Sacks 1972; Chang and Keisler 1973). This will not only provide generalizations of classical theorems but will also provide insight into what avenues of research are particular to classical first-order logic and do not make sense in a broader setting.
On the other hand, classical model theory was developed together with the analysis of some very relevant mathematical structures. In consequence, its principal results provided a logical interpretation of such structures. Thus, if we want model theory’s idiosyncratic interaction with other disciplines to be preserved, the redefinition of the fundamental notions of graded model theory cannot be obtained from directly fuzzifying every classical concept. Quite the contrary, the experience acquired in the study of different structures, the results obtained using specific classes of structures, and the potential overlaps with other areas should determine the light the main concepts of graded model theory have to be defined in. It is in this way that several fundamental concepts of the model theory of mathematical fuzzy logic have already appeared in the literature.
The goal of this paper is to give syntactic characterizations of classes of graded structures; more precisely, we want to study which kinds of formulas can be used to axiomatize certain classes of structures based on finite (expansions of) \(\mathrm {MTL}\)-chains. Traditional examples of such sort of results are preservation theorems in classical model theory, which, in general, can be obtained as consequences of certain amalgamation properties (cf. Hodges 1993). We provide some amalgamation results using the technique of diagrams which will allow us to establish analogues of the Łoś–Tarski preservation theorem (Hodges 1993, Theorem 6.5.4) and the Chang–Łoś–Suszko theorem (Hodges 1993, Theorem 6.5.9).
This is not the first work that addresses a model-theoretic study of the preservation and characterization of classes of fuzzy structures. Indeed, Bagheri and Moniri (2013) have obtained results for the particular case of continuous model theory by working over the standard \(\mathrm {MV}\)-algebra and with a predicate language enriched with a truth-constant for each element of . In that context, they characterize universal theories in terms of the preservation under substructures (Bagheri and Moniri 2013, Prop. 5.1) and prove versions of the Tarski–Vaught theorem (Bagheri and Moniri 2013, Prop. 4.6) and of the Chang–Łoś–Suszko theorem (Bagheri and Moniri 2013, Prop. 5.5).
The connection between classical model theory and the study of classes of fuzzy structures needs to be clarified. Namely, as explained and developed in previous papers (Cintula et al. 2009; Dellunde et al. 2016, 2018), there is a translation of fuzzy structures into classical many-sorted structures, more precisely, two-sorted structures with one sort for the first-order domain and another accounting for truth-values in the algebra. Such connection certainly allows to directly import to the fuzzy setting several classical results, but, as already noted in the mentioned papers, it does not go a long way. Indeed, the translation does not preserve the syntactical complexity of sentences (regarding quantifiers), and hence, it cannot be used for syntactically sensitive results, such as those studied in the present paper.
The paper is structured as follows: in Sect. 1, we introduce the syntax and semantics of fuzzy predicate logics. In Sect. 2, several fuzzy model-theoretic notions such as homomorphisms or the method of diagrams are presented. In Sect. 3, we study the preservation of universal formulas, obtain an existential form of amalgamation and derive from it an analogue of the Łoś–Tarski theorem. In Sect. 4, we study classes given by universal-existential sentences by showing that such formulas are preserved under unions of chains, obtaining another corresponding amalgamation result and a version of Chang–Łoś–Suszko preservation theorem. We end with some concluding remarks and suggestions for lines of further research.
2 Preliminaries
In this section, we introduce the syntax and semantics of fuzzy predicate logics, and recall the basic results on diagrams we will use in the paper. We use the notation and definitions of the Handbook of Mathematical Fuzzy Logic (Cintula et al. 2011).
Definition 1
(Syntax of Predicate Languages) A predicate language\(\mathcal {P}\) is a triple \(\left\langle Pred_{\mathcal {P}},Func_{\mathcal {P}},Ar_{\mathcal {P}} \right\rangle \), where \(Pred_{\mathcal {P}}\) is a non-empty set of predicate symbols, \(Func_{\mathcal {P}}\) is a set of function symbols (disjoint from \(Pred_{\mathcal {P}}\)), and \(Ar_{\mathcal {P}}\) represents the arity function, which assigns a natural number to each predicate symbol or function symbol. We call this natural number the arity of the symbol. The predicate symbols with arity zero are called truth-constants, while the function symbols whose arity is zero are named object constants (constants for short).
\(\mathcal {P}\)-terms, \(\mathcal {P}\)-formulas, \(\forall _n\) and \(\exists _n\)\(\mathcal {P}\)-formulas, and the notions of free occurrence of a variable, open formula, substitutability, and sentence are defined as in classical predicate logic. A theory is a set of sentences. When it is clear from the context, we will refer to \(\mathcal {P}\)-terms and \(\mathcal {P}\)-formulas simply as terms and formulas.
Let MTL stand for the monoidal t-norm based logic introduced by Esteva and Godo (2001). Throughout the paper, we consider the predicate logic MTL\(\forall \) [for a definition of the axiomatic system for MTL\(\forall \) we refer the reader to Cintula et al. (2011, Def. 5.1.2, Ch. I)]. Let us recall that the deduction rules of MTL\(\forall \) are those of MTL and the rule of generalization: from \(\varphi \) infer \((\forall x)\varphi \). The definitions of proof and provability are analogous to the classical ones. We denote by \(\varPhi \vdash _{\text {MTL}\forall }\varphi \) the fact that \(\varphi \) is provable in MTL\(\forall \) from the set of formulas \(\varPhi \). For the sake of clarity, when it is clear from the context we will write \(\vdash \) to refer to \(\vdash _{\text {MTL}\forall }\). The algebraic semantics of MTL\(\forall \) are based on \(\mathrm {MTL}\)-algebras (Esteva and Godo 2001).
\({\varvec{A}}\) is called an \(\mathrm {MTL}\)-chain if its underlying lattice is linearly ordered. Since it is customary to consider fuzzy logics in languages expanding that of \(\mathrm {MTL}\), henceforth, we will confine our attention to algebras which are expansions of \(\mathrm {MTL}\)-chains of such kind and just call them chains.
Definition 2
(Semantics of Predicate Fuzzy Logics [Cintula et al. 2011, Def. 5.2.1, Ch. I]) Consider a predicate language \(\mathcal {P}=\langle Pred_{\mathcal {P}}, Func_{\mathcal {P}}, Ar_{\mathcal {P}} \rangle \) and let A be a chain. We define an \({{\varvec{A}}}\)-structure\({\mathbf {M}}\) for \(\mathcal {P}\) as a pair \({\mathfrak {{M}}} = \langle {{\varvec{A}},\mathbf M}\rangle \) where
where M is a non-empty domain, \(P_{{\mathbf {M}}}\) is an n-ary fuzzy relation for each n-ary predicate symbol, i.e. a function from \(M^n\) to A, identified with an element of \({{\varvec{A}}}\) if \(n=0\); and \(F_{{\mathbf {M}}}\) is a function from \(M^n\) to M, identified with an element of M if \(n=0\). As usual, if \({\mathbf {M}}\) is an \({{\varvec{A}}}\)-structure for \(\mathcal {P}\), an \({\mathbf {M}}\)-evaluation of the object variables is a mapping v assigning to each object variable an element of M. The set of all object variables is denoted by Var. If v is an \({\mathbf {M}}\)-evaluation, x is an object variable and \(d\in M\), we denote by \(v[x\mapsto d]\) the \({\mathbf {M}}\)-evaluation so that \(v[x\mapsto d](x)=d\) and \(v[x\mapsto d](y)=v(y)\) for y an object variable such that \(y\not =x\). If \({\mathbf {M}}\) is an \({{\varvec{A}}}\)-structure and v is an \({\mathbf {M}}\)-evaluation, we define the values of terms and the truth-values of formulas in M for an evaluation v recursively as follows:
-
\(\Vert x\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=v(x)\);
-
\(\Vert F(t_1,\ldots ,t_n)\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=F_{\mathbf {M}}(\Vert t_1\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v},\ldots ,\Vert t_n\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v})\), for \(F\in Func\);
-
\(\Vert P(t_1,\ldots ,t_n)\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=P_{\mathbf {M}}(\Vert t_1\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v},\ldots ,\Vert t_n\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v})\), for \(P\in Pred\);
-
\(\Vert c(\varphi _1,\ldots ,\varphi _n)\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=\circ ^{\varvec{A}}(\Vert \varphi _1\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v},\ldots ,\Vert \varphi _n\Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v})\), for \(\circ \in \mathcal {L}\);
-
\(\Vert (\forall x)\varphi \Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=inf_{\le ^{\varvec{A}}}\{\Vert \varphi \Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v[x\rightarrow d]}\mid d\in M\}\);
-
\(\Vert (\exists x)\varphi \Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=sup_{\le ^{\varvec{A}}}\{\Vert \varphi \Vert ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf {M},v[x\rightarrow d]}\mid d\in M\}\).
For a set of formulas \(\varPhi \), we write \(\Vert \varPhi \Vert ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=1\), if \(\Vert \varphi \Vert ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=1\) for every \(\varphi \in \varPhi \). We denote by \(\Vert \varphi \Vert ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}}=1\) the fact that \(\Vert \varphi \Vert ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M},v}=1\) for all \(\mathbf {M}\)-evaluations v. We say that \(\langle \varvec{A},\mathbf {M}\rangle \) is a model of a set of formulas\(\varPhi \), if \(\Vert \varphi \Vert ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}}=1\) for any \(\varphi \in \varPhi \). Sometimes, we will denote by \(\overrightarrow{x}\) a sequence of variables \(x_1,\ldots ,x_n\) (and the same with sequences \(\overrightarrow{d}\) of elements of the domain). Given a structure \(\langle \varvec{A},\mathbf {M}\rangle \) and a formula \(\varphi (\overrightarrow{x})\), we say that \(\overrightarrow{d}\subseteq M\)satisfies\(\varphi (\overrightarrow{x})\) (or that \(\varphi (\overrightarrow{x})\) is satisfied by \(\overrightarrow{d}\)) if \(\left\| {\varphi (\overrightarrow{x})}\right\| ^{{{{\varvec{A}}}}}_{\mathbf{M },v[\overrightarrow{x}\rightarrow \overrightarrow{d}]}=\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\) for any \(\mathbf M \)-evaluation v (also written \(\left\| {\varphi [\overrightarrow{d}]}\right\| ^{{{{\varvec{A}}}}}_\mathbf{M }=\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\)); for the sake of clarity, we will use also the notation \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \models \varphi [\overrightarrow{d}]\) when is needed. Two theories T and U are said to be 1-equivalent if a structure is a model of T if it is also a model of U (in the case where T and U are singletons of formulas, we say that these formulas are 1-equivalent).
Given a set of sentences \(\varSigma \), and a sentence \(\phi \), we denote by \(\varSigma \models _{\varvec{A}}\phi \) the fact that every \(\varvec{A}\)-model of \(\varSigma \) is also an \(\varvec{A}\)-model of \(\phi \). We focus on classes of structures over a fixed finite chain A whose set of elements is denoted by \(\{a_1,\ldots ,a_k\}\). Such restriction is due to the fact that dropping finiteness can cause to lose compactness, which is an essential element of our proofs. However, the results will still be quite encompassing in practice. Indeed, for instance, prominent examples of weighted structures in computer science are valued over finite chains. Structures over a fixed finite chain A have two important properties: they are witnessed (the values of the quantifiers are maxima and minima achieved in particular instances) and have the compactness property, both for satisfiability and for consequence (see e.g. Dellunde 2014).
Proposition 1
Let \(\varvec{A}\) be a fixed finite chain. For every set of sentences \(\varSigma \cup \{\alpha \}\), the following holds:
-
1.
If every finite subset \(\varSigma _0\subseteq \varSigma \) has a model \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M }_{\varSigma _0}\rangle \), then \(\varSigma \) has a model \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{N }\rangle \).
-
2.
If \(\varSigma \models _{\varvec{A}} \alpha \), then there is a finite subset \(\varSigma _0\subseteq \varSigma \) such that \(\varSigma _0 \models _{\varvec{A}} \alpha \).
From now on, we refer to A-structures simply as structures (or as \(\mathcal {P}\)-structures if we need to specify the language). For the remainder of the article, let us assume that we have a crisp identity \(\approx \) in the language.
Definition 3
Let \(\mathcal {P}\) be a predicate language, \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) and \(\langle {\varvec{B}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \) structures for \({{\mathcal {P}}}\), f a mapping from \({{\varvec{A}}}\) to \({\varvec{B}}\) and g a mapping from M to N. The pair \(\langle f,g\rangle \) is said to be a strong homomorphism from \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) to \(\langle {\varvec{B}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \) if f is an algebraic homomorphism and for every n-ary function symbol \(F\in \mathcal {P}\) and \(d_1,\ldots ,d_n\in M\),
and for every n-ary predicate symbol \(P\in \mathcal {P}\) and \(d_1,\ldots ,d_n\in M,\)
A strong homomorphism \(\langle f,g\rangle \) is said to be elementary if we have, for every \({{\mathcal {P}}}\)-formula \(\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) and \(d_1,\ldots ,d_n\in M\),
Let \(\langle f,g\rangle \) be a strong homomorphism from \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) to \(\langle {{\varvec{B}}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \), we say that \(\langle f,g\rangle \) is an embedding from \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) to \(\langle {{\varvec{B}}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \) if both functions f and g are injective, and we say that \(\langle f,g\rangle \) is an isomorphism from \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) to \(\langle {{\varvec{B}}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \) if \(\langle f,g\rangle \) is an embedding and both functions f and g are surjective. For a general study of different kinds of homomorphisms and the formulas they preserve, we refer to Dellunde et al. (2016).
Later in the article, we will use diagram techniques. We present here some corollaries of the results obtained in Dellunde (2011). Given a language \(\mathcal {P}\), we start by introducing three different expansions adding either a new truth-constant for each element of the algebra, or new object constants. For any element a of \({\varvec{A}}\), we will use the truth-constant \(\overline{a}\) to denote it. When \(a=\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\) or \(a=\overline{0}^{\varvec{A}}\), then \(\overline{a}=\overline{1}\) or \(\overline{a}=\overline{0}\), respectively.
Definition 4
Given a predicate language \(\mathcal {P}\), we expand it by adding an individual constant symbol \(c_m\) for every \(m\in M\), and denote it by \(\mathcal {P}^{\mathbf {M}}\). If \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf {M}\rangle \) is a \(\mathcal {P}^{\mathbf {M}}\)-structure, we denote by \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf {M}^\sharp \rangle \) the expansion of the structure \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf {M}\rangle \) to \(\mathcal {P}^{\mathbf {M}}\), where for every \(m\in M\), \((c_m)_\mathbf{M ^\sharp }=m\).
Definition 5
Given a predicate language \(\mathcal {P}\), we expand it by adding a truth-constant symbol \(\overline{a}\) for every \(a \in A\), and denote it by \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\). When we expand the language \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\) further by adding an individual constant symbol \(c_m\) for every \(m\in M\), we will denote it by \(\mathcal {P^{\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle }}\).
Definition 6
Let \(\mathcal {P}\) be a predicate language and \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) a \(\mathcal {P}\)-structure. We define the following sets of \(\mathcal {P^{\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle }}\)-sentences:
whereas \(Diag ({{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M })\) is the subset of \(ElDiag ({{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M })\) containing all formulas \(\sigma \leftrightarrow \overline{a}\) where \(\sigma \) is quantifier-free.
Following the same lines of the proof of Dellunde (2011, Prop. 32), we can obtain a characterization of strong and elementary embeddings between two \(\mathcal {P}\)-structures over a chain \({\varvec{A}}\).
Corollary 2
Let \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) and \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \) be two \(\mathcal {P}\)-structures for \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\). The following are equivalent:
-
1.
There is an expansion of \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \) that is a model of Diag\(({{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M })\) (ElDiag\(({{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M })\), respectively).
-
2.
There is a mapping \(g:M \rightarrow N\) such that \(\langle Id_{{{\varvec{A}}}},g \rangle \) is a strong (elementary, respectively) embedding from \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) into \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},{\mathbf {N}}\rangle \).
3 Universal classes
In this section, we prove a result on existential amalgamation (Proposition 4) from which we extract a Łoś–Tarski preservation theorem for universal theories (Theorem 5) and a characterization of universal classes of structures (Theorem 6). Relevant structures in computer science are axiomatized by sets of universal formulas; one prominent example is the class of weighted graphs. Particular versions of the above-mentioned results appeared for Ł\(\forall \) in Spada (2009). In the context of fuzzy logic programming, Gerla (2005) studied universal formulas with relation to Herbrand interpretations.
For the upcoming results, we need to recall the notion of substructure.
Definition 7
(Substructure) Let \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M }\rangle \) and \(\langle {\varvec{B}},\mathbf{N }\rangle \) be \(\mathcal {P}\)-structures. We say that \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M }\rangle \) is a substructure of \(\langle {\varvec{B}},\mathbf{N }\rangle \) if:
-
(1)
\({{\varvec{A}}}\) is a subalgebra of \({\varvec{B}};\)
-
(2)
\(M\subseteq N;\)
-
(3)
for any n-ary function symbol \(F\in \mathcal {P}\) and elements \(d_1,\ldots ,d_n\in M\), we have
$$\begin{aligned} F_{\mathbf{M }}(d_1,\ldots ,d_n)=F_{\mathbf{N }}(d_1,\ldots ,d_n); \end{aligned}$$ -
(4)
for any n-ary predicate symbol \(P\in \mathcal {P}\) and elements \(d_1,\ldots ,d_n\in M\), we have
$$\begin{aligned} P_{\mathbf{M }}(d_1,\ldots ,d_n)=P_{\mathbf{N }}(d_1,\ldots ,d_n). \end{aligned}$$
Remark that \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf M \rangle \) is a substructure of \(\langle {{\varvec{B}}},\mathbf N \rangle \) if and only if conditions (1)–(3) are satisfied and, instead of (4), the following condition holds: for every quantifier-free formula \(\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) and any elements \(d_1,\ldots ,d_n\in M\),
With this notion at hand, we can define a corresponding closure property for classes of structures.
Definition 8
(Class Closed Under Substructures) Let \({\mathbb {K}}\) be a class of \(\mathcal {P}\)-structures. We say that \({\mathbb {K}}\) is closed under substructures if, for any structure \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M }\rangle \in {\mathbb {K}}\),
Since our characterizations will be based on axiomatizability of classes, we need to recall the definition of elementary class of structures.
Definition 9
[Elementary Class (Burris and Sankappanavar 1981, Def. 2.15)] A class \({\mathbb {K}}\) of \(\mathcal {P}\)-structures is an elementary class (or a first-order class) if there is a set \(\varSigma \) of sentences such that for every \( \langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M }\rangle \),
In this case, \({\mathbb {K}}\) is said to be axiomatized (or defined) by\(\varSigma \).
Using a predicate language with only one binary relation R, the class of weighted undirected graphs is axiomatized by the following set of universal sentences:
Notice that the notion of induced weighted undirected subgraph corresponds to the model-theoretic notion of substructure used in MFL.
Definition 10
Let \(\mathcal {P}\) be a predicate language. We say that a \(\mathcal {P}\)-formula \(\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) is preserved under substructures if for any \(\mathcal {P}\)-structure \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}},\mathbf{M }\rangle \) and any substructure \(\langle {\varvec{B}},\mathbf{N }\rangle \), if \(\left\| {\varphi (d_1,\ldots ,d_n)}\right\| ^{{{\varvec{A}}}}_{\mathbf{M }}=\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\) for some \(d_1,\ldots ,d_n\in N\), then \(\left\| {\varphi (d_1,\ldots ,d_n)}\right\| ^{{\varvec{B}}}_{\mathbf{N }}=\overline{1}^{\varvec{B}}\).
The following lemma can be easily proved by induction on the complexity of universal formulas.
Lemma 3
Let \(\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) be a universal formula. Then, \(\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) is preserved under substructures.
In classical model theory, amalgamation properties are often related in elegant ways to preservation theorems (see e.g. Hodges 1993). We will try an analogous approach to obtain our desired preservation result. The importance of this idea is that the problem of proving a preservation result reduces then to finding a suitable amalgamation counterpart. This provides us with proofs that have a neat common structure (such as those of the main results in this section and the next one).
We will write \( \langle {\mathbf{A }, \mathbf{M}_2, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \Rrightarrow _{\exists _n} \langle {\mathbf{A }, \mathbf{M}_1, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \) if for any \(\exists _n\)-formula \(\varphi \), \( \langle {\mathbf{A }, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \models \varphi [\overrightarrow{d}] \) only if \( \langle {\mathbf{A }, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \models \varphi [\overrightarrow{d}]\).
Proposition 4
(Existential amalgamation) Let \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) and \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) be two structures for \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\) with a common part \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}}\rangle \) with domain generated by a sequence of elements \(\overrightarrow{d}\). Moreover, suppose that
Then, there is a structure \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{N}}\rangle \) into which \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) can be strongly embedded by \(\langle {f, g}\rangle \), while \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) is \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\)-elementarily strongly embedded (taking isomorphic copies, we may assume that \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) is just a \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\)-elementary substructure). The situation is described by the following picture:
Moreover, the result is also true when \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) and \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) have no common part.
Proof
It is not a difficult to show that \( \text{ ElDiag }({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1) \cup \text{ Diag }({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2)\) (where we let the elements of the domain serve as constants to name themselves) has a model, which suffices for the purposes of the result. Suppose otherwise, that is, for some finite \(\text{ Diag }_0({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2) \subseteq \text{ Diag }({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2)\), we have that
for the immediate predecessor a in the lattice order of A of \(\overline{1}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\).
Quantifying away the new individual constants, we obtain a set of formulas \( \text{ Diag }_0^{*}({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2)\) such that:
Since \(\langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \Rrightarrow _{\exists _1} \langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \), then
which is a contradiction. Note, moreover, that if
we also have that whenever \(\varphi (\bar{x}) \) is quantifier-free formula of \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\), \( \langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2 }\rangle \models \varphi [\overrightarrow{d}]\) iff \( \langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1 }\rangle \models \varphi [\overrightarrow{d}] \). Left-to-right is clear; the contrapositive of the right-to-left direction follows easily: if \(\langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1 }\rangle \nvDash \varphi [\overrightarrow{d}]\), then \(\langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1 }\rangle \nvDash \varphi \leftrightarrow \overline{a} [\overrightarrow{d}]\) for some \(a \ne \overline{1}^{{\varvec{A}}}\), so \( \langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2 }\rangle \models \varphi \leftrightarrow \overline{a}[\overrightarrow{d}]\), which means that \( \langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2 }\rangle \nvDash \varphi [\overrightarrow{d}]\).
Observe that the proof can be similarly carried out, mutatis mutandi, when \(\langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) and \(\langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) have no common part as well. \(\square \)
Now, we have the elements to establish an exact analogue of Theorem 5 from Łoś (1955), Łoś–Tarski preservation theorem.
Theorem 5
(Łoś–Tarski preservation theorem) Let T be a \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\)-theory and \(\varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) a set of formulas in \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\). Then, the following are equivalent:
-
(i)
For any models of T, \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \subseteq \langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N}\rangle \), we have: if \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N}\rangle \models \varPhi \), then \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \models \varPhi \).
-
(ii)
There is a set of universal \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\)-formulas \(\varTheta (\overrightarrow{x})\) such that: \(T, \varPhi \vDash \varTheta \) and \(T, \varTheta \vDash \varPhi \).
Proof
Let us prove the difficult direction (the converse direction is clear by Lemma 3). Consider \((T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _1}\), the collection of all \(\forall _1\) logical consequences of \(T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\). We need to establish that the only models of \((T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _1}\) among the models of T are the substructures of models of \(\varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\). Let \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \) be a model of \((T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _1}\). All we need to do is find a model \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N}\rangle \) of the theory \(T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) such that \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \Rrightarrow _{\exists _1} \langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N}\rangle \) and then quote the existential amalgamation theorem.
Let U be all \(\exists _1\)-formulas that hold in \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \). We claim then that \(T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}) \cup U\) has a model. Otherwise, by compactness, for
we have that in all models of \(T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\), it holds that
where a is the immediate predecessor of \(\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\), and by basic manipulations,
which is just equivalent to
The latter formula must be in \((T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _1}\) then, which is a contradiction. \(\square \)
Following a similar proof, we can obtain an algebraic characterization equivalent to Theorem 5 (as long as we have truth-constants around).
Theorem 6
Let \({\mathbb {K}}\) be a class of \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\)-structures. Then, the following are equivalent:
-
(i)
\({\mathbb {K}}\) is closed under isomorphisms, substructures, and ultraproducts.
-
(ii)
\({\mathbb {K}}\) is axiomatized by a set of universal \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\)-sentences.
The following corollary can be obtained because in our setting, two forms of compactness (that are generally distinct, in, say, Łukasiewicz logic) collapse, namely (1) the compactness of the consequence relation and (2) the compactness of the satisfiability relation. (1) clearly implies (2) in the presence of \(\overline{0}\) in our language. To see the converse, say that \(T \vDash \varphi \), which amounts to say that \(T \cup \{\varphi \rightarrow \overline{a}\}\) (where a is the predecessor of \(\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\)) does not have a model. Hence, by (2), there is a finite \(T_0 \subseteq T\) such that \(T_0 \cup \{\varphi \rightarrow \overline{a}\}\) has no model, so, in fact, \(T_0 \vDash \varphi \).
Corollary 7
Let \(T \cup \{\varphi \}\) be a set of \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\)-sentences. Then, \(\varphi \) is preserved under substructures of models of T if, and only if, \(\varphi \) is 1-equivalent to a universal \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\)-sentence modulo T.
Proof
Apply Theorem 5 for \(\varPhi = \{\varphi \}\). Consequently, \(\varphi \) is axiomatized by a set of universal \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\)-sentences. Then, bring it down to a single such formula using A-compactness for consequence. \(\square \)
A natural question is whether Corollary 7 can be strengthened to strong equivalence in terms of \(\leftrightarrow \), that is, whether one can find a universal formula that agrees with \(\phi \) on each value in every structure (not just on value \(\overline{1}^{{\varvec{A}}}\)). Following the lines of the above proof, this would require to show something like, for an arbitrary model \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \),
Then, one would expect to reduce the left side of the inequality to a finite set \(\varPsi \) such that
However, this reduction would come from compactness in the usual argument, but it does not in this one. This is because compactness is about consequence as opposed to implication, which are different in a setting without a deduction theorem such as this. In fact, in Spada (2009) similar results in the framework Łukasiewicz logic are obtained only for 1-equivalence as well.
Needless to say, the previous results, in particular, allow to conclude that a class of \(\mathcal {P}\)-structures (that is, structures for a language without additional truth-constants) closed under substructures can be axiomatized by universal \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\)-sentences. One might wonder, of course, if it is really necessary to resort a universal axiomatization in the expanded language.
Let us present a counterexample showing that, in general, the base language \(\mathcal {P}\) does not suffice for Theorem 6. Let \(\mathcal {P}\) be the language with only one monadic predicate P and take two structures over the standard Gödel chain, \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf M\rangle \) and \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf N \rangle \). The domain in both cases is the set of all natural numbers \(\mathbb {N}\), and the interpretation of the predicate is, respectively, defined as: \( P_{\mathbf M} (n)=\frac{3}{4} \), and \( P_{\mathbf N} (n)=\frac{1}{2}\), for every \(n \in \mathbb {N}\). First, we show that \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf M\rangle \equiv \langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf N \rangle \), that is, that for any \({{\mathcal {P}}}\)-sentence \(\varphi \), \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf M\rangle \models \varphi \) iff \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf N \rangle \models \varphi \). Take f as any non-decreasing bijection from [0, 1] to [0, 1] such that \(f(\frac{3}{4})=\frac{1}{2}\), \(f(1) = 1\), \(f(0) = 0\). It is easy to check that f is a \(\mathrm {G}\)-homomorphism preserving suprema and infima. Then, we can consider the \(\sigma \)-mapping \(\langle {f,\textit{Id}}\rangle \) and apply (Dellunde et al. 2018, Lemma 11) to obtain that \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf M\rangle \equiv \langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf N \rangle \). Consider now the finite subalgebra \({{{\varvec{A}}}}\) of \([0,1]_\mathrm {G}\) generated by the subset \(\{0,\frac{1}{2},\frac{3}{4}, 1\}\). Clearly, the structures \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf M\rangle \) and \(\langle [0,1]_\mathrm {G}, \mathbf N \rangle \) can be regarded as structures over \({{{\varvec{A}}}}\). Thus, we have
Observe that \(\left\| {(\forall x) P(x)}\right\| ^{{{{\varvec{A}}}}}_{\mathbf M} =\frac{3}{4}\) and \(\left\| {(\forall x) P(x)}\right\| ^{{{{\varvec{A}}}}}_{\mathbf N} = \frac{1}{2}\). Consider the expanded language \(\mathcal {P}_{{{{\varvec{A}}}}}\) obtained by adding a constant symbol \(\overline{a}\) for every element \(a \in A\). Let \( {\mathbb {K}}\) be the class of \({{\mathcal {P}}}\)-structures valued on \({\varvec{A}}\), whose natural expansion to \(\mathcal {P}_{{{{\varvec{A}}}}}\) (that is, the expansion in which every constant \(\overline{a}\) is interpreted as the corresponding element a) satisfies the sentence
Clearly, \({\mathbb {K}}\) is closed under substructures and \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf M\rangle \in {\mathbb {K}}\). However, \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf N\rangle \notin {\mathbb {K}}\), because \(\left\| {(\forall x) P(x)}\right\| ^{{{{\varvec{A}}}}}_{\mathbf N} = \frac{1}{2}\). Therefore, \( {\mathbb {K}}\) cannot be axiomatized by \(\mathcal {P}\)-sentences, and a fortiori, by a set of universal \(\mathcal {P}\)-sentences, since it contains \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf M\rangle \) but not the elementary equivalent \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf N \rangle \). Hence, we have produced an example of a class of \({{\mathcal {P}}}\)-structures closed under substructures (and, obviously, under isomorphisms and ultraproducts) which is not axiomatizable with universal \({{\mathcal {P}}}\)-sentences.
Whether constants are necessary for Theorem 5 in general is an open question, we conjecture that they are.
4 Universal–existential classes
This section runs quite parallel to the previous one. We recall the notion of elementary chain of structures and its corresponding Tarski–Vaught theorem and prove that universal–existential formulas are preserved under unions of chains (Lemma 9). After that, we prove a result on existential–universal amalgamation (Proposition 10) and derive from it a Chang–Łoś–Suszko preservation theorem (Theorem 11).
Consider the class \({\mathbb {K}}\) of all structures in a signature with a binary function symbol \(\cdot \), a unary function symbols \(^{-1}\), an individual constant 1, and a unary predicate G satisfying the following axioms:
-
\((\forall x) (\exists y) (y^n \approx x)\) for each \(n \geqslant 2\).
-
\((\forall x, y) ((x\cdot y)\cdot z \approx x\cdot (y \cdot z))\).
-
\((\forall x) (x \cdot 1 \approx x)\).
-
\((\forall x) (x\cdot x^{-1} \approx 1)\).
-
\((\forall x, y)(x\cdot y \approx y\cdot x)\).
-
\((\forall x,y) ((Gx \wedge Gy) \rightarrow G(xy))\).
-
\((\forall x) (Gx \rightarrow G(x^{-1}))\).
This is the class of divisible Abelian groups with a fuzzy subgroup defined by the predicate G (following the definition of Rosenfeld 1971). By our Chang–Łoś–Suszko preservation theorem below, \({\mathbb {K}}\) is a class closed under unions of chains.
Another example of such class be provided by the class of all weighted graphs where the formula
holds, that is, every vertex has at least two incident edges. This axiomatizes the class of graphs where every vertex has degree \(\geqslant 2\).
Given an ordinal \(\gamma \), a sequence \(\{\langle {{\varvec{ A}}, \mathbf{M}_i}\rangle \mid i < \gamma \}\) of models is called a chain when for all \(i<j<\gamma \) we have that \(\langle {{\varvec{ A}} , \mathbf{M}_i}\rangle \) is a substructure of \(\langle {{\varvec{ A}}, \mathbf{M}_j}\rangle \). If, moreover, these substructures are elementary, we speak of an elementary chain. The union of the chain \(\{\langle {{\varvec{ A}}, \mathbf{M}_i}\rangle \mid i < \gamma \}\) is the structure \(\langle {{\varvec{ A}}, \mathbf{M}}\rangle \) where \(\mathbf M \) is defined by taking as its domain \(\bigcup _{i<\gamma }{ M}_i\), interpreting the constants of the language as they were interpreted in each \(\mathbf{M}_i\) and similarly with the relational symbols of the language. Observe as well that \(\mathbf{M}\) is well defined given that \(\{\langle {{\varvec{ A}}, \mathbf{M}_i}\rangle \mid i < \gamma \}\) is a chain.
Next, we recall a useful theorem that has been established and used to construct saturated models in the context of mathematical fuzzy logic in Badia and Noguera (2018b).
Theorem 8
(Badia and Noguera 2018b) (Tarski–Vaught) Let \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M}\rangle \) be the union of the elementary chain \(\{\langle {{\varvec{A}},\mathbf M_i}\rangle \mid i < \gamma \}\). Then, for every sequence \(\overrightarrow{d}\) of elements of \(\mathbf{M}_i\) and formula \(\varphi \), \( \left\| {\varphi (\overrightarrow{d})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf M} = \left\| {\varphi (\overrightarrow{d})}\right\| ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf M_i}\). Moreover, if the chain is not elementary, we still have that \( \left\| {\varphi (\overrightarrow{d})}\right\| ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf M} = \left\| {\varphi (\overrightarrow{d})}\right\| ^{{\varvec{A}}}_{\mathbf M_i}\) for every quantifier-free formula.
Therefore, unions of elementary chains preserve the values of all formulas. It is also interesting to consider formulas that are preserved by all unions of chains.
Definition 11
We say that a formula \(\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) is preserved under unions of chains if whenever we have a chain of models \(\{\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf{M}_i}\rangle \mid i < \gamma \}\) such that for every i, \(\left\| {\varphi (\overrightarrow{d})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf M_i} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}} ( i < \gamma )\) for some sequence \(\overrightarrow{d}\) of elements of \(M_0\), then \(\left\| {\varphi (\overrightarrow{d})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf M} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\), where \(\langle {{\varvec{ A}}, \mathbf{M}}\rangle \) is the union of the chain.
Let a be the element of \({\varvec{A}}\) immediately above \(\overline{0}^{\varvec{A}}\).
Lemma 9
\(\forall _2\)-formulas are preserved under unions of chains.
Proof
Let \( (\forall \overrightarrow{x})(\exists \overrightarrow{y}) \phi \) be a \(\forall _2\)-formula, \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}},{\mathbf {M}}\rangle \) be the union of a chain \(\{\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}},{\mathbf {M}_i}\rangle \mid i < \gamma \}\), and \(\overrightarrow{c}\) some sequence of elements of \(M_0\). Assume that for every \(i < \gamma \), \( \left\| {(\forall \overrightarrow{x})(\exists \overrightarrow{y}) \phi (\overrightarrow{c})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}_i} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\). Let \(\overrightarrow{d} \in M\), we show that
\( \left\| {(\exists \overrightarrow{y}) \phi (\overrightarrow{d}, \overrightarrow{c})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\). Let \(j< \gamma \) be such that \(\overrightarrow{d} \in M_j\). Since \( \left\| {(\forall \overrightarrow{x})(\exists \overrightarrow{y}) \phi (\overrightarrow{c})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}_j} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\), we have \(\left\| {(\exists \overrightarrow{y}) \phi (\overrightarrow{d},\overrightarrow{c})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}_j} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\). Since \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}},{\mathbf {M}_j}\rangle \) is \(\exists \)-witnessed, there are \(\overrightarrow{e} \in M_j\) such that \(\left\| { \phi (\overrightarrow{d},\overrightarrow{e},\overrightarrow{c})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}_j} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\). Therefore, \(\left\| { \phi (\overrightarrow{d},\overrightarrow{e}, \overrightarrow{c})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\), because extensions preserve quantifier-free formulas, and then clearly
We can conclude that for every \(\overrightarrow{d} \in M\),
and hence, \( \left\| {(\forall \overrightarrow{x})(\exists \overrightarrow{y}) \phi (\overrightarrow{c})}\right\| ^{\varvec{A}}_{\mathbf {M}} = \overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\). \(\square \)
Next, we provide the amalgamation result that will allow us to prove a version of Chang–Łoś–Suszko theorem for graded model theory.
Proposition 10
\((\exists _2\)-amalgamation) Let \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) and \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) be two structures for \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\) with a common part \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}}\rangle \) with domain generated by a sequence of elements \(\overrightarrow{d}\). Moreover, suppose that
Then, there is a structure \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{N}}\rangle \) into which \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) can be strongly embedded by \(\langle {f, g}\rangle \) preserving all \(\forall _1\)-formulas, while \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) is \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\)-elementarily strongly embedded (taking isomorphic copies, we may assume that \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) is just a \(\mathcal {P}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\)-elementary substructure). The situation is described by the following picture:
Moreover, the result is also true when \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_1}\rangle \) and \(\langle {{{\varvec{A}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) have no common part.
Proof
Let \(\text{ Diag }_{\forall _1}({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2)\) be the collection of all \(\forall _1\)-formulas in the language of the diagram of \(\langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2}\rangle \) (where we let the elements of the domain serve as constants to name themselves) that hold in said structure. It is not difficult to show that \( \text{ ElDiag }({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1) \cup \text{ Diag }_{\forall _1}({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2)\) (where again we let the elements of the domain serve as constants to name themselves) has a model, which suffices for the purposes of the result. For suppose otherwise, that is, for some finite
we have that
for some \(a \ne \overline{1}^{{{\varvec{A}}}}\) (the supremum of all the values taken by \(\bigwedge \text{ Diag }_{\forall _1 0}({{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2)\) in \({{{\varvec{A}}}}\)). Quantifying away the new individual constants,
so
Since \( \langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_2, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \Rrightarrow _{\exists _2} \langle {{{{\varvec{A}}}}, \mathbf{M}_1, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \), then
which is a contradiction. \(\square \)
Now, we are ready to prove the promised analogue of Robinson (1959, Theorem 1.2).
Theorem 11
(Chang–Łoś–Suszko preservation theo.) Let T be a theory and \(\varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) a set of formulas in \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\). Then, the following are equivalent:
-
(i)
\(\varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) is preserved under unions of chains of models of T.
-
(ii)
\(\varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) is 1-equivalent modulo T to a set of \(\forall _2\)-formulas.
Proof
Once more, we only deal with the non-trivial direction of the equivalence. Consider \((T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _2}\). We want to show that
which will suffice to establish the theorem. The strategy is establish that any model of \( T \cup (T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _2}\) has an elementary extension which is a union of \(\omega \)-many models of \(\varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\), so by hypothesis, \(\varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) will hold there, and hence back in our original model of \( T \cup (T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _2}\).
So, we start with \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_0}\rangle \) being an arbitrary model of \( T \cup (T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _2}\). Now, assuming that we have \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i}\rangle \) which is an elementary extension of \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_0}\rangle \). We first need to find a model \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i^{\prime }}\rangle \) of the theory \(T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) such that \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i}\rangle \Rrightarrow _{\exists _2} \langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i^{\prime }}\rangle \) and then quote the \(\exists _2\)-amalgamation theorem to obtain a model \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N_i}\rangle \) of \(T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x})\) into which \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i}\rangle \) can be strongly embedded in such a way that all \(\forall _1\)-formulas are preserved by such strong embedding.
Let U be all \(\exists _2\)-formulas that hold in \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i}\rangle \). We claim then that \(T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}) \cup U\) has a model. Otherwise by compactness, for
we have that in all models of T, it holds that
where a is the immediate predecessor of \(\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\) and by basic manipulations,
The latter formula must be in \((T \cup \varPhi (\overrightarrow{x}))_{\forall _2}\) then, which is a contradiction.
Now,\(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N_i}\rangle \) is also such that for a listing \(\overrightarrow{d}\) of all the elements of \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i}\rangle \), \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N_i, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \Rrightarrow _{\exists _1} \langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_i, \overrightarrow{d}}\rangle \). To prove the contrapositive, suppose that
where a is the immediate predecessor of \(\overline{1}^{\varvec{A}}\) in the linear order of \({\varvec{A}}\). But then
so indeed,
and hence,
Now, using the existential amalgamation theorem we can obtain a structure \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_{i+1}}\rangle \) as an elementary extension of \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf M_{i}}\rangle \) into which \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \mathbf N_{i}}\rangle \) can be strongly embedded. Now, just take the union \(\langle {{\varvec{A}}, \bigcup _{i\in \omega } \mathbf M_i}\rangle = \langle {{\varvec{A}}, \bigcup _{i\in \omega } \mathbf N_i}\rangle \) and apply Theorem 8. \(\square \)
As a consequence, we can again obtain a result for single formulas, using the compactness of the consequence relation.
Corollary 12
Let T be a theory in \({{\mathcal {P}}}^{{\varvec{A}}}\) and \(\varphi \) a formula. Then, the following are equivalent:
-
(i)
\(\varphi \) is preserved under unions of chains of models of T.
-
(ii)
\(\varphi \) is 1-equivalent modulo T to a set of \(\forall _2\)-formulas.
5 Conclusions
In this paper, we have provided some necessary steps in the systematic study of syntactic characterizations of classes of graded structures and their corresponding preservations theorems. Work in progress in the same line includes the study of the universal Horn fragment of predicate fuzzy logics and the classes axiomatized by sets of Horn clauses. Moreover, in the general endeavour of graded model theory, we believe that, among others, future works should focus on the study of types, with the construction of saturated models and type-omission theorems, the study of particular kinds of graded structures that are relevant for computer science applications and, also, the development of Lindström-style characterization theorems for predicate fuzzy logics that may lead to the creation of a non-classical abstract model theory.
References
Badia G, Noguera C (2018a) Fraïssé classes of graded relational structures. Theor Comput Sci 737:81–90
Badia G, Noguera C (2018b) Saturated models in mathematical fuzzy logic. In: Proceedings of the IEEE international symposium on multiple-valued logic. IEEE Computer Society, pp 150–155
Bagheri SM, Moniri M (2013) Preservation theorems in Łukasiewicz model theory. Iran J Fuzzy Syst 10(3):103–113
Burris S, Sankappanavar HP (1981) A course in universal algebra, vol 78. Graduate texts in mathematics. Springer, Berlin
Chang CC, Keisler HJ (1973) Model theory. Elsevier Science Publishers, Amsterdam
Cintula P, Esteva F, Gispert J, Godo L, Montagna F, Noguera C (2009) Distinguished algebraic semantics For T-norm based fuzzy logics: methods and algebraic equivalencies. Ann Pure Appl Log 160:53–81
Cintula P, Diaconecsu D, Metcalfe G (2015) Skolemization for substructural logics. In: Davis M, Fehnker A, McIver A, Voronko A (eds) Proceedings of LPAR-20, lecture notes in computer science. Springer, pp 1–15
Cintula P, Fermüller C, Hájek P, Noguera C (eds) (2011, 2015) Handbook of mathematical fuzzy logic, studies in logic, mathematical logic and foundations, vol 37, 38, 58. College Publications, London
Cintula P, Metcalfe G (2013) Herbrand theorems for substructural logics. In: McMillan KL, Middeldorp A, Voronkov A (eds) Proceedings of LPAR-19. Lecture notes in computer science 8312. Springer, pp 584–600
Costa V, Dellunde P (2017) On the existence of free models in fuzzy universal Horn classes. J Appl Log 23:3–15
Dellunde P (2011) Preserving mappings in fuzzy predicate logics. J Log Comput 22(6):1367–1389
Dellunde P (2014) Applications of ultraproducts: from compactness to fuzzy elementary classes. Log J IGPL 22(1):166–180
Dellunde P, García-Cerdaña À, Noguera C (2016) Löwenheim-Skolem theorems for non-classical first-order algebraizable logics. Log J IGPL 24(3):321–345
Dellunde P, García-Cerdaña À, Noguera C (2018) Back-and-forth systems for fuzzy first-order models. Fuzzy Sets Syst 345:83–98
Esteva F, Godo L (2001) Monoidal t-norm based logic: towards a logic for left-continuous t-norms. Fuzzy Sets Syst 124:271–288
Gerla G (2005) Fuzzy logic programming and fuzzy control. Stud Log 79(2):231–254
Hájek P, Cintula P (2006) On theories and models in fuzzy predicate logics. J Symb Log 71(3):863–880
Hodges W (1993) Model theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Łoś J (1955) On the extending of models (I). Fundam Math 42(1):38–54
Robinson A (1959) Obstructions to arithmetical extension and the theorem of Łoś and Suszko. Proc R Dutch Acad Sci Amst (A) 62:489–495
Rosenfeld A (1971) Fuzzy groups. J Math Anal Appl 35(3):512–517
Sacks G (1972) Saturated model theory. W. A. Benjamin Inc., New York
Spada L (2009) Some consequences of compactness in Łukasiewicz logic. In: Drossos C, Peppas P, Tsinakis C (eds) Proceeding of the VII Panhellenic symposium, Patras
Acknowledgements
Open access funding provided by Austrian Science Fund (FWF). The authors are indebted to two anonymous referees and to the editor for their critical and interesting remarks that have helped improving the presentation the paper. Costa, Dellunde, and Noguera received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Curie Grant Agreement No. 689176 (SYSMICS project). Badia is supported by the Project I 1923-N25 (New perspectives on residuated posets) of the Austrian Science Fund (FWF). Costa is also supported by the Grant for the recruitment of early-stage research staff (FI-2017) from the Generalitat de Catalunya. Dellunde is also partially supported by the Project RASO TIN2015-71799-C2-1-P, CIMBVAL TIN2017-89758-R, and the Grant 2017SGR-172 from the Generalitat de Catalunya. The research leading to these results has received funding from AppPhil-RecerCaixa. Finally, Noguera is also supported by the Project GA17-04630S of the Czech Science Foundation (GAČR).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of interest
The authors declare they have no conflict of interest.
Human and animal rights
This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.
Additional information
Communicated by L. Spada.
This paper is dedicated to Lluís Godo in the occasion of his 60th birthday.
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made.
About this article
Cite this article
Badia, G., Costa, V., Dellunde, P. et al. Syntactic characterizations of classes of first-order structures in mathematical fuzzy logic. Soft Comput 23, 2177–2186 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00500-019-03850-6
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00500-019-03850-6