Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Alternating Turing machine

In computational complexity theory, an alternating Turing machine (ATM) is a non-deterministic Turing machine (NTM) with a rule for accepting computations that generalizes the rules used in the definition of the complexity classes NP and co-NP. The concept of an ATM was set forth by Chandra and Stockmeyer[1] and independently by Kozen[2] in 1976, with a joint journal publication in 1981.[3]

Definitions

edit

Informal description

edit

The definition of NP uses the existential mode of computation: if any choice leads to an accepting state, then the whole computation accepts. The definition of co-NP uses the universal mode of computation: only if all choices lead to an accepting state does the whole computation accept. An alternating Turing machine (or to be more precise, the definition of acceptance for such a machine) alternates between these modes.

An alternating Turing machine is a non-deterministic Turing machine whose states are divided into two sets: existential states and universal states. An existential state is accepting if some transition leads to an accepting state; a universal state is accepting if every transition leads to an accepting state. (Thus a universal state with no transitions accepts unconditionally; an existential state with no transitions rejects unconditionally). The machine as a whole accepts if the initial state is accepting.

Formal definition

edit

Formally, a (one-tape) alternating Turing machine is a 5-tuple   where

  •   is the finite set of states
  •   is the finite tape alphabet
  •   is called the transition function (L shifts the head left and R shifts the head right)
  •   is the initial state
  •   specifies the type of each state

If M is in a state   with   then that configuration is said to be accepting, and if   the configuration is said to be rejecting. A configuration with   is said to be accepting if all configurations reachable in one step are accepting, and rejecting if some configuration reachable in one step is rejecting. A configuration with   is said to be accepting when there exists some configuration reachable in one step that is accepting and rejecting when all configurations reachable in one step are rejecting (this is the type of all states in a classical NTM except the final state). M is said to accept an input string w if the initial configuration of M (the state of M is  , the head is at the left end of the tape, and the tape contains w) is accepting, and to reject if the initial configuration is rejecting.

Note that it is impossible for a configuration to be both accepting and rejecting, however, some configurations may be neither accepting or rejecting, due to the possibility of nonterminating computations.

Resource bounds

edit

When deciding if a configuration of an ATM is accepting or rejecting using the above definition, it is not always necessary to examine all configurations reachable from the current configuration. In particular, an existential configuration can be labelled as accepting if any successor configuration is found to be accepting, and a universal configuration can be labelled as rejecting if any successor configuration is found to be rejecting.

An ATM decides a formal language in time   if, on any input of length n, examining configurations only up to   steps is sufficient to label the initial configuration as accepting or rejecting. An ATM decides a language in space   if examining configurations that do not modify tape cells beyond the   cell from the left is sufficient.

A language that is decided by some ATM in time   for some constant   is said to be in the class  , and a language decided in space   is said to be in the class  .

Example

edit

Perhaps the most natural problem for alternating machines to solve is the quantified Boolean formula problem, which is a generalization of the Boolean satisfiability problem in which each variable can be bound by either an existential or a universal quantifier. The alternating machine branches existentially to try all possible values of an existentially quantified variable and universally to try all possible values of a universally quantified variable, in the left-to-right order in which they are bound. After deciding a value for all quantified variables, the machine accepts if the resulting Boolean formula evaluates to true, and rejects if it evaluates to false. Thus at an existentially quantified variable the machine is accepting if a value can be substituted for the variable that renders the remaining problem satisfiable, and at a universally quantified variable the machine is accepting if any value can be substituted and the remaining problem is satisfiable.

Such a machine decides quantified Boolean formulas in time   and space  .

The Boolean satisfiability problem can be viewed as the special case where all variables are existentially quantified, allowing ordinary nondeterminism, which uses only existential branching, to solve it efficiently.

Complexity classes and comparison to deterministic Turing machines

edit

The following complexity classes are useful to define for ATMs:

  •   are the languages decidable in polynomial time
  •   are the languages decidable in polynomial space
  •   are the languages decidable in exponential time

These are similar to the definitions of P, PSPACE, and EXPTIME, considering the resources used by an ATM rather than a deterministic Turing machine. Chandra, Kozen, and Stockmeyer[3] proved the theorems

  • ALOGSPACE = P
  • AP = PSPACE
  • APSPACE = EXPTIME
  • AEXPTIME = EXPSPACE
  •  
  •  
  •  

when   and  .

A more general form of these relationships is expressed by the parallel computation thesis.

Bounded alternation

edit

Definition

edit

An alternating Turing machine with k alternations is an alternating Turing machine that switches from an existential to a universal state or vice versa no more than k−1 times. (It is an alternating Turing machine whose states are divided into k sets. The states in even-numbered sets are universal and the states in odd-numbered sets are existential (or vice versa). The machine has no transitions between a state in set i and a state in set j < i.)

  is the class of languages decidable in time   by a machine beginning in an existential state and alternating at most   times. It is called the jth level of the   hierarchy.

  is defined in the same way, but beginning in a universal state; it consists of the complements of the languages in  .

  is defined similarly for space bounded computation.

Example

edit

Consider the circuit minimization problem: given a circuit A computing a Boolean function f and a number n, determine if there is a circuit with at most n gates that computes the same function f. An alternating Turing machine, with one alternation, starting in an existential state, can solve this problem in polynomial time (by guessing a circuit B with at most n gates, then switching to a universal state, guessing an input, and checking that the output of B on that input matches the output of A on that input).

Collapsing classes

edit

It is said that a hierarchy collapses to level j if every language in level   of the hierarchy is in its level j.

As a corollary of the Immerman–Szelepcsényi theorem, the logarithmic space hierarchy collapses to its first level.[4] As a corollary the   hierarchy collapses to its first level when   is space constructible[citation needed].

Special cases

edit

An alternating Turing machine in polynomial time with k alternations, starting in an existential (respectively, universal) state can decide all the problems in the class   (respectively,  ).[5] These classes are sometimes denoted   and  , respectively. See the polynomial hierarchy article for details.

Another special case of time hierarchies is the logarithmic hierarchy.

References

edit
  1. ^ Chandra, Ashok K.; Stockmeyer, Larry J. (1976). "Alternation". Proc. 17th IEEE Symp. on Foundations of Computer Science. Houston, Texas. pp. 98–108. doi:10.1109/SFCS.1976.4.
  2. ^ Kozen, D. (1976). "On parallelism in Turing machines". Proc. 17th IEEE Symp. on Foundations of Computer Science. Houston, Texas. pp. 89–97. doi:10.1109/SFCS.1976.20. hdl:1813/7056.
  3. ^ a b Chandra, Ashok K.; Kozen, Dexter C.; Stockmeyer, Larry J. (1981). "Alternation" (PDF). Journal of the ACM. 28 (1): 114–133. doi:10.1145/322234.322243. S2CID 238863413. Archived from the original (PDF) on April 12, 2016.
  4. ^ Immerman, Neil (1988). "Nondeterministic space is closed under complementation" (PDF). SIAM Journal on Computing. 17 (5): 935–938. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.54.5941. doi:10.1137/0217058.
  5. ^ Kozen, Dexter (2006). Theory of Computation. Springer-Verlag. p. 58. ISBN 9781846282973.

Further reading

edit