Abstract
It is argued that one can learn from minimal economic models. Minimal models are models that are not similar to the real world, do not resemble some of its features, and do not adhere to accepted regularities. One learns from a model if constructing and analysing the model affects one’s confidence in hypotheses about the world. Economic models, I argue, are often assessed for their credibility. If a model is judged credible, it is considered to be a relevant possibility. Considering such relevant possibilities may affect one’s confidence in necessity or impossibility hypotheses. Thus, one can learn from minimal economic models.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Suarez defends a ‘deflationary or minimalist attitude and strategy towards the concept of scientific representation’ that is related to the minimal model presented here (Suárez 2004, p. 770). However, he suggests that representational force and allowing inferences are necessary conditions for scientific representations. It seems to me that both conditions are rather matters of degree, and thus only function as comparative but not exclusionary criteria. The minimal-model account presented here does not lay claim to any necessary criteria.
Cf. Hausman (1992, p. 75).
Giere has since proposed an alternative, pragmatic account that does not rely to this extent on similarity (Giere 2004). His previous account, however, still attracts attention, particularly among scientists. It therefore seems worthwhile discussing it here.
These differences were documented for some of the main economic journals during the period from 1972 to 1986. About 45% of all economic research articles analysed mathematical models without making use of or even referring to any form of data, while the respective figures were 18% in political science, 1%in sociology, 0% in chemistry and 12% in physics (Leontief 1982; Morgan 1988). It is my impression that these proportions have not significantly changed in economics (although they may, as part of the methodological aspect of economics imperialism, have increased in the other social sciences).
I should add that Cartwright (2007; this issue) arrives at a similar conclusion. Yet for her this conclusion is bad news for economics—while I would consider it bad news for the ‘stronger model requirements’ position.
By induction Sugden presumably means the broad category of non-deductive inferences (i.e. all those in which the premises of an argument are believed to support the conclusion but do not entail it), and not the narrower inference from empirically confirmed tokens to other tokens of the same type.
Sugden also mentions credibility in a different way, as a quality of the inferences themselves. He writes, ‘Since the same effects are found in both real and imaginary cities, it is at least credible to suppose that the same causes are responsible’ (Sugden 2000, p. 24, my emphasis). Here ‘credible’ is used in the sense of ‘more probable’. This is incompatible with the notion of credibility as depicting a parallel—i.e. counterfactual—reality: the descriptions of counterfactual worlds are necessarily false, and hence cannot be probable. In personal communication with the author, Bob Sugden has suggested that the above use of ‘credible’ is spurious, and that replacing ‘credible’ with ‘reasonable’ or ‘defensible’ would be a way to avoid possible confusion.
I therefore disagree with the claim that model credibility implies robustness of the results (cf. Kuorikoski and Lehtinen, this issue, section 5).
As further supported by his reference to ‘the general laws governing events in the real world’ (Sugden 2000, p. 25, my emphasis).
For example, Russell (1948) uses ‘credibility’ in the same way as ‘confidence in’ or ‘degree of belief in’ the truth of that proposition.
The exception here is Behavioural Economics, which often refers to experimental results as a way of justifying certain constraining model assumptions.
For an overview, see Frigg (2009, p. 6).
It is sometimes claimed that folk economics has predictable biases, focusing on wealth and its distribution, and neglecting the production and allocation of goods and their efficiency (cf. Rubin 2003).
Economic theory, as well as folk economics, also proposes impossibility hypotheses. Significant examples include the claim that a firm’s investment is totally independent of its liquidity position (Modigliani-Miller Theorem), and that the stability of the economy is neutral with respect to the systematic reaction of monetary policy to the business cycle (Rational Expectations Hypothesis).
Tobin’s ultra-Keynesian model is another good example (Knuuttila, this issue, section 6).
This irrelevancy problem does not arise in the cases Schlimm discusses. The impossibility claims these models dispute concern the construction of entities that display intelligent behaviour without a ‘vitalistic’ element. The impossibility hypothesis is about the very possibility of modelling. Thus, the existence of any entity that exhibits such behaviour without incorporating the vitalistic element contradicts the impossibility hypothesis. This feature makes Schlimm’s cases special, and prevents their generalisation to other situations.
References
Alexandrova, A. (2006). Connecting rational choice models to the real world. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36(2), 173–192.
Aydınonat, N. E. (2007). Models, conjectures and exploration: An analysis of Schelling’s checkerboard model of residential segregation. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14(4), 429–454.
Cartwright, N. (1999). Capacities. In J. B. Davis, D. W. Hands, & U. Mäki (Eds.), The handbook of economic methodology (pp. 45–48). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Cartwright, N. (2007). The vanity of rigor in economics. In N. Cartwright (Ed.), Hunting causes and using them: Approaches in philosophy and economics (pp. 217–35). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cartwright, N. (2009). If no capacities then no credible worlds. But can models reveal capacities? Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9136-8.
de Donato, X., & Zamora-Bonilla, J. (2009). Credibility, idealisation, and model building: An inferential approach. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9139-5.
Frigg, R. (2009). Models and fiction. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11098-008-9313-2.
Gallagher, C. (2006). The rise of fictionality. In F. Moretti (Ed.), The novel (Vol. 2, pp. 336–363). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gibbard, A., & Varian, H. R. (1978). Economic models. The Journal of Philosophy, 75, 664–677.
Ginits, H. (2000). Game theory evolving. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71, 742–752.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 725–740.
Grüne-Yanoff, T., & Schweinzer, P. (2008). The roles of stories in applying game theory. Journal of Economic Methodology, 15(2), 131–146.
Hausman, D. (1992). The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hindriks, F. A. (2006). Tractability assumptions and the Musgrave-Mäki typology. Journal of Economic Methodology, 13(4), 401–423.
Hughes, R. I. G. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science, 64, S325–S336.
Knuuttila, T. (2009). Isolating representations vs. credible constructions? Economic modelling in theory and practice. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9137-7.
Kuorikoski, J., & Lehtinen, A. (2009). Incredible worlds, credible results. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9140-z.
Leontief, W. (1982). Academic economics. Science, 217, 104–107.
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Lind, H. (2007). The model and the story told: An evaluation of mathematical models of rent control. Regional Science and Urban Economics, 37(2), 183–198.
Mäki, U. (1994). Isolation, idealization and truth in economics. In B. Hamminga & N. De Marchi (Eds.), Idealization-VI: Idealization in economics (pp. 67–68). Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities, 38. Amsterdam: Rodopoi.
Mäki, U. (2004). Realism and the nature of theory: A lesson from J.H. von Thünen for economists and geographers. Environment and Planning A, 36, 1719–1736.
Mäki, U. (2009) . MISSing the world. Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9135-9.
Morgan, T. (1988). Theory versus empiricism in academic economics: Update and comparisons. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 2, 159–164.
Morgan, M. S. (1999). Learning from Models. In Morgan and Morrison (1999), (pp. 347–388).
Morgan, M. S., & Morrison, M. (Eds.) (1999). Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rubin, P. H. (2003). Folk economics. Southern Economic Journal, 70(1), 157–171.
Rubinstein, A. (2001). A theorist’s view of experiments. European Economic Review, 45, 615–628.
Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Samuelson, P. A. (1963). Foundations of economic analysis. London: Oxford University Press (first edition 1947).
Schelling, T. (2006). Strategies of commitment and other essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Schlimm, D. (2009). Learning from the existence of models. On psychic machines, tortoises, and computer simulations. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-008-9432-5.
Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71, 767–779.
Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7(1), 1–31.
Sugden, R. (2009). Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9134-x.
Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(2), 207–233.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Grüne-Yanoff, T. Learning from Minimal Economic Models. Erkenn 70, 81–99 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-008-9138-6
Received:
Revised:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-008-9138-6