The Matter of Design
The Matter of Design
The Matter of Design
Clive Dilnot
To cite this article: Clive Dilnot (2015) The matter of design, Design Philosophy Papers, 13:2,
115-123, DOI: 10.1080/14487136.2015.1133137
Download by: [Professor Anne-Marie Willis] Date: 18 May 2017, At: 01:05
DESIGN PHILOSOPHY PAPERS, 2015
VOL. 13, NO. 2, 115–123
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14487136.2015.1133137
1. ‘In the future design will be very important, designers less so’
Two hundred years ago a Design Research Society conference was not possible. Indeed,
Design, as we know it, as a professional activity, did not exist. One hundred years ago we
could have had debates on design – in 1914 there was a famous debate between Gropius
and Van der Velde at the German Werkbund (in effect on art versus industry, some things
do not change much) – but at that date the idea of design research was all but impossible
and indeed the Design profession itself, as we know it was still incipient. The concepts of
high-level design education and of design research waited for another half-century.
The point I am making here is obvious – almost, but not quite, for to point to the historical
emergence of design as profession is to remind us what we continually tend to forget, namely
that if design is what we think of today as (in effect) an anthropological capacity – without
which we could not be fully human (in the words of the late British design historian John
Heskett, ‘a unique characteristic of what defines us as human beings on a par with literature
and music’) it is also specifically, in the form that it takes as capacity, a historical phenomenon.
In other words, if design, again to quote Heskett, allows us, or helps us, ‘to create a world
of artifice to meet our needs and give meaning to our lives,’ and thus (ideally if not always
in practice) ‘beneficially reshape the world of artifice we have created and inhabit,’ it does so
always under particular historical conditions. Design is never outside of history: it occurs; in
the context of forces and circumstances; in the play that is set in motion between a relation
of forces and the potential (shi) which is implied by that situation, and can be made to play
in one’s favor.
Hegel argued that philosophy is always its own time reflected in thought. Design partakes
on something of the same condition. It is always at once beholden to and reflective of, its
moment – but, and this is crucial, it is also at best reflective on or reflective concerning its
moment. Design, in other words, sometimes thinks its moment and its possibilities.
What does it signify/or mean/ to say that design is never outside of history? Two things:
one general, one specific.
The generality is that design is always and everywhere historical. That means it cannot
be thought outside of a historical perspective. To try to think design analytically or anthro-
pologically without also thinking it historically is doomed to failure.
One proof of this is that it is the lack of such a perspective that renders so much design
research intellectually null; that strips it of substantive content.
The more specific point is that, as a professional activity design does not occur, does not
happen, only or even largely through its own volition. Rather, Design – modern design, pro-
fessional design – is called into being by Industrialization and is so in order to do a specific
job; that is, design is tasked with ‘overcoming,’ at least in appearance, the subject–object split
at the level of objects. (Or we might equally say, with reconciling ‘use value’ and ‘exchange
value’ – normally, commercially in the interests of the latter through the intensification of
the former.)
Two essential qualifiers:
– The first is the reminder that industry (aka capitalism) does not simply call design into
being as such, but only on its terms. That is, it calls it into being as a subaltern practice (a ‘not
too serious’ profession in latour’s terms). Industry wishes only to have design for its use.
The history of design from the 1840s through to the present day is in part a struggle with
this determination.1 But neither practice, nor history, nor research easily escapes from the
a priori structuring of design activity. Put another way, designing, ‘design thinking’ and the
thinking of design are radically limited by this origin – as well as by the uses to which they
are put.
– The second qualifier becomes a question. Today it is not quite correct to say that we are
in a ‘post-industrial’ world – certainly one would not say so if one lived in China for example.
But, and it is a very important ‘but,’ even in China, let alone in the de-industrialized West,
industry is no longer socially or economically formative.
We can put a precise date on the transition: 1973–1974, the oil price shock, the collapse
of manufacturing profitability and the beginnings of a move to accumulation through the
management of financial flows and consumption fueled by debt. After this point, in a certain
way, industry no longer matters. It becomes like craft in the nineteenth century, present,
but no longer formative.
What is formative in the world and the economy belongs to consumption and to finance
and to the realm of digital communication and above all to their interlinking.
An obvious question now intrudes. If Design was born from industry and industry is no
longer formative how then is Design? What happens to Design as it loses that which formed
it?
We need to be careful as we answer this question. For it raises a larger one: if industry is
no longer formative of society as a whole are we then even in ‘industrial society?’ Does the
demise of industry (and rise of other factors of production as formative for a global society
grounded on nothing but an economy that is taking a hyper-capitalist form) perhaps mean
that we are entering into a new kind of historical epoch?
DeSIGN PHIlOSOPHY PAPeRS 117
It is my contention that we are. I would say that since 1945 we have been in transition
to a new historical period, one that obviously emerges out of industrialization but is yet
distinct from it.2
What makes it different?
The far too short answer is that over the last 70 years we have been in transition toward
an epoch where the artificial, and not nature, is the horizon, medium and prime condition of
human (and not only human) existence. This epoch is qualitatively different from the preced-
ing industrial epoch. To put it over simply, the quantitative expansion, after 1945, in artifice
in every dimension (technological, symbolic, in relation to nature) becomes a qualitative
transformation in the underlying conditions of our being.
What are some of the aspects of this new historical condition?
This is an immensely complex topic. In the time we have here I can say very little but I will
name three ‘meta’ conditions that describe, in my view, the metaphysics (in the strict sense
of the term – meaning the condition of the real and of truth) of this new epoch.
• The first is the absolute dependence (even in our relations with nature) on how we relate
to [or in my language ‘contend with’] the artificial.3
• The second is the equally absolute dependence for our futures on the quality (and I
stress this) of our mediation with the artificial – and on the quality of the mediation of
the artificial with all other living and non-living systems on the planet.
• The third point, in certain ways the most interesting, or at least that which is yet least
understood, is the fact that things no longer ‘are’ as facts. To put it another way, at least
in the realm of all that we make, certainty is dead. Today, there is, in a certain sense no
law, and we have to learn to live with this fact. (In the artificial there are only possibilities,
which are without definite end. All artificial things are therefore propositions concerning
the artificial.)
How does this bear on design? [And on the proposition I am arguing for?] Very quickly,
I think in two major ways:
First, the ideas of relation, mediation and the propositional – the converse of the end of
certainty – means that designing, in the broad sense of re-configurative activity is now objec-
tively positioned as an essential, perhaps even the essential mode of acting in the artificial
world. Designing is essential because mediation means the mediation of incommensurable
requirements and conditions. Design, unlike technology potentially welcomes, is at home
with, and does not see to erase incommensurability.
Since incommensurability – at the largest of humans, their actions and natural systems – is
our global condition, this means, in effect, that there is no humanly or ecologically successful
living with the artificial that is not also ‘designing.’ Designing (lower case, a transitive and
operative verb) -as-mediation therefore becomes (will become in the future) less a specialist
but marginal activity and more an essential generalized mode of acting in the world.
Second, in the context of generalized artifice the level at which design acts as mediation
is profound. It is not a kind of supplement to what-is (which is how it functioned in the
last century) but a kind of depth condition. The essential mediation of subject and object
(design’s subject matter after all!) now displaces the split Descartes introduced between the
subject and the object. That antagonism disappears: just as ‘Will’ and ‘law’ disappear – to
be replaced by negotiated configurative activity (which replaces will) and by the idea of the
proposition (which replaces law).
118 C. DIlNOT
This is also why ‘technology’ disappears as such. Technology is not absolute but
is born as a concept with the splitting that marks the beginning of industrial modernity
– roughly, that between aesthetics, ethics and technics. ‘Design’ was invented, industrially,
to pretend the overcoming of that split, but in a condition of the artificial as world its over-
coming becomes real. Designing therefore supplants technology, which now reverts to a
sub-set of making and is in fact dissolved as such since its ‘objectivity’ is now penetrated
on every side.
You can already see that the ‘design’ that is now being referred to is no longer quite – the
qualifier is important – Design as we have comprehended it over the last two centuries.
But what then of the designer? After all, if Design (capitalized) was born out of industri-
alization then so was the Designer (capital D). The ‘death’ of industry [as formative for our
society] therefore means also the death of the Designer (capitalized).
Why should we be surprised at this? Out of the whole of human history, only in the last
two centuries have there truly been Designers in the professional sense, identified as such.
But then, were designers ever designers?
Just as Bruno latour argues, ‘[w]e have never been Modern,’ I would say: we never yet had
design – only its weak, subaltern industrial-capitalist, version. One reason we have never
had design is perhaps that Designers, as well as struggling to exemplify the capabilities
of design, also, in some ways, ‘got in the way’ of design. Is the radical conclusion of this
then that in the emerging future we shall get to the point where the Designer ‘disappears’
within a wider praxis of designing as a ubiquitous and necessary condition of becoming
human?
Of course, we could say, designers (in the old sense of the term) will continue to exist. But
they will be like craftsmen in the nineteenth century. They will work, but they will not as such
exert a formative influence. That formative influence will belong to design, as a multiple and
generalized human capacity, occasionally professionalized.
Might the world be a better place for this? After all, the ghetto is always a precarious
existence; assimilation has its advantages (recall the Borg in Star Trek).
The world loses Designers but it gains design.
2. What is the relation between matter & matter(ing) – or why are things ‘us’?
Something is absent in the discussion and this absence is not negligible, it goes to the
heart of understanding what we are doing.
I say ‘an absence,’ there are actually three.
– Absence in the debate of any sense of that which links, connects and at the same time
differentiates between, ‘objects’ and ‘design.’
– An absence of any sense of what it is that design works on; of what, if you like, is the
subject-matter of design (and the term ‘objects’ is not by itself an adequate answer, nor is an
adequate answer ‘design’).
– An absence of what makes the difference (if any) between ‘matter’ and ‘matter(ing).’
There is also a fourth missing item, this one a kind of meta-absence, it is the lack of suf-
ficient examination of the changing historical, operational and critical context in which all
this is taking place.
DeSIGN PHIlOSOPHY PAPeRS 119
let me begin with the third point (while keeping the fourth very much in mind). One way
to think this differentiation, or this movement between matter/mattering, is to use latour’s
useful little point about the shift in our time from ‘Matters of Fact’ to ‘Matters of Concern.’
Philosophically, for us, until very recently indeed, matter, as above all natural matter,
earth-stuff, has meant Fact. In effect, matter was/is equated to ‘object’ and was/is contrasted
to ‘subject.’
But Mattering, meaning that which matters (to us) is precisely a matter of concern and
thus cannot have the quality of a fact. A matter(ing) is not therefore an object.
On the contrary, a matter of concern always takes the form of a question: ‘This?’
So here is a first shift.
But we can go a little further.
Most matter is not today for us natural matter, it is artificial.
Indeed if you were to accept the claim that we (meaning we + nature) are today wholly
within the horizon of the artificial then all matter, including everything we used to see as
‘nature,’ is ‘Artificial.’
Oil is artificial, coal is artificial, air is artificial.
The underlying historical claim here is that since 1945 we have been in transition to a
world where it is the artificial, and no longer nature, that is (for us) the horizon and medium of
the world; where it is the artificial (and our relations with ‘it’) that constitutes as the formative
totality of existence and thus becomes the prime condition of our existence.
The condition of the artificial re-frames the world, deeply.
This shift has enormous implications, which we have by no means yet intellectually fath-
omed, indeed have not begun to think it adequately.
In relation to what we are discussing, it changes the status of things; it re-positions things
within the world.
especially it changes the status and character of the made. Matter moves. Which means
matter, all matter, becomes as I already asserted a minute ago, artificial: all matter is for us,
now, artifice.
Some implications:
(a) If this is so, then, since artifice is always the product of mind, all matter comes within
mind.
(b) Therefore, matter is not other to us. If Toys ‘R’ Us, Matter is us.
(c) The proof of this is climate change. Climate change means we, collectively, have
entered matter: oil is you, coal is you, air is you. To put it another way, all matter is
now mattering. All matter matters differently. All matter is a matter for concern. As we
are continuous with matter so the separation matter/persons falls.
(d) If this is so then the mind–matter distinction falls, and so too, obviously, the sub-
ject–object distinction. The discontinuity between these moments – on which the
entirety of the modern world is built – falls.
(e) Conversely, the entire question becomes for us that of subject–object mediation. This,
I would insist, is the only question that should concern human beings today.
But we need to go still further. It is not even, in fact, a question of subject–object media-
tion, for that formulation still preserves a discontinuity that we must now accept the loss of.
Since, as we know in our hearts, we are essentially failed animals, unable to survive without
mediation, what we have in fact, as us, as ourselves, is subjects seeking the mediators on
which we depend for our lives. (This is Herbert Simon’s ‘search for good designs’).4
120 C. DIlNOT
Three implications:
(1) Certainty disappears (no law). The artificial is the realm of the possible. Possibility
is here not will. It is the objective condition of the artificial.
DeSIGN PHIlOSOPHY PAPeRS 121
(2) The status of truth in the artificial is not that of fact but the possible. The truth of
something is its possibility. We get to an understanding of this truth through the
negotiation of potentiality.
(3) In the artificial, the world is ‘possible’ – but we do not know in advance what that
possibility is; and the possibilities that are explored will always be contingent, a
historical product of encounters. Thinking possibility is thinking these conditions
through the modeled negotiation of possibility (potentiality).
(4) Hence, in the artificial, there is not being, but only possible becoming.
(5) In fact, we can speak about a metaphysics of the artificial – meaning a description
of ‘what is’ and what is true. But this means, in a different sense to other historical
epochs we have made and make the conditions of own metaphysics. What are those
conditions? We can summarize them in this way.
– in the artificial, all artifice, and therefore the artificial as a whole is contingent and
radically so: i.e. lacking any certainty whatsoever
– the artificial is a matter of encounters
– the artificial is a matter of the possible.
My use of the word ‘matter’ here in this context is deliberate.
What does this change? Well, one thing it changes is the relation between knowing (that)
and acting (how).
Previously (under the horizon of nature) we focused on knowing that, i.e. on knowing
what-is, i.e. laws, whether of gods, God or nature. This was where knowledge lay. Theology,
philosophy and science successively confirmed this. In this regime, acting, the question of
‘how,’ is simply applied knowledge. Technology is the obvious instance. Note that as sec-
ond-order knowledge acting is not permitted reflection which itself rises to the condition of
knowing.7 Heidegger’s line, from the essay ‘Overcoming Metaphysics,’ captures this perfectly:
‘Technology as the highest form of rational consciousness, technologically interpreted, and
the lack of reflection as the arranged powerlessness, opaque to itself, to attain a relation to
what is worthy of question, belong together: they are the same thing’ (my emphasis).8
But in the Artificial, all of this reverses. The artificial cannot be known in law-like terms.
The artificial ‘is’ not: it is a perpetual possibility. Therefore ‘what’ the artificial might be (I stress
the conditional) can only be known via how it manifests. In the artificial, the royal road to
understanding is not through contemplation or measurement or ‘research,’ it is through
acting, i.e. it is through, one way or another, no matter how this is conceived, making. The
artificial is known only through what is made, more specifically, what is configured, what is
proposed, what is modeled, prototyped.
What experiment is to science, configurative action and ‘making’ is to the artificial.9 Making
is at once the embodiment of the artificial: its exemplification – its exploration, its discov-
ery – and is itself, always, also a complex symbolic activity and thus a mode of knowing.10
Now we are coming close to design (but we have actually been there all the time).
We can return to the little slide of the variety of modern chairs.
How we know what chairs can be is only by creating chairs. each chair is a proposition con-
cerning what a chair might be. The essence of that proposition, and the factor now that both
links and differentiates objects and designs, is contained in the configuration of each chair.
All things, natural and artificial, have configuration. That is they are physically structured,
and through that structuring enabled to act in certain ways.
122 C. DIlNOT
Notes
1. Design has struggled to attain a quasi-autonomy that turns out itself to be part of the social
and intellectual division of labor. Design is infinitely more determined by historical forces than
it wishes to admit.
2. I have started to explore this in a chapter in Tony Fry, Clive Dilnot and Susan Stewart, Design
and the Question of History (london, Bloomsbury, 2014). See also the chapter ‘Why the Artificial
May Yet Save Us,’ in Design as Future-Making, ed. Susan Yelavich and Barbara Adams (london,
Bloomsbury, Fall 2014).
3. ‘To Contend with What We Have Made’ is the title of a work-in-progress.
DeSIGN PHIlOSOPHY PAPeRS 123
4. ‘The proper study of mankind has been said to be man. But I have argued that people or at
least their intellective component may be relatively simple, that most of the complexity of their
behavior may be drawn from their environment, from their search for good designs. If I have
made my case, then we can conclude that, in large part, the proper study of mankind is the
science of design, not only as the professional component of a technical education but as a
core discipline for every liberally educated person.’ Herbert Simon, The Sciences of the Artificial,
3rd edition (Cambridge, MIT press, 2001) p. 139.
5. That is, at the level of the configuration of the artifact no law can be drafted. There is no Ur law
determining in any a priori form, the configurative character of an artifact. The configuration
(form) of a chair is entirely a matter of encounter and contingency. All chairs are therefore
explorations of what a chair could be. As noted below all chairs are therefore propositions
concerning what a chair could be. The propositional is a condition of the artificial.
6. ‘The contingency of artificial phenomena has always created doubts as to whether they fall
properly within the compass of science. Sometimes these doubts refer to the goal-directed
character of artificial systems and the consequent difficulty of disentangling prescription from
description. This seems to me not to be the real difficulty. The genuine problem is to show how
empirical propositions can be made at all about systems that, given different circumstances,
might be quite other than they are.’ Herbert Simon, The Sciences of the Artificial, 3rd edition
(Cambridge, MIT press, 2001) p. 3.
7. Cf. design. It has never yet been permitted to Design to be thought of as a site of knowledge.
Hence the oxymoron of the idea of the ‘design-led university.’
8. Martin Heidegger, ‘Overcoming Metaphysics’ in Joan Stambaugh, trans., The End of Philosophy
(New York, Harper and Row, 1973) p. 99.
9. The close reading of Heidegger’s text ‘The Age of the World Picture’ is essential here. See The
Question Concerning Technology trans. William lovitt (New York, Harper, 1977) pp. 115–154.
10. Nelson Goodman gets this point perfectly. ‘The primary purpose [of symbolic activity] is
cognition in and for itself: the practicality, pleasure, compulsion & communicative utility all
depend on this. Symbolization, then, is to be judged fundamentally by how well it serves the
cognitive purpose: by the delicacy of its discriminations and the aptness of its allusions; by
the way it works in grasping, exploring and informing the world; by how it analyzes, sorts and
organizes; by how it participates in the making, manipulation, retention and transformation
of knowledge. Considerations of simplicity and subtlety, power and precision, scope and
selectivity, familiarity and freshness, are all relevant and often contend with one another; their
weighting is relative to our interests, our information, our inquiry.’ Languages of Art (Indianapolis,
Bobbs-Merrill, 1969) p. 258.
11. lacan says somewhere that culture is where form gets ‘put on the table.’ Design is (ideally)
the place where the [given] form of things (now interpreting this term in broadest possible
aspects) ‘gets put on the table.’
12. See elaine Scarry, The Body in Pain, chapter 5 passim (Oxford, OUP, 1985).
13. Herbert Simon, The Sciences of the Artificial, ibid, p. 164.
14. Alain Badiou, Ethics (london, Verso, 2003) p. 15. Quotation adapted.
Notes on contributor
Professor of Design Studies, Parsons School of Design, New York