Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Real-World Music As Composed Listening

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 58

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/242216252

Real-World Music as Composed Listening

Article  in  Contemporary Music Review · July 1996


DOI: 10.1080/07494469608629686

CITATIONS READS
37 1,504

1 author:

Katharine Norman
www.novamara.com
5 PUBLICATIONS   51 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by Katharine Norman on 27 August 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Published in:

A Poetry of Reality: Composing with Recorded Sound

Contemporary Music Review, vol 15 Parts 1-2, ISBN 3-7186-5932-8 (1996), Taylor

and Francis (formerly published by Gordon and Breach/Harwood) issue editor

Katharine Norman.

1
Real-World Music as Composed Listening

Katharine Norman

University of Sheffield, Department of Music, 38 Taptonville Road,

Sheffield S10 5BR,UK

Abstract

The paper considers the aesthetic implications of employing sounds from the real

world as musical material. It takes the view that music composed from, and about,

real-world sounds shares concerns already explored by writers and practitioners in

film, poetry and other non-sonic arts. The preoccupations of, among others, film-

makers Eisenstein and Vertov, philosophers Bachelard and Casey and composers

themselves are investigated to support the contention that real-world tape music is

enriched and, to some extent formed, through the listener’s imaginative response: real-

world sounds - their meaning, being and sonic implications - encourage an internalized

listening montage; a composed listening constructed in order to make imaginative

sense from non-narrative sonic journeys.

keywords: listening, montage, representation, imagination, real-world music

2
Real-World Music as Composed Listening

...one need only think of the rumbling of thunder, the whistling

of the wind, the roaring of a waterfall, the gurgling of a brook...the rattling jolt

of a cart on the road, and of the full, solemn, and white breath of a city at night.

...

...Let us cross a large modern capital with our ears more sensitive

than our eyes. ... ...We will amuse ourselves by orchestrating together in our

imagination the din of rolling shop shutters, the varied hubbub of train stations,

iron works, thread mills, printing presses, electrical plants, and subways.

(Russolo,1986, pp. 25-6)

Russolo’s infamous manifesto, written in 1913, is more than an ironic piece of

cultural provocation. His celebration of environmental noise urges us to learn from

real-world sounds and from the way in which we listen to them, to gain understanding

- through investigation and analysis - of both our environments and ourselves. His

proclamations, whilst advocating the philosophical fulfillment of understanding and

enjoying such sounds as purely sonic discourse, also appear to indicate that music

made from them cannot be anything but political.

Eighty years down the line we have the technology to put it all on tape, we’ve had

it for quite a while. Computers give us the power - and it is a certain kind of power -

to ‘orchestrate’ sampled sounds from the ‘real world’, and to use sophisticated

wizardry to cajole them into new forms, frequencies and fantastic documentaries. And

3
while there is a vast body of more ‘abstract’ tape music using real-world sounds as a

basis for sonic alchemy, there is also much music which seeks to preserve our

connection to its recorded sources. In this latter kind of approach the meaning of the

sounds is maintained, heightened or transformed. These pieces are about the real

world.

My intention in this paper is to examine how this ‘real-world music’ might be

construed as arising from a particular aesthetic approach, one which is listening-

centred. Composers working with real-world sounds are, naturally, acutely aware of,

and concerned with, listening: Barry Truax and John Young (both writing in this

journal) provide enlightening appraisals of how we respond to real-world sounds, in

both real life and as music. My initial discussion is similarly concerned with the

listener’s response to real-world sounds, focussed on an investigation of listening as

montage, with direct parallels to be drawn between montage film and documentary art.

For Russolo, the ‘orchestration’ of real-world sounds was an activity necessarily -

in the absence of digital editing - undertaken in the individual listener’s imagination. It

is my thesis that real-world tape music still, and primarily, celebrates that internal

fusion of listening and imagination. In fact it depends on our listening participation and

invites us - through our active, imaginative engagement with ‘ordinary’ sounds - to

contribute, creatively, to the music. In listening to a piece of real-world music we

employ, and develop, the ‘non-musical’ strategies that we ordinarily use, in addition to

our more rarefied musical sensibilities. We expand our understanding of both familiar

sounds and experiences, and of music itself. As listeners, and composers, we may

return to real life disturbed, excited and challenged on a spiritual and social plane by a

music with hands-on relevance to both our inner and outer lives.

4
Listening In

Our ordinary listening is itself a complex, multi-layered activity of which hearing

is but a part. In going about our everyday listening lives we take - I suggest - several

different, but interdependent, stances, which amount to a dynamic construct.

References, memories, associations, symbols - all contribute to our understanding of

sonic meaning. Rather than deprive us of this activity, the real-world composer can

treat it as a creative force, one which may be influenced, changed or subtlely directed

to give us an enriched understanding of real-world sounds : listening is as much a

‘material’ for the composer as the sounds themselves.

Referential listening

So, how do we listen ? In real life, we tend primarily to understand sounds as

referring to objects or events, and we use memory to to recall this essential

information. By invoking recognition and contextual judgments we decide on a

sound’s immediate relevance to our situation - whether it’s worth listening to. Sounds

lead us towards references to sounding things, and in this way referential meanings for

sound could be attributed to reminiscences awakened through the sound’s agency.

Yet, on listening, our immediate reaction is to supplement, or supplant, sound with

visual data; we look for the sounding object, either in reality or by using remembered

knowledge to envisage a likely source. The persistent dependency of sound on sight

5
could be seen as a corrective strategy; visualization provides information that listening

either contradicts, or fails to convey. Perhaps visualization is more than a

reinforcement of actual aural perception; it is also an attempt to bring a sonic

experience into the temporal reality of our presence.

Presence, naturally, is defined in terms of time and space. “To be

in the presence of someone” is to recognize him as existing contemporaneously

with us and to note that he comes within the actual range of our senses.

(Bazin, 1967, p. 96)

In ordinary experience we each place ourselves at the centre of our personal

temporal universe and judge things to be here and now only when they infiltrate our

attention. Bazin neglects to stress the primacy of sight in our evaluation of what is

present - as a film-maker, he takes it for granted. But attention here is synonymous

with sight : we insist on visual perception as our window on temporal presence despite

the fact that many other perceptions continually invade our consciousness. As a sound

impinges on our listening attention we create an internal visual presence to bring the

experience into our perceptual ‘now’. For instance, a telephone conversation makes

especial demands on our consciousness because, as McLuhan suggests, the auditory

image needs to be strengthened by other senses.1 But, surely the reason for this lies

not in the quality of the auditory image but in the fact that the experience is insistently

present in our attention without providing confirmatory visual data. This is untenable

for our visually weighted understanding of presence, so we make a strong and

comprehensive visual picture to fit a voice. All our senses ultimately inform our

6
experience of how we exist in time and, with sight as a primary means of defining

what is happening in our presence, we readily visualize to draw other senses into our

temporal domain.

There are other ways, perhaps less consciously perceived, in which sounds can

influence our perceptual understanding and defy the symbiotic relationship between

sight and sound. Consider, for instance, sounds such as alarms and sirens, or pealing

church bells. The meanings that we allocate to these types of sound arise from a

contradiction in our referential listening processes, directly attributable to the volume

of the sound. These sounds surely claim our full attention, yet they are usually

disembodied visually from their sounding objects. Although the objects themselves do

not enter our presence their sound, through its continuous and loud insistence, seems

near to the point of immediacy.

Loud sounds can disorientate us through an apparent spatial proximity - the

hypothetical object seems to be here, now - that contradicts a failure to allocate a focal

visual source. The confusion arising from this deprivation of visual confirmation

brings us to a point of timelessness where nothing matters except the aural presence of

the sound and we expend little, if any, energy on attempts to imagine the physical

source. And this, of course, is the response intended by alarms and sirens, whose role

is to alert us to danger - a learnt association - rather than refer us to their sounding

objects.

Some musical examples

Transferred to a musical domain, the implication that disembodied real-world

sounds must be loud in order to have true ‘presence’ for the listener becomes an issue

7
for the composer. The frequently voiced criticism of tape music as ‘lacking’ in visual

stimulation may have less to do with unsuitable performance or playback scenarios

than with the very fact that we are distanced from disembodied real-world sounds in

both musical and real life circumstances, and in tape music circumstances all sounds

are disembodied. Such criticisms indicate an unsuccessful attempt to find listening

parallels between our relationship to recorded sounds and to the sounds of live musical

instruments. Perhaps it would be more appropriate to seek similarities between

referential listening in real life and in the concert hall. For instance, the sheer volume

and intensity of many tape pieces mirrors the immediacy of alarms and sirens and may

arise from a similar attempt to force sounds into the individual listener’s presence,

despite the lack of a visually perceived source. We could make an interesting

comparison between sonic amplification and Bazin’s evaluation of visual enlargement

in film:

What we lose by way of direct witness do we not recapture

thanks to the artificial proximity provided by photographic enlargement ?

Everything takes place as if in the time-space perimeter which is the definition

of presence.... ...the increase in the space factor re-establishes the equilibrium

of the psychological equation.

(Bazin, 1967, p.98)

As a musical example, Stockhausen’s dramatic use of a real-world sound as a

structural device in his work Trans makes judicious use of our propensity to give

‘presence’ to loud sounds. The sound engendered by a mundane object - a weaving

8
shuttle - is transmuted by amplification into an enlarged and alarming entity, which

takes full control of our aural attention. Here, the absence of visual stimulus aids the

effectiveness of a sound whose role is to momentarily confound our understanding of

temporal flow. We are encouraged to regard the sound as distinct and ‘timeless’ in

relation to the progress of the movement - visual and temporal - of the instrumental

music.

A shuttle of a weaving chair passing loudly through the hall from

the left to the right, shooting through the air. And with each shuttle sound the

string players were beginning the next upward movement of their bows, all

synchronously, and then in the middle of the duration between two shuttle

sounds, they started a downward motion. Another shuttle sound, and they

played a new note. The first shuttle sound opens the chromatically dense wall at

a certain interval, closes it with the next sound.

(Stockhausen in Cott, 1973, p.55).

In this case whether we recognize the sound as that of a weaving shuttle is less

important than whether we interpret it as communicating a particular kind of

mechanical side-to-side movement; an abstraction of the sound’s real-world meaning

is sufficient and intended. And this dissociation of visual and aural meaning is

borrowed from our listening to alarms and other ‘present’ sounds since, by changing

our normal listening relationship to the shuttle sound, Stockhausen discourages

visualization and encourages us to refer not to the cause of the sound but to the

external information it conveys. The disembodied sound becomes symbolic of a kind

9
of movement which, in turn, becomes an analogy for the ‘slicing’ of the musical form

which it initiates. Indeed the left-to-right spatial projection heightens this significance

by translating visual data into aural terms.

It seems that, once a sound has become timeless and source-less, in the manner

described, we are free to extend our temporal understanding outside the frame of the

physically perceived environment to the world of historical remembrance. In this

manner sounds are listened to, not as emanations from a visual source but as informing

symbols imbued with culturally acquired significance. Although we recognize

Stockhausen’s weaving shuttle as a real-world sound, its actual provenance isn’t

something we strive to ascertain, in fact we probably can’t. Instead we accept it as a

‘generic’ sound from life, one that has attained a symbolic significance independent of

its physical source.

Every sound has its cultural tale to tell although the older the symbolic knowledge,

the more likely we are to appreciate the historical breadth of its informing content.

Consider churchbells whose religious symbolism reaches a far wider audience than the

Christian community. A large proportion of listeners, in the Western world at least,

will be touched by the story of these sounds. And, for the composer, such well-

established sound symbols provide a conceptual vocabulary which will have meaning

for the audience:

Any attentive reader of newspapers will have noticed the old

trick by which his or her attention is sought - the classic first paragraph in

which the essence of a story is presented with maximum impact. Harvey

10
achieves precisely this, opening Mortuos with a vigorous carillon of bells

which gradually declines in intensity until only two or three slowly pealing

bells are left ... (Campbell, 1986, p.524)

Philip Campbell doesn’t elaborate precisely on how ‘maximum impact’ is made at

the opening of Harvey’s work; we might naturally assume it sufficient that the sounds

are loud, sonorous and interesting to the ear. But the force of the impact comes as we

encounter a known symbol which refers us to a learnt meaning for ‘church bells’. The

symbolic association of bells with worship and the web of meanings that leads them to

‘enumerate the fleeing hours...mourn the dead...call the living to prayer’2 continues to

inform because the cultural history of the sound is ingrained.

In the composer’s words :

We constitute the music according to the interplay of the

composer’s codes and our own, the references to past meaning and usage of

sound, the patterning of repetition and variation within the work itself. A

Chinese peasant’s codes would be totally different from Wagner’s, and our own

different from both.(my italics)

(Harvey, 1985, p.11)

While referential listening connects sounds to objects, to measurements of time and

place and to learnt ‘symbols’, the latter connection finds us removed from our initial

attachment of sights to sounds into a world of conceptual meaning. In broadening our

investigation of real-world listening to include such attention we might find that, once

11
we get past seeing things , we can obtain a deeper experience of qualities, rather than

quantified relationships, of time and space.

Reflective listening

The above discussion indicates that real-world sounds are loaded towards

referential listening, unlike the more abstract timbres of musical instruments whose

‘imaginary’ world status is clearly delineated. But that isn’t to say that real-world

listening is devoid of imaginative activity. How - and why - do we hear the ‘song’ of

the sea ? To do this we have to switch listening channels to a less usual, reflective type

of attention. This reflective listening is neither a contemplation of an action invoked -

Stockhausen’s moving shuttle - nor a meditation on its extra-sonic cultural history -

Harvey’s ecclesiastical bells - but a creative, enjoyable appraisal of the sound for its

acoustic properties. Yet, although it might seem that reflective and referential listening

are independent activities, I prefer to see them as working together as a means of

synthesizing our knowledge and our enjoyment of real-world sounds.

To hear music in the sea we change our usual relation to the sound, allowing

interested enchantment to eclipse alert information-gathering. As in daydreams and

reveries a perceptual shift lulls us into ‘forgetting’ how, and why, things normally

make sense. Instead, we use our ears and minds to create, or reinterpret, imagined

meanings for the sound. This seems to be diametrically opposed to referential

listening in which we take considerable pains to ‘remember’ how things are. But what

conditions encourage reflective rather than referential listening ? If a real-world sound

can be responded to with either it seems likely that optimum conditions for the one

must separate, or mute, an inclination to focus in on the other. We need to consider

12
what inner processes invite a particular listening stance.

Remembered content is actual in status; it is something that we

assume has in fact appeared or occured on some previous occasion (even if we

cannot now recall the precise moment). Imagined content, in contrast, is purely

possible in status, it is something that, at most, might have appeared or

occurred previously or that might yet do so in the future. Positing imagined

content as only possible, I am not as engrossed in it as such; my attention

wanders more freely beyond this content to its immediate environs and more

particularly to its margin, where still other possibilities might emerge. When I

posit remembered content as actual, however, I tend to remain riveted to it,

and I am correspondingly less tempted to transcend it toward a marginal region

that lacks such sturdy actuality.

(Casey, 1987, p. 77)

Taking Casey’s description as a model for response to real-world sounds, we could

take the view that an interest in the acoustic qualities of a sound prompts us towards

imagined content while a focus on referential meaning prompts recognition, that is

remembered content. Assuming the real-world sound’s ability to represent meanings

of either the particular or the general when disembodied - as with Stockhausen’s

shuttle sound - then the sound can act alternatively as an agent for remembrance or

imaginative fantasy. (In this sense I classify straightforward recognition as

‘remembering’ the significance of the sound from its sensory data.) Secondly, Casey’s

assessment of remembered versus imagined content proposes a dependency of inward

13
attentiveness on content for each. This suggests that, in the case of imaginative,

reflective listening for instance, we move toward a particular kind of inward

attentiveness. By precluding the attentiveness for remembered content we are moved

away from our usual relation to sound as a referential trigger. This hypothesis

represents an idealized model in which imagination and remembering are completely

estranged and, if it is true, we should switch from hearing at one moment the sound of

the waves and the next a sound which makes no sense at all, completely divorced from

‘sturdy actuality’ and taking the sound’s disembodiment one step further to a stage

where even significatory meaning is abandoned.

But reflective listening, as with other perceptual interpretations, doesn’t in reality

achieve complete estrangement of memory and imagination. This apparent deficiency

is especially true of real-world sounds: we can’t pretend that we don’t know them.

Imagination, nevertheless, enables us to attend to remembered data in a creative and

free-wheeling way that needs make fewer concessions to commonplace perception;

conditions for reflective listening mean that we do not need to hear the sound of waves

but can instead imaginatively recognize them as whispers, hissing or any other

comparable remembrance. In seeking to clarify the difference between remembering

and imagination Casey goes on to suggest that we ‘compare, for example, the

visualization of a wholly imagined friend with the visualization of a remembered

friend’. But there can surely be no such thing as a ‘wholly imagined friend’; our

imaginings are composite fantasies on experienced data. So, inevitably, tensions are

set up by a friction between imagined and remembered content and conflicting types of

simultaneously perceived meaning.

This continuous shifting between referential remembering and reflective,

14
imaginative forgetting may be constructive in itself. Perhaps one nourishes the other so

that contradictory meanings can provide a multi-faceted and richer understanding of a

source. Compare, for instance, the way we remember a new acquaintance in terms of

friends they resemble, until we know them better. This is a fairly simple example of a

deficiency in terms of recognition - we do not know this person from previous

experience - being supplemented by imagination’s propensity to fill the gaps with

remembered data. And the data can be remarkably obscure as our imaginative

‘attention wanders more freely ... ...to its margin, where still other possibilities might

emerge’; we can perhaps come up with remembered vocal inflections or a subtle

physical gesture, or even a way of sneezing, to help our understanding.

How does this compare with the imaginative conditions of reflective listening to

real-world sounds which are, after all, familiar friends rather than casual acquaintances

? Perhaps we can find a connection in the perceptual games we play to ‘deceive’ us

into perceiving fictions in everyday experiences. When we find faces in the wallpaper,

demons dancing in a fire or voices in the wind we are playing a similar game of

imaginative substitution but in these cases with less imperatively functional intent. So

there are fewer constraints on how freely imaginative attention can wander and we’re

at liberty to produce startlingly distant possibilities. And, in the case of these

examples, we have time to do so; all of them represent continuously transmitting

sources which are recognized in an instant, but leave temporal room to spare.

Although survival requires instant, or at least fast, recognition of a source, attention is

less weighted to remembered content while the source continues. Synthesizer sounds

which splice sampled instrumental attacks to crude synthetic sustains are practical

15
examples which exploit our tendency to lose referential interest. So, time can suspend

the source from its usual context; after we see the log-fire, we sit down to watch it for

demons. In the same way we listen to the song of the sea after we’ve heard, and

recognized, the waves though, in reality, we never stop hearing them completely.

But this still doesn’t quite account for why we delve up such distant and intricate

images as demons and faces, voices and songs to describe the complex appearance of

diverse phenomena. This part of the game exhibits an attention to the behaviour of the

source and represents another attempt to make sense of the unknown.

They had a game they would play, sitting at a coffeehouse. They

would ask: How far away is the nearest strange attractor ? Was it that rattling

automobile fender ? That flag snapping erratically in a steady breeze ? A

fluttering leaf ? “You don’t see something until you have the right metaphor to

let you perceive it,” Shaw said...

(Gleick, 1987, p. 262)

Imagined content produces metaphors for complex behaviour that would otherwise

be interpreted as chaotic and meaningless. These metaphors are obviously going to be

dependent on to what extent the behaviour seems chaotic, and that will naturally vary

from one person to another as will the ‘right metaphor’ that imagination provides. But

metaphors denote, they don’t explain, and the right metaphor must come from an

understanding, at some level, of the structure of the behaviour. In reflective listening

to the sea we are, again, shifting our relation to sensory perceptions in an attempt to

evade normative understanding, but we are also noting sensory messages that don’t

16
generally warrant perceptual attentiveness such as subtle changes in amplitude or

pitch. If, estranged from its referential meaning, the ordinary real-world sound would

have seemed confusingly random, making no sense at all, now we can take an

unusually analytical approach in order to explain it. To find a metaphor we

perceptually deconstruct the sound and listen to it as temporally shaped behaviour in a

constant state of flux. We try continually to build relationships between what we are

analytically perceiving and what we know. We are listening differently. As we

actively engage both referential and reflective listening stances, our freely wandering

attention to imaginative content is, all the time, travelling further in order to obtain the

‘right’ metaphors to summarise this acquisition of knowledge. The metaphors, in turn,

change as perceptual understanding increases, giving us pitches, rhythms, songs,

voices - whatever comes to mind.

Contextual listening

We evidently enjoy attempting games in which, to quote Nietzsche, ‘the

overturning of experience into its opposite, the purposive into the purposeless, of the

necessary into the arbitrary... ...delights us, for it momentarily liberates us from the

constraints of the necessary’ (Nietzsche, p. 512). Perhaps we can compare this to our

response to humour; we laugh at punchlines that strike home with a shock or surprise

because, in the context of a joke, they are non-threatening. Similarly, in reflective

listening we direct our attention over the source without any preconceived intent, other

than a willingness to fall prey to perceptual deceit. But the material, its context and

our relation to both each change in time so that, although we may direct our reflective

listening attention over real-world sounds, there is always the strong possibility that, at

17
any moment, circumstances will force a ‘cut’ to reality. Real life perceptual games are

difficult and ‘delight’ will always be qualified by contextual constraints; if we only see

demonsin the fire or hear songs in the sea we wander into the realms of unintelligible

hallucination. Vacillations between memory and imagination have to be fine-tuned to

our evaluation of the material’s contextual significance.

This implies that both referential and reflective listening activity in fact takes place

over a pervasive ground, through which material and context are interrelated and

evaluated. It is this ground, an amassing of individually experienced knowledge, that

extends beneath all our new experiences to influence and constrain our perceptual

direction. Prior to any acquisition of specific referential information, we relate our

current experience to our experiential history, to the context of our lives. Inwardly

comparing remembered and presently experienced personal contexts for the material,

we make a judgement as to its likely referential importance. So, contextual listening

relates the material to the context of our individual history, and influences both the

extent of our imaginative wanderings and the nature of the meanings they provide.

Creative tensions arise when the interrelationship between context and material is

disturbed so that contextual importance indicates the presence of referential meaning

that we’re unable to perceive. As an example we could consider our response to

language - contextually essential to all our lives - when verbal meaning is in some

way obscured. Jung remarks on a colleague’s journey on a Russian train during which

‘though he ... ... could not even decipher the Cyrillic script, he found himself musing

over the strange letters in which the railway notices were written and ... ...he imagined

all sorts of meanings for them.’(Jung, 1964, p. 27) Successive attempts at finding

referential meanings in material with known contextual importance lead imaginatively

18
to ‘all sorts of meanings’ for an unfamiliar actuality.

Similarly, when listening to human speech that is somehow made linguistically

incomprehensible, we find it difficult to mute referential perceptions because of the

important human context of this real-world sound. This places us in a frustrated

listening position in which contextual knowledge points to a vast substructure of

referential meaning - the communication of thoughts and emotions, syntactical logic,

indications of cultural and personal character - to which we are denied complete

access. Trying to gain entry to this mass of referential knowledge we gather all our

listening resources about us to perceive the source afresh. In fact, we re-perceive it,

attempting to create referential, and contextually relevant, order from the acoustic

properties of a cryptic sound. Our appraisal of its qualities now springs from an intent

to find informing relationships in the sound - accent, intonation, speech rhythms or

imagined verbal content - through a fusion of reflective and referential listening

stances.

Participating

This compulsion to ‘make sense’ of sounds is interesting; it seems that we are

prepared to go to extreme perceptual lengths in our desire to relate an obscured source

to experienced models. The more mysterious the material, the more ambitious our

perceptual reconstruction and the more varied the relationships we are willing to

entertain. We want to make these confusing sounds relevant to the fabric of our lives,

to contextualise them. And, I contend, we retain this participatory activity in listening

to real-world music.

19
Techniques such as processing and mixing give the composer the opportunity to

obscure real-world sounds, and so deny our easy access to referential clues without

entirely severing our contextual connection with the source. She can guide us on a

circuitous perceptual journey in which her re-perceptions of the sound direct our own,

creative, listening. In this sense we could regard the composer as just another listener,

but one who publicly reveals a rarefied listening process through her transformation of

the sound. In this sense we might compare her position to that of the film director who

reveals a re-perception of real-world narrative through the temporal refinement of

montage, but never disallows the viewer’s personal experience.

each spectator creates an image along the representational

guidance suggested by the author, leading him unswervingly towards knowing

and experiencing the theme in accordance with his own personality, in his own

individual way, proceeding from his own experience, from his own

imagination, from the texture of his associations, from the features of his own

character, temper, and social status. The image is at one and the same time the

creation of the author and the spectator.

(Eisenstein, 1986, p. 78)

As summarised by Bazin, who was, however, ultimately critical of this approach to

film, ‘the meaning is not in the image, it is in the shadow of the image projected by

montage onto the field of consciousness of the spectator.’(Bazin, 1967, p. 26) On

watching a film, we place the director’s image in the context of our own lives.

20
Montage can function similarly in real-world music: for instance, Harvey’s

gloriously familiar pealing bells are abruptly followed by a confusingly alien world

where individual spectral components are slowly explored. We retain our recent

memory of the source while experiencing sounds whose strange, but familiar, progress

clouds our contextual judgements. The music continues with similar juxtapositions

and is just one example, from many, of a work combining montage techniques with

more traditional relationships of pitch and timbre.

This kind of montage, in both film and music, might be defined as horizontal in

nature. Ultimately our re-perception of the material is guided by linear divisions of

time. But there is also, in both film and music, the possibility of what we might call a

vertical montage3. The composer can offer superimposed layers of sonic

transformation while appearing to preserve the temporal duration of a real-world

scenario. Instead of slavishly following a composer-directed narrative, we create an

inwardly perceived dynamic as our listening re-perception travels to and fro.

Paul Lansky’s Night Traffic appears to preserve the temporal flow of recorded

traffic sounds while submitting them to radical transformation. In fact the temporal

narrative is also surreptitiously tuned to both rhythmic patterns and the harmonic

rhythm of slowly changing chords. Nevertheless, we are left with the sensation that

the music’s linear time is a naturalistic reproduction of reality. Already his subtle

directon of time gives the impression that it is our listening attention, not the

composer’s manipulation, that creates the horizontal dynamic. The sounds themselves

are transformed with equal subtlety; the timbre of the source is never completely

obscured, instead it is lit by comb-filtered pitches which focus, rather than destroy, our

21
awareness of contextual meaning. Similarly, and importantly, controlled panning of

the sounds mimics the spatial effect of passing traffic and places each listener firmly

at the centre of the experience.

With a great deal of understated listener-direction, Lansky deceives us into

thinking that we create the music in these sounds. Everything conspires to place us at

the centre of the work - from the persistent familiarity of the sounds to their listener-

centred movement. There is just enough contextual confusion - in the filtered pitches,

the evolving harmonic progression and also the slightly unnerving sense of an invisible

approaching object - to encourage a perceptual quest. At the same time there is

enough recognition to maintain our concern with real-world significance and the many

associations attached to such culturally powerful, and pervasive, sounds

Compared to Harvey’s Mortuos plango, Lansky’s subtle direction is no less

rigorous, but is possibly more demanding of the listener. It places far more weight on

our individual response and encourages us towards the satisfying impression that we

aid the creation of the music through our perceptual activity. We might say that, in

doing this, he solves the problems of audience alienation often attributed to tape music.

How can we feel alienation when we’re part of the music ourselves ? In both his

treatment of the subject and his attitude to the listener, Lansky achieves a gently

political work.

Listening Montage in Real-World Music

If the composer’s ‘direction’ of our listening can, in some way, make us feel that

22
we participate in the creation of the work, we need some analysis of the means and

effect of that direction. Why are real-world sounds, and our ordinary, real life,

relationship to them, so essential to its success ? Perhaps because, once our real-world

listening response can be guaranteed, the composer is at liberty to place ‘noise’ in our

perceptual channels, confusing, obstructing or colouring our normal understanding of

the sounds. This leaves our evaluation of who is ‘intending’ our listening at any one

time in a constant state of flux, along with our evaluation of the ‘being’ of the real-

world sound. At one moment recorded traffic sounds, the next a quasi-tonal

progression of filtered chords. Real-world and abstract, ‘musical’ listening - and the

various combinations and permutations within them - get so mixed up in our

responsive endeavours that they engender a kind of internal ‘listening montage’.

Ultimately they cease to exist as distinct from one another as we ‘re-assemble’ the

relationships between them.

montage is proposed purposefully as a kit designed to be

assembled, while collage is nothing but a mixed bag full of obviously

incongruous components

(Thomas, 1983, p. 85)

But montage, as opposed to collage, strives for coherence through confusion. And,

as in montage, our individual reconstitution of intentionally confused listening stances

becomes a part of the real-world work.

Confusion of intent

23
Real-world listening - our ordinary, quite possibly creative, take on sounds as we

attend to them in real life - might be classified, or included, as self-intended listening.

While attention is the state of applying our mind to, in this case, sounds, intention is

the determination - an active process - to ‘stretch out’ towards this state. Through

intention we make the transition from passive hearing to attentive listening. In this

sense, self-intended listening occurs when the imaginative decisions that lead to a

creative or analytical consideration of sounds are largely, if not entirely, of our own

volition. In Cageian terms self-intended listening can certainly be musical; as

individual inhabitants of the real world, we can ‘let sounds be themselves’ and make a

conscious decision to attend, musically, to our natural environment. But then we

create our ‘own’ music, and we do not seek, neither are we able, to transmit the

inwardly-formed result to another individual And although our appraisal of abstract

sonic relationships in ordinarily occuring sounds is certainly, as I’ve discussed,

encouraged by contextual considerations, it is, finally, our own choice. As we sit on

the beach, revelling in our sonic environment, no person ‘tells’ us that we might listen

to the ‘song’ of the sea. Of course, the real life context may defeat a desire to reflect

creatively: if we were drowning, we’d probably take less aesthetic delight in sonic

matters ; presumably, even if we wanted to listen reflectively, we’d have difficulty in

doing so. Yet, in both cases, our priorities are molded by external, fortuitous

circumstances rather than an external, communicating individual.

This last point is essential to a distinction between self-intended and composer-

intended4 listening. Initially it would seem that composer-intended listening is

synonymous with ‘musical’ listening, in the traditional sense of listening out for an

abstract sonic discourse. That isn’t to say that the composer dictates, or can dictate,

24
how we listen but merely that she intends our listening to be attuned to the perception

of acoustic relationships, sonic architecture and the like. In a concert hall we are

already contextually conditioned to expect this intent and we are somewhat more open

to aural suggestion, perhaps, than in real life. We are switched into the ‘correct’

listening channel. But, regardless of whether we hear music in an ‘appropriate’,

encouraging context - the concert hall, or coming out of our CD player - or in

unprepared, real-world circumstances - as we do the weekly shopping, in a lift, through

an open window -we appear to know that a composer intended us to listen to the

sounds in a particular, ‘musical’, way. We decide that we are hearing ‘someone else’s’

music.

Or so it seems. In fact the ground is already shifting beneath our feet since the

perceived distinction between composer-intended and self-intended listening is

disempowered when the two fuse, or con-fuse each other. For instance, Alvin

Lucier’s I am sitting in a room shows an exquisite awareness of the potentialities of

transforming our self-intended experience of real-world sounds into composer-

intended music, through the introduction of surreptitious intentional confusion.

In this work Lucier’s natural speaking voice - complete with stutter- informs us of

his actions and then, as this recorded speech is successively re-recorded in the same

environment, an accumulation of reverberating frequencies transfigures his words into

clouds of resonant pitch. Lucier’s complete text is as follows:

I am sitting in a room different from the one you are in now. I

am recording the sound of my speaking voice and I am going to play it back

25
into the room again and again until the resonant frequencies of the room

reinforce themselves so that any semblance of my speech, with perhaps the

exception of rhythm, is destroyed. What you will hear, then, are the natural

resonant frequencies of the room articulated by speech. I regard this activity

not so much as a demonstration of a physical fact, but, more as a way to smooth

out any irregularities my speech might have.

Lucier is careful to avoid referring to musical listening or, indeed, listening of any

kind. His words refer solely to a description of what we will hear. He tells us what he

is going to do, and then he does it; listening, it appears, is entirely up to us. Indeed, as

the work commences we seem to be entirely engaged in self-intended, real-world

listening. We recognize and process speech, we may well reflectively contemplate the

‘musical’ qualities of its patterns but in, at this stage, an informative rather than an

interpretive context. As the work progresses the reflective aspects of real-world

listening take over, the context expands to encompass both ‘demonstration’ and

musical ‘performance’, and our engagement with pitches, rhythms and timbral

resonances is successively heightened. Yet all these phenomena happen

simultaneously and, also at the same time, our referential attention to words is

imaginatively redefined. For each of us there comes a point, or rather there isn’t a

discernible point, where we are listening to music as well as listening musically to

real-world sounds. When the work ends, forty-five minutes later, we are left in no

doubt that Lucier-intended listening has directed our own intent. But we’re also in no

doubt that our intent made music from what we heard. This is confusing. It’s all the

more confusing since , in reality, this work is nothing more than a demonstration, a

26
process set in motion by the composer but left to run without any creative intervention.

We’re ‘duped’ by our assumptions, but our willing ‘suspension of disbelief’ enables

us to appreciate more fully the musical attributes of a natural phenomenon.

Noise as interference

Ultimately, Lucier’s work disrupts the powerful connection between listener and

language by putting noise in our communication channel. In this case it’s done,

literally, through the ‘noisy’ reverberation of the room, but this is just one means of

confusing the listening intent of speech. Luc Ferrari’s Presque Rien avec filles

achieves a similar confusion simply through the superimposition of material. This

work takes candid recordings of environmental sounds and edits them seamlessly

together. But his material includes speech, in French, German and Italian. By layering

the three simultaneously Ferrari effectively confuses our recognition of intent. If we

understand one of the languages, its communication of intent draws our attention while

the others appeal more for their sonic content. Yet, even if we understand all, or none,

of the languages concerned the experience is confusing. Are we listening to a surreal

multi-lingual conversation ? Are we in three places at once ? What are they talking

about ? Are their linguistic messages connected ?

These disconcerting questions plague us because, despite the fact that we also

appreciate the speech for its purely sonic profile, its listening intent is demanding. And

Ferrari’s layering brings noise to our self-intended, real-world understanding, through

which we evaluate the ‘being’ of a sound.

On the face of it, the composer’s creation of cognitive noise might seem a perverse

activity because noise generally pollutes communication and confounds explanation.

27
Or, rather, it confounds the expected explanation and makes for a more volatile,

unpredictable relationship between compser and listener. But when the ‘noise’

amplifies the confusion between listening intents the resulting volatility may provide

new listening discoveries. Marie Maclean shares this sentiment with regard to growth

in narrative form:

[noise] can be an invaluable stimulus, constantly setting the

challenge of winning the battle for control.... ...The disruptive input of anarchy ,

of violence, of noise, stimulates the mutation and the new growth of narrative

forms and their evolution within the wider interplay of social forces.

(Maclean, 1988, p.3)

Perhaps, also, noisily frustrated intents can lead to ‘new growth’ in our listening

habits. Paul Lansky’s The Lesson is a rather different work from Lucier’s, but it also

uses speech and frustrates the intents of language. But Lansky’s work creates

cognitive noise of a complex, dynamic kind by blithely frustrating all intents. Through

making all our listening channels noisy and unstable, The Lesson prevents us from

clinging to any one point on our listening dial. But of course we might discover new,

and more interesting, stations this way - ones we’d never heard of.

Lansky takes some speech (from a friend, and colleague, J.K.Randall) and

processes it continuously. Like several of his speech-based works the processing

largely takes the form of plucked string synthesis which is generated by the amplitude

contours of the speaker’s inflection and tuned to particular chords. So while the speech

engenders the processing, the processing obscures the speech.

28
But this work is, for Lansky, unusual in two particular respects. Firstly, for a

significant proportion of the time the words, and vestiges of the speaker’s natural

timbres, are heard intelligibly, or semi-intelligibly. Secondly, the harmonies have a

distinct sense of ‘progression’ which is heightened by careful voice-leading, and aided

by sustained vocal tones. The composer reveals connected reasons for his decisions:

The Lesson uses more complex ‘sort-of-atonal’ harmonies, with

fairly complex voice leading relations. I remember struggling long and hard

with these issues there and deciding that this sort of voice leading was much

more analogous to the reasoning processes of JKR than my approaches in

Quakerbridge or Night Traffic etc.. I think that using these latter approaches

with JKR’s texts would have made his words seem silly.

(from correspondence with the author)

J.K.Randall’s words are entirely relevant to our discussion since they are

concerned with his experiential evaluation of listening to Mozart and Beethoven, and

this is perhaps why Lansky allows us teasing glimpses of the speaker’s meaning. But

they are only fleeting allusions since the text is fragmented in a random collage and the

processing ultimately frustrates our engagement with the listening intent of speech.

Repeated listenings reveal a little more each time, but there will always be moments of

complete confusion as particularly dense flurries of plucks obscure the words entirely

while simultaneously signalling their existence. Even then, as in the popular story of

the young Tolstoy, standing in the corner trying ‘not to think of a white bear’, we are

constantly frustrated by trying ‘not to’ perceive speech.

29
The plucks seem to impose a particular cognitive noise on the speech; on the intent

of its ‘being’, its linguistic meaning, and the timbre and inflections of its sound. But

the loudest cognitive noise comes from a more ‘traditional’ direction. While trying to

‘parse the damn thing’ (one of the few intelligible spoken phrases in the work ) I

discovered that words were far easier to discern when, winding the tape back and forth,

I randomly selected very short sections. In doing so, I removed all harmonic

progression. For a few seconds only, the words suddenly emerged more clearly, as did

the disconcerting realization that the composer had very tangibly filtered, or intended,

my listening. This implies that the familiar logic of an harmonic progression had

effectively frustrated the intent of speech and also implies that Lansky’s choice of

tonal or ‘sort-of-atonal’ vocabulary achieves far more than mere sonic appeal.

This work is especially intriguing, then, because we are presented with a

complexity of intents which each impose noise on the other, since the speech and the

plucked rhythms also introduce their own cognitive noise to, for instance, the

harmonic rhythm. Our listening attention flits rapidly from one to another, sometimes

of our own, individual volition, often through the fluctuations created within the work.

We are confused, and frustrated, and yet we’re compelled by the result.

Transforming the being of the sound

While assembling our montage ‘kit’ from intentional confusion, cognitive noise

and frustrated expectations, we begin to see that our precarious listening situation is

changing our relationship to sounds. As our listening is questioned and fragmented, so

is our evaluation of what sounds mean, of their essential being.

Each of the above musical examples makes use of speech, a sound with a peculiar

30
and important being. Lucier could have used any sound source for the same

‘demonstration’ but instead:

decided to use speech; it’s common to just about everybody and

is a marvelous sound source. ... ...It’s also extremely personal.

(Lucier interviewed by Simon, liner notes to I am Sitting in a Room)

His observation understates the significance that speech itself ‘intends’ towards our

ears. As previously discussed, speech has an unusually defined being and we honour

it with special attention, even if we don’t understand the language concerned, because

it speaks of communication. We cannot choose to ignore it, for it communicates such a

variety of emotional, intellectual and sonic information. Try listening to a subtitled

foreign film with the sound down and see how much you miss.

So, while Lucier plays with listener and composer intents he does so with material

that makes its own demands, constantly. The source exacerbates his fruitful confusion

since, even when the intelligibility of the words becomes completely lost in the ringing

reverberation, their meaning resonates in our minds. We retain what might be called

‘speech-intended’ listening to the end; as each re-recording proceeds we compare and

contrast it with the remembered original, we attempt to perceive the sound of the

words by continuing to delve for remnants of verbal meaning. The being of speech as

a sound source insistently transmits its own listening intent.

Similarly, Lansky and, to a lesser extent, Ferrari are engaged in compositional

activity which interacts with, rather than radically transforms, the being of the speech.

A great deal of The Lesson’s attraction lies in the resilience of the source. As in other

31
speech-based works by Lansky, we certainly come to perceive speech differently,

revelling in its rhythmic and spectral content in a manner which enriches its being, but

the enduring magic resides in the persistence of its being, against all odds.

But when a composer engages with a real-world source, or sources, of less

‘focussed’ significance, the result can be very different since our listening montage can

causes changes in our evaluation of being.

An obvious way to ‘de-focus’ the being of a sound is to remove it from its usual

context and thus deprive us of our contextual listening judgements. Acousmatic music

chooses to take this decontextualization beyond the point of real-world understanding,

abstracting sounds completely from their being. However, it need not be the case.

Ferrari’s Hétérozygote, for instance, is a somewhat pointillistic collage of real-world

fragments, ranging from speech to birds, to ambiguously perceived noises. Out of

context, we have no environment in which to place these sounds. Unlike his Presque

Rien pieces, there is no attempt at conveying a ‘realistic’ context. The only context is

the rhythmic environment defined by the sounds in time. As incongruent

superimpositions and momentary real-world allusions assail our ears, we start to listen

to sounds as musical objects, almost as ‘notes’ or ‘phrases’, but without ever losing our

connection to their real-world provenance. At the same time, we persist in attempts to

make some kind of narrative out of contradictory real-world meanings. As a result of

their decontextualization, sounds whose being, in real life, might be deemed of passing

significance become essential to our musical understanding.

Jean-Claude Risset’s Sud provides an example whose very subject is this active

process of transformation. He does this by confusing our recognition of a sound’s

32
origins, so that our appraisal of the being of the sound is frequently, and continuously,

disrupted. In Sud we are, at all times, confronted with a careful amalgam of ‘real’

sounds - largely unadulterated real-world sounds - and ‘imaginary’ sounds -

transformed real-world sounds or entirely synthetic timbres. But, because the divisions

between ‘real’ and ‘imaginary’ are constantly in a process of transition, nothing is

what it seems to be. This work infiltrates and directs our internal listening montage to

such an extent that we are constantly at sea perceptually.

The complexity, and subtlety, of Risset’s procedures warrants an extended

description of the opening minutes of the work, in which I use the terms ‘real’ and

‘imaginary’ in the sense described above5:

The movement opens with real wave sounds, filling the stereo field, underneath

which an harmonic grid is, very quietly, present. While the waves continue, and get

louder, real birdcalls build up distantly. A distinctive real birdcall is accompanied by

an equivocal peeping sound, probably imaginary, which is repeated several times,

alternating between channels. The waves subside imperceptibly as the birdcall texture

becomes louder. The texture has started to pan, fairly rapidly and continuously. The

rate of panning, and its regularity, is now too controlled for a natural spatial

environment.

About one minute into the movement, the previously real birdcall texture becomes

higher, more white-noise like and pans faster. A new, abrupt birdcall appears

repeatedly, with a breathy, pipe-like timbre. It appears to be real. As it accelerates in

tempo and occurrence, its imaginary status is revealed. Its progress occurs over

vestiges of the real birdcall texture, which exacerbates the confusion.

33
At around two minutes a croaking, almost frog-like pattern enters under the

birdcalls. It’s loud, reverberant and very clearly processed. It is hard to pinpoint

referentially, perhaps it is slowed-down birdsong, or insects. The croaks rise in an

obviously ‘un-natural’, fast glissando, the rhythmic pattern accelerates simultaneously.

As the pitch rises, the timbre changes until, at the extreme of the glissando, almost

imperceptible in pitch, the sound re-emerges as a ‘woody’ wind-chime clattering.

During this mutation the real birdcall texture has continued, similarly accelerating

and rising in amplitude, though not so much in pitch. By the arrival of the wind-chime

sounds the texture has become unnaturally frenetic and loud. The sound cuts off

abruptly at this point.

After a moment’s silence, a resonant synthetic pitch collection bursts in. There is

an abrupt change of context, with no real-world sounds. For an extended period the

texture is largely synthetic; sine waves, metallic sounds, transformed piano and bell-

like sounds. The rhythmic contours of some gestures are reminiscent of the preceding

birdcalls, now slower and suspended in an imaginary world. Synthetic clusters,

heavily-processed real-world sounds, sine-wave burblings and glissandi are obviously

shaped by the profile of the waves. Near the end of this passage a fairly loud, real,

seagull cry - a new sound - is suddenly introduced within the established imaginary

context.

This extended ‘wave’ of music is a real tour de force; within the large-scale move

from a real to an imaginary context, Risset creates a fluctuating and carefully paced

gradation which constantly evades our expectations and evaluation of all the sounds.

Our listening montage is never allowed to come to rest. Only when we reach his

34
resonant, harmonic clouds do we breathe a perceptual sigh of relief at finally reaching

something familiar; if the imaginary can be judged familiar. Yet, now that we’re safely

ensconced in this illusory world the subsequent, unannounced, seagull arrives with an

almost extra-terrestrial surprise.

So our constant reevaluation of real-world sounds engenders a shifting appraisal of

their meaning. We strive to make sense of our increasingly untrustworthy deductions

regarding sounds that, significantly, are rarely abstracted to the point of non-

recognition. The birdcalls, initially real, are distinctive enough to be attended to

closely. There are several clearly defined, different birdcalls. We are aware of their

being, as identifiable cries and as part of a natural environment. Mixing real and

imaginary birds creates a progressively uncomfortable perceptual confusion, a need to

re-perceive. What are we listening to ? Where (on earth ?) are we ? While bird, insect

and wave sounds are continually in the process of ‘be-coming’ transformed, so is our

appreciation of their being. As the wave reaches its peak the transformations of being

reach radical conclusions; when frogs become chimes a communicative cry has

become the byproduct of an action, implicitly the arbitrary action of the wind. Animate

being has become inanimate being.

Risset’s perceptual roller-coaster ride puts paid to any representational

expectations we might have had of the recorded environment. He isn’t in the market

for convincing us that what we hear is mimetically ‘realistic’ but neither is he

concerned to disrupt our connection to the real world. What we perceive and listen to

are resemblances, traces and transformations of the known. More importantly, what

this work is perhaps ultimately about is the way in which we forge some kind of

35
coherence from these perceptions within our internal listening montage.

Listening montage as rediscovery

This brings us back to the initial definition of montage as a purposeful ‘kit

designed to be assembled’ from apparently incongruous elements. As we resynthesize

our fractured listening processes we ‘rediscover’ the relationships between them and

we are required to make new listening deductions. The significance of this process of

discovery shouldn’t be underestimated. Our perceptual deductions are normally

ingrained and inflexible. Part of the success of real-world music lies in its ability to

shake us out of our established listening processes; deduction is, of course, a process of

perceptual subtraction, whereas real-world music seeks to add to our perception.

But what exactly is maintained as the result of our reassembled listening ? For one

thing, real-world music places us in a constant state of retrospective evaluation, both

during our listening to the work and afterwards, as we evaluate our musical listening

experience in relationship to our lives. To clarify this point, compare the experience to

the processes we undertake in completing a cryptic crossword puzzle :

As we make successive attempts to solve crossword clues we create a kind of

internal linguistic montage. In order to come up with the answers we engage in lateral

thinking, exploring all implications of the information. We start to think of words

differently; in terms of their sound, their content, their shape or etymology. We look

for unforseen or double meanings and we actively strive to expand our comprehension.

As when listening to a real-world work, we open ourselves to shifts of perception, to

re-perceptions, and on solving a clue we retrospectively trace how we ‘got’ its

meaning.

36
On finishing a crossword we are confronted with an unusual presentation of words,

out of their normal context. We appreciate connections of a more unorthodox kind;

connections of length, of internal structure, of visual pattern or spatial symmetry. Just

as the real-world work causes us to retrospectively re-evaluate the being of familiar

sounds, now we overlook a completed structure that presents these familiar words - for

a while at least - as strange and new.

But, more importantly, we have the satisfaction of regarding the completion of the

puzzle as partly down to us. Our minds created and perceived the answers. Unless we

feel particularly frustrated or peevish we choose to forget that, somewhere out there, a

crossword compiler already has them written down.

Although real-world music offers an infinitely more enriching listening ‘puzzle’,

we can likewise emerge from our listening montage feeling that we had a say in

creating the answers, even if the composer created the clues that directed our

perception. Yet it is the process of completing the puzzle, rather than the final result,

that has enlarged our understanding. And the listening deductions that we each make

in reassembling our listening montage are personal ‘solutions’. Just as the process of

solving crosswords is something we each undertake in individual, unforseeable ways,

so our listening understanding arises from an individual, creative activity.

Montage postulates intersubjective communication and the

transmission of meaning, but it refuses the literal character of representation

and the direct accessibility of its meaning. Just like the collage, montage is a

destruction of reality; but when collage, insisting on the heterogeneous

37
superficial character of the summoned-up fragments, plays the hand of

provocation (the rapture of rupture), montage is an inducement to rediscover

the network of signification that organizes them, to recover underneath the

deconstruction not a nihilistic chance, which only retains the absurd and the

accidental, but the uncanny that economizes significance.

(Thomas, 1985, p.85)

The essence of a real-world approach to composition lies in the invitation to

participatesubjectively in the creation and transmission of transfigured meanings, to

create through the confusion of our individual listening montage. Real-world music

prompts a creative state that, while also ‘destructing’ our normal perception of reality,

encourages us to discover it, in retrospect, anew. And this process of re-discovery is, I

believe, the aesthetic crux of the matter. Discoverers embark on journeys into the

unknown, leaving the safety of hearth and home in search of new knowledge and

experience. We, listening to a newly imagined reality, can travel away from both

listening, and experiential, assumptions.

Imaginative Journeys

As I write this it is Halloween or, in its original Celtic sense, the ‘Night of the

Dead’; the night in which we face our innermost fears regarding spirits, ghosts and

ghouls, through stories, bonfires and other assuaging rituals. And I’ve been listening to

ghost stories on the radio, each framed by the lugubrious tones of Vincent Price,

38
conjuring up a dark and forbidding environment for tales which are themselves of

darkness and dark things. When we want to be frightened, we turn down the lights and

scare each other with spooky stories, or we watch a horror film. Having been

transported imaginatively from our darkened reality, we return to it again, but now

there are movements in the shadows and strange beings in the flames. We have moved

from reality, to fantasy, and back again. And reality has changed, just as your reading

reality has changed as you remember that I have a life, and time, outside this text.

But, returning to the text, not all imaginative journeys are frightening, of course.

Risset’s Sud, even within the short excerpt discussed, makes a similar, wave-like,

movement which rises from the real to the imaginary and ebbs back to the known.

Like a wave, and like the ending of a story, there is that sense of return, of shaking

ourselves back into real life, picking up our coats and programmes and leaving for

home. Yet we retain the experience of a journey of some kind between departure and

re-arrival. Sud is perhaps unusual in that the journey is described within the work, but

all real-world music is concerned with similar travel A real-world work can be seen as

a move away from the reality, but through the reality, that frames our experience of the

music. And real-world works provide ‘open-ended’ musical worlds since they require

our continued remembrance of reality; of how things really are, or seem, or were, to us.

While not being realistic, real-world music leaves a door ajar on the reality in

which we are situated. I contend that real-world music is not concerned with realism,

and cannot be concerned with realism because it seeks, instead, to intitiate a journey

which takes us away from our preconceptions, so that we might arrive at a changed,

perhaps expanded, appreciation of reality.

The idea of real-world music as providing an imaginative experience which

39
proceeds through reality towards a more fantastic recognition brings us back to

Casey’s contrast between remembered and imagined content:

Remembered content is actual in status; it is something that we

assume has in fact appeared or occured on some previous occasion (even if we

cannot now recall the precise moment). Imagined content, in contrast, is purely

possible in status, it is something that, at most, might have appeared or

occurred previously or that might yet do so in the future.

(Casey, 1988, p.77)

For me, Casey’s distinction remains problematic, since my belief is that in real-

world music it is our recognition, i.e. our remembrance, of real events that invites an

imaginatively fruitful journey. We need to discover if there might be a useful

connection between our remembering of reality and our imaginative reinterpretation of

what it might mean. This necessitates exploring how and why listening to recorded

events within real-world music might invoke a different kind of recognition from the

norm, and it may elucidate the open-ended nature of the world offered by even the

most ‘fantastic’ real-world work.

A departure from realism

Realism relies on, even demands, our normal recognition. For instance, Bazin

regards the value of film realism as recording and then re-presenting6 a ‘slice’ of

reality, with the onus on the viewer to provide their own interpretation of events.

40
Bazin pictures the viewer of mimetic cinematography as

accepting that he or she is witnessing a slice of reality - the film viewer is said

to regard the image as the representation of some event or state of affairs from

the past. ... ...What Bazin sees as the glory of cinema - its purported capacity to

move viewers to accept that they are in the presence of the referent of the image

- ciné-Brechtians bewail as film’s disgrace.

(Carroll, 1988, pp. 94-5)

In Bazin’s view recorded material and reality are, in effect, -and affect - identical.

This idealistic model requires our perceptual response to film to be identical to our

relationship to real, unrecorded, life. But this means that we are restricted to our

normal perceptual activities; everything has to come from us, and any meaning we

might glean from our experience of - in this case - film realism will be bounded by

personal knowledge. Moreover, any imaginative activity we undertake is purely of our

own, unaided, volition. Ultimately, we embark on a journey with few shocks in store,

which can prove unsatisfying if we are seeking involvement of a more enlarging kind:

When Flaherty sees a woman walking along the shore with a

casket of seaweed on her back, it is for him exciting and dramatic, because he

knows by experience the struggle for existence that that load represents. But

when the audience see the same picture, they see only the woman and the

seaweed. Man of Aran is a sealed document, the key to which is still in

Flaherty’s own mind. (from a contemporary newspaper review in the Observer)

41
But more often realism, in both documentary and fiction film, is compromised by

the inclusion of dramatic events that will engender in us an apparently natural

‘trauma’. In reality, Flaherty compromised himself in an attempt to capture his

audience dramatically: Man of Aran (1934) used actors, contained a dramatic whale-

hunt and a storm sequence - both of which were ‘staged’ - and, subsequent to its

completion as a silent film, an added soundtrack using Gaelic dialogue. In this respect

it could perhaps be viewed as one of the first ‘docu-dramas’. In their search for

‘hyper-realism’ docu-dramas impose narratives on reality while soap-operas - fictional

‘real life dramas’- are littered with car-accidents, terminal illnesses, love affairs and

other ‘natural’ conflicts. Yet none of these dramatic excursions ask for a departure

from rationally grounded habits. Rather than inviting us towards a more fantastic,

imaginative understanding of reality, they confirm what we already know:

photographic and cinematographic processes can accomplish

better, faster, and with a circulation a hundred thousand times larger than

narrative or pictorial realism, the task which academicism had assigned to

realism: to preserve various consciousnesses from doubt.

(Lyotard, 1984, p.75)

But although reality is its starting point, real-world music doesn’t seek to preserve

normal consciousness of the real from doubt. We aren’t required to respond to the

music as a Bazinian re-presentation of reality. But none of the works I have discussed

uses musical drama to ‘spice up’ the action - there are no sonata forms or symphonies

here - neither do they present overtly programmatic ‘plots’. Indeed, Risset - taking

42
the continuous, repetitive ebb and flow of a wave as his structural model - is almost

perverse in his avoidance of confrontation. The absence of ‘dramatic realism’ in real-

world music indicates that while it ‘fails’ to provide a ‘realistic’ world, rather than

leave reality it leaves realism behind.

Emotional recognition

Ferrari’s Presque Rien avec filles, like montage film, re-orders reality according to

the composer’s internal, subjective viewpoint. What we recognize is not a realistic and

objective representation of reality, but an individual’s emotionally coloured

interpretation of recorded events. In this respect Ferrari, himself a film-maker, has

much in common with directors such as Vertov and Eisenstein, who were scathing in

their disregard of film realism as an imitative re-presentation of reality - ‘Imitation is

the sincerest form of flattery. Not a film, but a filing cabinet’ (Vertov, p. 264) and

polemical in their advocation of subjectively interpreted reality:

Not dispassionate information, but the music of science. The

poetry of reality. An emotional approach to the cognitive and a cognitive

interest in the emotional. Research that uses the methods of the artist rather

than just purely scientific methods.

(Vertov, p.233)

Vertov’s proclamations ask for a recognition that is essentially emotional.

Similarly, though we may recognize a close friend through their voice, their

appearance or their manner, our ‘intelligent’ recognition of them as a friend employs

43
an emotionally educated knowledge, to which our intellectually governed perceptions

contribute peripherally. In comparison, although we might imaginatively understand

the sounds of real-world music through a complex listening montage, our recognition

of the music’s meaning - for us, personally - is both part of, and more, than this. If

real-world music seems to offer an ‘open-ended’ world that both connects us to reality

and transfigures our understanding of it, this may be because our remembrance of

reality is evoked through an unusually emotional response.

From this standpoint there might be more freedom to engage in imaginative flights

of fancy, without abandoning a recognition of the real. Many imaginative journeys

maintain the appearance of a connection to the known; by convincing us that the world

we are entering has some relation to reality, fantasies can encourage us to believe the

increasingly irrational intelligence of an imagined world. ‘Once upon a time’ gives us

access to a fairy-tale fabrication but also implies that, once, this remembered time was

real. And fairy-tale characters often live in real or pseudo-real countries, have

realistically described homes, and do real things - drink, eat, sleep - even if the homes

are golden palaces, the food and drink is ultimately enchanted or the sleep may be for a

hundred years. The irrational is still tenuously connected to reality and, for many

children, Red Riding Hood seems real enough to be perhaps inadvisable as a bedtime

story. And though we might regard our adult selves as more sophisticated, we are just

as prone to the emotional pull of an apparently irrational recognition.

However, real-world music differs, of course, from fairy-tale worlds in that its

source material is essentially documentary and immediately connected to real life.

Like a documentary film, or a journalistic report, it carries the ‘authority’ of apparent

truth. But this doesn’t exclude emotional recognition - in fact it may accentuate its

44
effect.

The fabulist need only convince on the basis of the internal

cohesion of his purely imaginary works. He says, All this could never happen,

so do not blame me if it does not seem real. The new journalist, on the other

hand, need only convince on the basis of verifiable sources and his personal

integrity: All this actually did happen, so do not blame me if it does not seem

real. (Hellman, 1981, p.11)

The new journalist, in presenting his personal interpretation of ‘verifiable sources’

has perhaps more emotional latitude than the fabulist because the ‘contract’ he makes

with his reader assumes a connection to reality, however irrational or fantastic its

presentation may seem.7 We don’t dismiss the ‘authority’ of his tale lightly, and

perhaps this aids a willingness to place more ‘weight’ than usual on our emotional

response. Similarly, in advocating that films ‘must be highly emotional narratives and

not merely logical exposés of facts’(Eisenstein, 1970, p.62) Eisenstein implies that an

emotional recognition can be powerful when the material, and subject, is documentary

in nature. A ‘highly emotional narrative’ doesn’t require that we lose our hold on the

facts, rather it encourages our recognition of them to be ‘coloured’ by emotions.

Perhaps an appreciation of real things can be changed or filtered precisely because

recognition involves both emotional and intellectual responses, and we may be

directed towards one response, without entirely abandoning the other.

Partial representation

45
Through an appeal to emotional recognition, then, we may be distracted from our

normal perceptions. We are discouraged from travelling along habitual routes that now

appear to be changed or ‘repressed’ in some manner.

The author sees with his mind’s eye some image, an emotional

embodiment of his theme. His task is to reduce that image to two or three

partial representations whose combination or juxtaposition shall evoke in the

consciousness and feelings of the spectator the same generalized initial image

which haunted the author’s imagination.

(Eisenstein, 1970, pp. 76-7)

For Eisenstein ‘partial representation’ provided the means to the imaginative

‘liberation’ of emotional recognition. And his chief means of obtaining it was through

film montage, which he regarded as an essentially emotional molding of images in

time. By cutting up film he also ‘cut up’, and thereby obscured, the normal flow of

events to create a new structure of relationships, carefully selected for their evocative

power.

In his film October8, for instance, he conveyed the emotionally charged sense of

‘waiting’ that preceded the storming of the Winter Palace through a disjointed

succession of fleeting images. The film cuts continually from shots which include a

stationary warship by a bridge, a pair of soldiers huddled in anticipation of a message

and the opposing women soldiers nervously walking the battlements. The same images

return repeatedly and, each time, nothing has changed. As an almost superfluous

confirmation, the word ‘waiting’ briefly appears on the screen. An emotional

46
recognition is almost inevitable with such evocative images whose temporally

obscured representations transmit far more than the sum of their individual parts.

In similarly eschewing ‘realism’ or ‘plot’ it seems no accident that real-world

music frequently uses signal processing in a manner which, literally, obscures the

recorded source. The techniques may be - if the composer so chooses - directly

analogous to this intention to ‘partially represent’ a theme. While musique concrète

frequently uses digital filtering or synthesis, for instance, to destroy all referential

information, real-world music may use these same techniques - as in Lansky’s filtered

speech pieces, or Risset’s cross-synthesized birds - to retain particular, evocative

aspects of a source. This music speaks of - and through - the composer’s internalized

vision of reality - an emotional response that cannot be communicated through realism

alone. Instead, it presents fragmentary or restructured images that, while retaining

allusions to their real-world ‘being’, are decontextualised from the normal course of

events; and each are more concerned with experience than fact.

Real-world music, perhaps, has a slight edge on film here since - in less time than

it takes to sing a g-sharp - reality can be transformed through musical abstraction.

Partial representations are abetted by the fact that, in addition to the vagaries of

obscured recorded images, we may contend with the emotional ‘disruption’ of overtly

musical contours. This is particularly apparent in Lansky’s Quakerbridge, a work

where quasi-tonal harmony becomes the means, to quote the composer, to ‘find the

music of the experience of.. ..nostalgia’ or, rather, escape the ‘restrictions’ of realism

in recorded shopping mall sounds. And he, like Eisenstein, speaks in terms of

47
emotional rather than intellectual engagement in referring to nostalgia, an image of

personal experience conceived within his own ‘mind’s eye’. Lansky’s intention is to

lead us away from realism towards a musical appreciation; he places us in a ‘musical’

chair - we listen to the sounds of the mall through our musical ears because his

interaction with the material ‘sits us down’ to listen this way. It seems that music,

more than film, can give us ‘another room’ from which to watch the world go by.

Wthout in any way seeking to control our emotions the composer invites us to use

them to find, in Vertov’s deceptively flamboyant phrase, our own ‘poetry of reality’.

And an evocative, irrational journey, one which takes fantastic flight from normal

understanding, depends on a poetic sensibility that, far from being dramatic, arouses a

subtle evolution of illusions, allusions and other departures from the known.

Poetic Metaphors

We could say that a stable and completely realized image clips

the wings of the imagination.... ...But real mobility, the very essence of motion,

which is what imagined motion is, is not aroused by the description of reality,

even when it describes the unfolding of reality. ... ...What I would actually like

to examine... ...is how the imaginary is immanent in the real, how a continuous

path leads from the real to the imaginary.

(Bachelard, 1988, p.4)

If reality obscured - through mythologizing, through montage, through digital

48
filtering - accesses a peculiarly emotional recognition, Bachelard gives some

indication of the poetic value of this exercise. In exploring that ‘continuous path’ from

the real to the imaginary, through the poetics of real-world music rather than poetry

per se, we might discover that real-world music also encourages an individual,

imaginative discovery of what is immanent in reality. And this is why it holds fast to

its connection to the real.

My work, people underground fails - intentionally - as an essay in either dramatic

‘realism’or abstract sonic art. Because it is about being underground in its

metaphorical, as much as its physical, sense, it might be regarded as an attempt to

document metaphysical relationships which transcend the reality of our normal

perceptions. The sounds of people walking in foot-tunnels, and interacting

spontaneously with these unusual surroundings, are used as the starting point for an

imaginative, inner journey, one weighted towards emotional rather than intellectual

perception. Although framed by a simple ‘narrative’- a descent from above ground, a

journey underground and re-arrival at the surface - this musical underground journey

descends beyond reality, and beyond temporal narrative. It strives to take us away

from a simple apprehension of real things towards a complex apprehension of their

associative meanings. It also seeks to remind us of the un-reality available in real life :

we are captivated by tunnels; the changes in our environment are magic, we play with

the echoes, stamp our feet and shout as we, temporarily, enter a strange, new world.

And magic, of course, causes us to reevalute reality because what seemed to be real,

suddenly isn’t.

Like a deceptive magical illusion, people underground tries to create an experience

which almost could have happened this way, but then again, you never know. You

49
never know because the real-world sounds are processed and rearranged in a

surreptitious manner. This places us in a suitably insecure and wary state of mind,

despite which ‘fantastic’ events sneak up on us unawares, sometimes infiltrating our

reality without us even noticing. And because the work doesn’t sit us down safely in

either - to expand Lansky’s metaphor - a ‘real’ or ‘imaginary’ chair we don’t quite

know what kind of ground, or underground, we are going to land on.

For instance, shortly after an opening rhythmic ‘descent’, composed of sharp

attacks and fragments of speech, we arrive in a strange place. This, however, is

unprocessed and ‘real’: the sounds of two people walking, and talking intermittently,

underground. The regular rhythm of the footsteps is interrupted occasionally by

sudden ‘thuds’, which reverberate in the resonant environment. As we would expect,

their pitch is always the same, since - as in Lucier’s I am sitting in a room - the fixed

space provides the ‘filter’ which tunes them. This section could be, and in fact was, a

straightforward recording of real events, but its strangeness already engenders some

doubt. As the walkers proceed these thuds are tapped out in a clear rhythmic pattern

which is then promptly ‘answered’ by a loud collection of random attacks, layered and

occuring at a variety of pitches. The environment appears to have responded wilfully

to the human interaction. Reality fails and fantasy, momentarily, prevails.

In spite of the fact that overtly ‘musical’ parameters are underplayed, it is through

these parameters that I tried to extend our ‘underground’ associations metaphorically.

As already indicated, pitch is used to infiltrate reality. Towards the centre of this work,

where the established underground environment descends even further from reality,

pitch and rhythm are used to extend our imaginative journey:

A passage using the sounds of a crowd of people passing through the tunnel

50
gradually subsides and is replaced by distant fragments of speech interspersed with the

thudding sounds and the disruptive crash created by lift-doors. Solitary footsteps

return and continue in the foreground. This section is suddenly much quieter, events

happen infrequently and the sounds of the lifts, thuds and distant vocal fragments

occur in alternation, separated - for the first time - by moments of silence. Since the

resonance of the tunnel has defined our context, now we are nowhere. All these sounds

descend in pitch at each repetition, and the thuds are neither single events nor chaotic

collections but descending pairs, almost cadential in rhythm and pitch. Gradually all

sounds of human origin disappear and we are left with unidentifiable thuds and

crashes. Pitch and rhythm provide a musical trajectory; one which, though clearly

descending, provides no clues as to its point of arrival. We perch, tentatively, on a

‘musical’ chair. I tried to convey the sense that this downward journey could perhaps

go on for ever; we are abandoned underground and left alone to contemplate our

individual doubts - musical and otherwise - in gradually encroaching silence.

Our isolation is then relieved by the sound of a crowd of people, entering from

silence and gradually rising in amplitude and density. Thuds and crashes disappear and

humanity enthusiastically reasserts itself. Listening, we return to the inhabited world of

the real life tunnel, and the journey continues. And in a work whose only decisive

trajectory is that discovered by our listening minds in response to metaphorical

suggestions, both musical processes and realism are partial representations that we

meet along the way.

of all metaphors, metaphors of height, elevation, depth, sinking,

and the fall are the axiomatic metaphors par excellence. Nothing explains them,

51
and they explain everything. Put more simply, if a person is willing to live

them, feel them, and above all compare them, he realizes that they have an

essential quality and that they are more natural than all the others. ... ... And yet

language is not particularly well-suited to them. Language, conditioned by

forms, is not readily capable of making the dynamic images of height

picturesque.

(Bachelard, 1988, p.10)

Bachelard leads us from those powerful, elemental metaphors that all art strives to

let us to feel - to live - towards language’s struggle to express those things that words

can’t express, and that is the sublime frustration of true poetry:

Words strain,

Crack and sometimes break, under the burden,

Under the tension, slip, slide, perish,

Decay with imprecision, will not stay in place,

Will not stay still.

(T. S. Eliot, “Burnt Norton”)

Poetry takes words out of their usual context and seeks to defeat the power of

language, the rational ‘conditioning of forms’ that gives words their ‘normal’ sense.

And real-world music, similarly, takes real events out of their usual context, defeating

our rational balance of recognition; but it also takes musical processes out of their,

52
wholly imaginary, world where they normally struggle in abstraction with those same

‘axiomatic’ poetic metaphors that Bachelard describes. But in this world they find

expression in melodies, modulations, gestures, timbres or chords. Now these

metaphors are turned to poetic ends in that music enlightens the ‘continuous path’

from the real to the imaginary. In this manner pieces such as Sud, The Lesson and, I

hope, my own work imbue musical procedures with an additional poetic worth; they

give us a new, ‘de-conditioned’, recognition of chords, pitches, or amplitude curves.

Now there is a tension; between what we customarily ‘expect’ of words, sounds or

musical processes and the new ends to which they’re turned. We lose our

preconceptions of both music and reality - they make no sense.

When preconceptions desert us, we’re left with fantasy - the free play of our

creative imagination. And this, for Bachelard, is the dynamic, individual, condition

that poetry ideally invokes. I share Bachelard’s preoccupation with fantasy as an

internal state of affairs and believe that real-world music, like poetry, is impelled by a

desire to invoke our internal ‘flight’ of imagination so that, through an imaginative

listening to what is ‘immanent in the real’, we might discover what is immanent in us.

Notes

1. McLuhan, ‘Since the telephone offers a very poor auditory image, we strengthen

and complete it by the use of all the other senses.’ (McLuhan, 1964, p.235)

2. The inscription on the Winchester Cathedral bell is “Horas volantes numero,

mortuos plango: vivos ad preces voco” (“I enumerate the fleeing hours, I mourn the

53
dead, I call the living to prayer”) Both the inscription - sung by a boy soprano - and

the sound of the bell itself are used as material in Harvey’s Mortous plango.

3. Not to be confused with Eisenstein’s specific use of this term to describe the

relationship between sound and image in film.

4. Throughout this discussion the word ‘intent’ draws its meaning purely from its

etymological root, as a ‘stretching out’ towards some thing or purpose. So, in the case

of composer-intended listening the ‘stretching out’ is initiated by the composer,

although -- in more common parlance - we can certainly sit down to Beethoven’s 5th

emotionally intending, or not intending, to listen.

5. Risset provides the following guide to the first movement (of three), my description

proceeds from the opening to include the ‘harmonic clouds’:

The sea in the morning. The opening profile permeates the entire piece.

Waking birds: isolated peeps rising to a stretto.

Harmonic clouds.

Hybrid sounds emerge from the low frequencies.

Heat. Luminy, at the foot of mount Puget: real and imaginary insects and

birds

(Risset, liner notes to Sud)

6. Bazin’s notion of representation in film is narrowly defined, as Nöel Carroll

remarks: ‘Bazin argued that the truly cinematic film stays as close to recording as

possible, eschewing the interpretation, recreation, or reconstitution of reality.’

(Carroll,1988, p.96) For Bazin the film was, literally and (ideally) exclusively the re-

54
‘presentation’ of reality.

7. New Journalism is a term often used for reportage or ‘fictionalized’ fact, in which an

account of actual events is molded into an imaginative, even fantastic, work by the

author. Norman Mailer and Truman Capote are classic examples of this type of writer.

The category might be expanded to include the, increasingly prevalent trait of imbuing

fiction with factual events, or vice versa, in what is sometimes termed the ‘post

modern’ novel. As examples, D.M.Thomas’ Flying in to Love is an investigation of

John F. Kennedy’s assassination that soon becomes a reflection on dreams and

collective memory; Martin Amis’ Money is one of many recent novels where the

novelist himself appears as a character in the plot. These kind of strategies rely on our

willingness to integrate fantasy within a scenario that appears to be ‘authoritative’

through its use of real incidents and characters.

8. 1927, dir. Sergei Eisenstein and Brigory Alexandrov.

References

Bachelard, G. (1988) Air and Dreams trans. Edith R. Farrell and C. Frederick Farrell,

Dallas: The Dallas Institute Publications

Bazin, A. (1967) What is Cinema ? volume 1 trans. Hugh Gray, Berkeley: University

of California Press

Campbell, P. (1986) The music of digital computers. Nature(December issue)

Carroll, N. (1988) Philosophical Problems of Classical Film Theory, Princeton:

Princeton University Press

Casey, E. S. (1987) Remembering. A Phenomenological Study, Bloomington: Indiana

55
University Press

Collins, N. liner notes to Alvin Lucier I am sitting in a Room, Lovely Music LCD

1013 1990

Cott, J. (1973) Stockhausen. Conversations with the Composer, New York: Simon and

Schuster

Eisenstein, S. (1970) Notes of a Film Director, New York: Dover

______________ (1986) The Film Sense, trans. Jay Leyda, London: Faber and Faber

(first published 1958)

Eliot, T.S.. (1959) Burnt Norton. Four Quartets, London: Faber and Faber (first

published 1944)

Gleick, J. (1987) Chaos, London: Sphere (Macmillan)

Harvey, J. (1985) Electronics in Music: A New Aesthetic ? Composer (Summer issue)

Hellmann, J. (1981) Fables of Fact. The New Journalism as New Fiction, Urbana:

University of Illinois Press

Jung, C. (1964) Approaching the Unconscious. Man and his Symbols (ed. Carl Jung),

New York: Doubleday

Lehmann, J. F. (1972) Lewis Carroll and the Spirit of Nonsense, Nottingham:

University of Nottingham

Lyotard, J. (1984) Answering the Question: What is Postmodernism ? trans. R gis

Durand. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans. Bennington and

Massumi, Manchester: Manchester University Press

Maclean, M. (1988) Narrative as performance: the Baudelairean experiment,

London: Metheun

McLuhan, M. (1964) Understanding Media, New York: Signet Books

56
Nietzsche, F. (1977) extract from Human, all too Human in A Nietzsche Reader.

London: Penguin Classics

Russolo, L. (1986) The Art of Noises, trans. Barclay Brown, New York: Pendragon

Press

Thomas, J. (1983) Collage/Space/Montage. Collage, general ed. Jeanine Parisier

Plottel, New York : New York Literary Forum

Vertov, D. (1984) KINO-EYE: The Writings of Dziga Vertov, edited with an

introduction by Annette Michelson; trans. by Kevin O’Brien, Berkeley: University of

California Press

Discography

Ferrari, L. (1989) Presque Rien avec filles INA/GRM BFHAAST CD 9009

__________ (1963/4) Hétérozygote INA/GRM BFHAAST CD 9009

Harvey, J.(1986) Mortuos Plango Vivos Voco Erato STU 71544

Lansky, P. (1990/1) Night Traffic Bridge BCD 9035

___________ (1989) The Lesson Bridge BCD 9050

Lucier, A. (1969) I am sitting in a Room Lovely Music LCD 1013 1

Norman, K. (1991) people underground (forthcoming on NMC label)

Risset, J.C. (1985) Sud INA/GRM C 1003

Stockhausen, K. (1976) Trans DG 2530 726

57

View publication stats

You might also like