Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Chaosmosis: An Ethico-Aesthetic Paradigm

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 50

Chaosmosis

an ethico-aesthetic paradigm

Felix Guattari

translated by

Paul Bains and Julian Pefanis

INDIANA UNIVERSITY PRESS BLOOMINGTON & INDIANAPOLIS

English translation© 1995, Power Institute, Paul Bains, and Julian Pefanis

Chaosmosis was originally published in French as Chaosmose. © 1992, Editions Galilee

All rights reserved

No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by any information storage
and retrieval system,

without permission in writing from the publisher. The Association of American University Presses' Resolutions on Permissions constitutes the only exception to this prohibition.
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum

requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences-Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39 .48-1984.

Manufactured in the United States of America

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Guattari, Felix.
[Chaosmose. English] Chaosmosis : an ethico-aesthetic paradigm I Felix Guattari ; translated by Paul Bains and Julian Pefanis.
p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0-253-32945-0 (alk. paper). - ISBN 0-253-21004-6 (pbk. : alk. paper)
1. Psychoanalysis-Philosophy. 2. Subjectivity. I. Title. BFl 75.G81313 1995' 95-31403 194-dc20

1 2 3 4 5 00 99 98 97 96 95

On the planking, on the ship's bulwarks, on the

sea, with the course of the sun through the sky

and the ship, an unreadable and wrenching

script takes shape, takes shape and destroys

itself at the same slow pace - shadows, spines,

shafts of broken light refocused in the angles,

the triangles of a fleeting geometry that yields

to the shadow of the ocean waves. And then,

unceasingly, lives again.

Marguerite Duras

The North China Lover

Contents

1 On the production of subjectivity 1

2 Machinic heterogenesis 33

3 Schizoanalytic metamodelisation 58

4 Schizo chaosmosis 77
5 Machinic orality and virtual ecology 88

6 The new aesthetic paradigm 98

7 The ecosophic object 119

1 On the production of subjectivity

My professional activities in the field of psychotherapy, like my

political and cultural engagements, have led me increasingly to

put the emphasis on subjectivity as the product of individuals, groups and institutions.

Considering subjectivity from the point of view ofits produc

tion does not imply any return to traditional systems of binary

determination - material infrastructure/ideological super

structure. The various semiotic registers that combine to

engender subjectivity do not maintain obligatory hierarchical

relations fixed for all time. Sometimes, for example, economic

semiotisation becomes dependent on collective psychological factors -look at the sensitivity of the stock exchange to fluctu- _..,/

ations of opinion. Subjectivity is in fact plural and polyphonic - to use Mikhail Bakhtin's expression. It recognises no domi

nant or determinant instance guiding all other forms according to a univocal causality.

At least three types of problem prompt us to enlarge the def

inition of subjectivity beyond the classical opposition between individual subject and society, and in so doing, revise the mod- t: els of the unconscious
currently in circulation: ,the irruption of \
2 Chaosmosis

subjective factors at the forefront of current events, the massive

· development of machinic productions of subjectivity and, final

ly, the recent prominence of ethological and ecological perspec

tives on human subjectivity.

Subjective factors have always held an important place in


the course of history. But it seems that with the global diffusion

of the mass media they are beginning to play a dominant role.

We will only give a few brief examples here. The immense

movement unleashed by the Chinese students at Tiananmen

Square obviously had as its goal the slogans of political democ

ratisation. But it is equally certain that the contagious affective

charges it bore far surpassed simple ideological demands. A whole lifestyle, collective ethic and conception of social rela

tions (derived largely from Western images) were set into motion. And in the long run tanks won't be able to stop itl As in

Hungary or Poland, collective existential mutation will have

the last word! All the same, large movements of subjectivation

don't necessarily develop in the direction of emancipation. The

massive subjective revolution which has been developing

among the Iranian people for more than ten years is focused on

religious archaisms and generally conservative social attitudes

- particularly with regard to the position of women (this is a

sensitive issue in France, because of the events in the Maghreb and the repercussions of these repressive attitudes to women in

the area of immigration).

In the Eastern bloc, the fall of the Iron Curtain didn't hap

pen as the result of armed insurrection but through the crys

tallisation of an immense <.Q!lec1i\Te desire annihilating the

mental substrate of the post-Stalin totalitarian system. This is a

phenomenon of extreme complexity, since it intermingles

emancipatory aspirations with retrogressive, conservative - even fascist - drives of a nationalistic, ethnic and religious

nature. In this upheaval, how will the populations of central


On the production of subjectivity 3

Europe and the Eastern bloc overcome the bitter deception the

capitalist West has reserved for them until now? History will

tell us - admittedly a History full of unpleasant surprises but,

why not - about a subsequent renewal of social struggles! By

contrast, how murderous the Gulf War will have been! One

could almost speak of genocide, since this war led to the exter

mination of many more Iraqis (counting all ethnic groups)

than there were victims of the bombs dropped at Hiroshima and Nagasaki in 1945. With the passage of time it seems clear

that what was at stake was an attempt to bring the Arab popu

lations to heel and reclaim world opinion: it had to be demon

strated that the Yankee way ofsubjectivation could be imposed

by the combined power of the media and arms.

Generally, one can say that contemporary history is increas -� ingly dominated by rising demands for subjective singularity !1 quarrels
- over
language, autonomist d;�;,-�sues of �ation-'.i :I alism and of the nation, which, in total ambiguity, express on·

the one hand an aspiration for national liberation, but also

manifest themselves in what I would call conservative reterri- •·

t9riallsations of subjectivity. A certain universal representation._

of subjectivity, incarnated by capitalist colonialism in both East

and West, has gone bankrupt - although it's not yet possible ..

to fully measure the scale of such a failure. Today, as everyone

knows, the growth of nationalism and fundamentalism in Arab ,

and Muslim countries may have incalculable consequences not

only on international relations, but on the subjective

economies of hundreds of millions of individuals. It's the whole

problematic of disarray as well as the mounting demands of the

Third World, the countries of the South, which are thus

stamped with an agonising question mark.

As things stand, sociology, economic science, political sci ence and legal studies appear poorly equipped to account for
4 Chaosmosis

this mixture of archaic attachments to cultural traditions that

nonetheless aspire to the technological and scientific modernity

characterising the contemporary subjective cocktail.

Traditional psychoanalysis, for its part, is hardly better placed

to confront these problems, due to its habit of reducing social

facts to psychological mechanisms. In such conditions it

appears opportune to forge a more transversalist conception of

subjectivity, one which would permit us to understand both its

idiosyncratic territorialised couplings (Existential Territories)

and its opening onto value systems (Incorporeal Universes)

with their social and cultural implications.

Should we keep the semiotic productions of the mass media,

informatics, telematics and robotics separate from psychological

subjectivity? I don't think so. Just as social machines can be

grouped under the general title of Collective Equipment, techno

logical machines of information and communication operate at

the heart of human subjectivity, not only within its memory and

intelligence, but within its sensibility, affects and unconscious

fantasms. Recognition of these machinic dimensions of subjecti

vation leads us to insist, in our attempt at redefinition, on the

heterogeneity of the components leading to the production of subjectivity. Thus one finds in it: 1. Signifying semiological com

ponents which appear in the family, education, the environ ment, religion, art, sport . .. 2. Elements constructed by the media industry, the cinema,
etc., 3. A-signifying semiological
dimensions that trigger informational sign machines, and that function in parallel or independently of the fact that they pro

duce and convey significations and denotations, and thus

escape from strictly linguistic axiomatics. The different currents

of structuralism have given neither autonomy nor specificity to

this a-signifying regime, although authors like Julia Kristeva or

Jacques Derrida have shed some light on the relative autonomy

of this sort of component. But in general. the a-signifying econo-


On the production of subjectivity 5

my of language has been reduced to what I call sign machines,

to the linguistic, significational economy of language. This ten dency is particularly clear with Roland Barthes who equates the

elements of language and narrative segments with figures of

Expression, and thus confers on linguistic semiology a primacy

over all other semiotics. It was a grave error on the part of the

structuralist school to try to put everything connected with the

psyche under the control of the linguistic signifier!

Te�hnological transformationa oblige us to be aware of both

qniversalising and reductionist homogenisations of subjectivity and of a heterogenetic tendency, that is to say, of a reinforce

ment of the heterogeneity and singularisation of its compo

nents. Thus "computer-aided design" leads to the production of

images opening on to unprecedented plastic Universes - I am

thinking, for example, of Matta's work with the graphic palette

- or to the solution of mathematical problems which would

have been quite unimaginable a few years ago. But then again,

we should be on guard against progressivist illusions or visions

which are systematically pessimistic. The machinic production

of subjectivity can work for the better or for the worse. There

exists an anti-modernist attitude which involves a massive

rejection of technological innovation, particularly as it concerns

the information revolution. It's impossible to judge such a

machinic evolution either positively or negatively; everything

depends on its articulation within collective assemblages of

enunciation. At best there is the creation, or invention, of new

Universes ofreference; at the worst there is the deadening influ

ence of the mass media to which millions of individuals are cur

rently condemned. Technological developments together with social experimentation in these new domains are perhaps capa

ble of leading us out of the current period of oppression and into a post-media era characterised by the reappropriation and resin

gularisation of the use of media. (Access to data-banks, video


6 Chaosmosis

libraries, interactivity between participants, etc.)


The same movement towards a polyphonic and heterogenetic

comprehension of subjectivity leads us to consider certain aspects of contemporary research into ethology and ecology. Daniel Stern, in The
Interpersonal World of the Infant, 1 has
notably explored the pre-verbal subjective formations of

infants. He shows that these are not at all a matter of "stages" in the Freudian sense, but of levels of subjectivation which

maintain themselves in parallel throughout life. He thus rejects

the overrated psychogenesis of Freudian complexes, which have been presented as the structural "Universals" of subjectiv

ity. Furthermore, he emphasises the inherently trans-subjec

tive character of an infant's early experiences, which do not

dissociate the feeling of self from the feeling of the other. A

dialectic between "sharable affects" and "non-sharable affects"

thus structures the emergent phases of subjectivity. A nascent subjectivity, which we will continually find in dreams, delire, creative exaltation,
or the feeling oflove ...

Social ecology and mental ecology have found privileged sites of exploration in the experiences of institutional psy

chotherapy. I am obviously thinking of the clinic at La Borde,

where I have worked for a long time; everything there is set up

so that psychotic patients live in a climate of activity and

assume responsibility, not only with the goal of developing an

ambience of communication, but also in order to create local

centres for collective subjectivation. Thus it's not simply a mat ter ofremodelling a patient's subjectivity - as it existed before a psychotic crisis - but
of a production sui generis. For exam ple, certain psychotic patients, coming from poor agricultural

backgrounds, will be invited to take up plastic arts, drama,

video, music, etc., whereas until then, these universes had been

unknown to them. On the other hand, bureaucrats and intel-


On the production of subjectivity 7

lectuals will find themselves attracted to material work, in the

kitchen, garden, pottery, horse riding club. The important

thing here is not only the confrontation with a new material of

expression, but the constitution of ��lllJ?l�,xespf s.ubjectivatic;m: multiple exchanges between igdividual-group-machine. These

complexes actually offer people diverse possibilities for recom

posing their existential corporeality, to get out of their repeti- . tive impasses and, in a certain way, to resingularise them-
'

selves. Grafts of transference 0perate in this way, not issuing

from ready-made dimensions of subjectivity crystallised into

structural complexes, but from a creation which itself indicates

a kind of aesthetic paradigm. One creates new modalities of

subjectivity in the same way that an artist creates new forms

from the palette. In such a context, the most heterogeneous components may work towards a patient's positive evolution:

relations with architectural space; economic relations; the co

management by patient and carer of the different vectors of

treatment; taking advantage of all occasions opening onto the


outside world; a processual exploitation of event-centred "sin

gularities" - everything which can contribute to the creation

of an authentic relation with the other. To each of these com

ponents of the caring institution there corresponds a necessary

practice. We are not confronted with a subjectivity given as in

itself, but with processes of the realisation of autonomy, or of autopoiesis (in a somewhat different sense from the one

Francisco Varela gives this term2).

Let us now examine an example of the use of the psyche's etho

logical and ecological resources in the domain of family psy chotherapy. We are borrowing this example from a movement

which, around Mony Elkaim, is attempting to free itself from

the grip of systemic theories that circulate in Anglo-Saxon

countries and in Italy. 3 Here also the inventiveness of treat-


8 Chaosmosis

ment distances us from scientific paradigms and brings us clos

er to an ethico-aesthetic paradigm. Therapists get involved,

take risks and put their own fantasms into operation, creating a

paradoxical climate of existential authenticity accompanied by

a playful freedom and simulacra. Family therapy produces sub jectivity in the most artificial way imaginable. This can be

observed during training sessions, when the therapists impro

vise psychodramatic scenes. Here, the scene implies a layering

of enunciation: a vision of oneself as concrete embodiment; a

subject of enunciation which doubles the subject of the state

ment and the distribution of roles; a collective management of

the game; an interlocution with observers commenting on the scene; and finally, video which through feedback restores the

totality of these superposed levels. This type of performance

favours the relinquishment of a "realist" attitude which would

apprehend the lived scenes as actually embodied in family

structures. This multi-faceted theatrical aspect allows us to

grasp the artificial and creative character of the production of

subjectivity. It should be emphasised that the video is always

within sight of the therapists. Even when the camera is

switched off, they develop the habit of observing certain semi

otic manifestations which would escape normal observation.

The ludic face-to-face encounter with patients and the accep

tance of singularities developed in this sort of therapy distin

guishes it from the attitude of the traditional psychoanalyst

with an averted gaze, and even from classical psychodrama.

Whether one considers contemporary history, machinic semi


otic productions, the ethology of infancy, or social and mental

ecology, we witness the same questioning of subjective individ uation, which certainly survives, but is wrought by collective

assemblages of enunciation. At this stage, the provisional defin ition of subjectivity I would like to propose as the most encom-
On the production of subjectivity 9

passing would be: "The ensemble of conditions which render

possible the emergence of individual and/ or collective instances

as self-referential existential Territories, adjacent, or in a delim

iting relation, to an alterity that is itself subjective." We know

that in certain social and semiological contexts, subjectivity

becomes individualised; persons, taken as responsible for them

selves, situate themselves within relations of alterity governed

by familial habits, local customs, juridical laws, etc. In other

conditions, subjectivity is colledive - which does not, howev

er, mean that it becomes exclusively social. The term "collec

tive" should be understood in the sense of a multiplicity that

deploys itself as much beyond the individual, on the side of the

socius, as before the person, on the side of preverbal intensities,

indicating a logic of affects rather than a logic of delimited sets.

The conditions of production sketched out in this redefini

tion thus together imply: human inter-subjective instances

manifested by language; suggestive and identificatory exam

ples from ethology; institutional interactions of different

natures; machinic apparatuses (for example, those involving

computer technology); incorporeal Universes of reference such

as those relative to music and the plastic arts. This non-human

pre-personal part of subjectivity is crucial since it is from this

that its heterogenesis can develop. It would be to misjudge


Deleuze and Foucault - who emphasised the non-human part

of subjectivity - to suspect them of taking anti-humanist posi tions I That's not the issue. Rather, it's a question of being

aware of the existence of m�shL�es of s11bjectivatio� which

<!o_n_'t simply WQrk within the "the f&culties of _!_ht:i �oul," inter

personal relations or intra-familial complexes. Subjectivity does

not only produce itself through the psychogenetic stages of psy

choanalysis or the "mathemes" of the Unconscious, but also in the large-scale social machines of language and the mass

media- which cannot be described as human. A certain bal-


1 0 Chaosmosis

ance still needs to be struck between structuralist discoveries - which are certainly not unimportant - and their pragmatic

application, so as not to flounder in the social abandon of post-


"____ -.,_ --"-- ,modernism.
With his concept of the Unconscious Freud postulated the existence of a hidden continent of the psyche, where instinctu

al, affective and cognitive options in large part would be

played out. Today we can't dissociate the theories of the Unconscious from the psychoanalytic, psychotherapeutic,

institutional and literary practices which make reference to it. The Unconscious has become an institution, "Collective

Equipment" understood in a broadest sense. One finds oneself

rigged out with an unconscious the moment one dreams,

delires, forgets or makes a slip of the tongue ... Freudian dis coveries - which I prefer to call inventions - have undoubt

edly enriched the ways we can approach the psyche. I am cer tainly not speaking pejoratively of invention! In the same way

that Christians invented a new form of subjectivation (courtly

chivalry and romanticism, a new love, a new nature) and Bolshevism a new sense of class, the various Freudian sects

have secreted new ways of experiencing - or even of produc ing - hysteria, infantile neurosis, psychosis, family contlict,

the reading of myths, etc. The Freudian Unconscious has itself

evolved in the course of its history: it has lost the seething

richness and disquieting atheism of its origins and, in its struc turalist version, has been recentered on the analysis of the self,

its adaptation to society, and its conformity with a signifying

order.

My perspective involves shifting the human and social sciences

from scientific paradigms towards ethico-aesthetic paradigms.

It's no longer a question of determining whether the Freudian

Unconscious or the Lacanian Unconscious provide scientific


On the production of subjectivity 1 1

answers to the problems of the psyche. From now on these

models, along with the others, will only be considered in terms

of the production of subjectivity - inseparable as much from

the technical and institutional apparatuses which promote it as

from their impact on psychiatry, university teaching or the

mass media ... In a more general way, one has to admit that

every individual and social group conveys its own system of

modelising subjectivity; that is, a certain cartography - com

posed of cognitive references as well as mythical, ritual and

symptomatological references - with which it positions itself

in relation to its affects and anguishes, and attempts to manage

its inhibitions and drives.

Psychoanalytic treatment confronts us with a multiplicity

of cartographies: that of the analyst and analysand, and of the

family, the neighbourhood, etc. It is the interaction of these

cartographies that will provide regimes to the different assem

blages of subjectivation. None of them, whether fantasmatic,

delirious or theoretical, can be said to express an objective


knowledge of the psyche. All of them are important insofar as

they support a certain context, a certain framework, an exis tential armature of the subjective situation. Our question here

is not simply of a speculative order, but is posed in very practi

n
us o 'the
cal ways: how appropriate are concepts of the Unconcious, �ffered to psychoanalytic "market," to actual condi tions of the production of
subjectivity? Should they be trans

formed, should new ones be invented? This question of modeli

sation (more exactly of psychological metamodelisation) leads

to an evaluation of the usefulness of these cartographic instru

ments - these concepts from psychoanalysis, systems theory,

etc. Do we use them as a grid for an exclusive universal read

ing, with scientific claims, or as partial instruments, in combi

nation with others, the ultimate criterion being of a functional

order? What processes unfold in a consciousness affected by the


1 2 Chaosmosis

shock of the unexpected? How can a mode of thought, a capaci

ty to apprehend, be modified when the surrounding world itself is in the throes of change ? How are the representations of an

exterior world changed when it is itself in the process of chang

ing? The Freudian Unconscious is inseparable from a society

attached to its past, to its phallocratic traditions and subjective

invariants. Contemporary upheavals undoubtedly call for a

modelisation turned more towards the future and the emer

gence of new social and aesthetic practices. The devaluation of

the meaning of life provokes the fragmentation of the self

image: its representations become confused and contradictory.

Faced with these upheavals the best attitude would be to envis

age the work of cartography and psychological modelisation in

a dialectical relation with the individuals and groups con

cerned; the crucial thing is to move in the direction of co-man

agement in the production of subjectivity, to distrust sugges

tion and the attitudes of authority which occupy such a large

place in psychoanalysis, in spite of the fact that it claims to

have escaped them.

A long time ago I renounced the Conscious-Unconscious

dualism of the Freudian topoi and all the Manichean opposi

tions correlative to Oedipal triangulation and to the castration

complex. I opted for an Unconscious superposing multiple stra

ta of subjectivation, heterogeneous strata of variable extension


;and consistency. Thus a more "schizo" Unconscious, one liber \ated from familial shackles, turned more towards actual praxis r;t:han towards

fixations on, and regressions to, the past. An \pnconscious of Flux and of abstract machines rather than an pnconscious of structure and

language. I don't, however, con �ider my "schizoanalytic cartographies"4 to be scientific theo hes. Just as an artist borrows from his precursors
and contem

poraries the traits which suit him, I invite those who read me to

take or reject my concepts freely. The important thing is not the


On the production of subjectivity 1 3

final result but the fact that the multicomponential cartograph

ic method can co-exist with the process of subjectivation, and

that a reappropriation, an autopoiesis, of the means of produc

tion of subjectivity can be made possible.

Of course, I am not equating either psychosis to the work of art or the psychoanalyst to the artist! I am only emphasising

that the existential registers concerned here involve a dimen

sion of autonomy of an aesthetic order. We are faced with an

important ethical choice: eithe� we objectify, reify, "scientifise"

subjectivity, or, on the contrary, we try to grasp it in the dimen

sion of its processual creativity. Kant established that the

judgement of taste involved subjectivity and its relation to the other in a certain attitude of "disinterestedness."5 But it is not

enough to designate the categories of disinterestedness and

freedom as the essential dimension of the unconscious aesthetic

without clarifying their active mode of insertion into the psy

che. How do certain semiotic segments achieve their autono

my, start to work for themselves and to secrete new fields of ref

erence? It is from such a rupture that an existential singularisa

tion correlative to the genesis of new coefficients of freedom will

become possible. This detachment of an ethico-aesthetic "par

tial object" from the field of dominant significations corre

sponds both to the promotion of a mutant desire and to the

achievement of a certain disinterestedness. Here I would like to

establish a bridge between the concept of a partial object (object

"a" as theorised by Lacan) that marks the autonomisation of the components of unconscious subjectivity, and the subjective

autonomisation relative to the aesthetic object. At this point we

rediscover a problematic highlighted by Mikha'il Bakhtin in his first theoretical essay6 of 1924: the function of enunciative

appropriation of aesthetic form by the autonomisation of cogni

tive or ethical content and the realisation of this content in an aesthetic object - what I wil1 call a partial enunciator. I am
1 4 Chaos mos is

attempting to draw the psychoanalytic partial object that is

adjacent to the body - the point of coupling of the drive -

towards a partial enunciation. The expansion of the notion of

partial object, to which Lacan contributed with the inclusion of

the gaze and the voice in the object "a", needs to be followed

up. This entails expanding the category to cover the full range

of nuclei of subjective autonomisation relative to group sub

jects, and to instances of the production of subjectivity (machinic, ecological, archictectural, religious, etc.). Bakhtin ]described a

transference of subjectivation operating between \the author and the contemplator of a work of art- the "spec ;/tator" in Marcel Duchamp's

j
sense. According to Bakhtin, in . this movement the "consumer" in some way becomes co-cre \ator; the aesthetic form only achieving this
result through the

device of an isolating or separating function of such a kind that

the expressive material becomes formally creative. The content

of the work of art detaches itself from its connotations that are

as much cognitive as aesthetic: "isolation or detachment

relates not to the material, not to the work as thing, but to its

significance, to its content, which is freed from certain neces

sary connections with the unity of nature and the unity of the

ethical event of being. "7 There is tbus_a c_ertain tyIJe Q[frag ment of content that "taJrns possession ofthe author" to engen

der a certain mode of aesthetic enunciation. In music, for example, as Bakhtin emphasises, isolation and invention can

not be axiologically related to the material: "It is not the sound of acoustics that is isolated, and not the mathematical number

of the compositional order that is made up. What is detached

and fictively irreversible is the event of striving, the axiological

tension, which actualises itself thanks to that without any

impediment, and becomes consummated."8 In the domain of

poetry, in order to detach itself, autonomise itself, culminate

itself, creative subjectivity will tend to seize upon:


On the production of subjectivity 1 5
1. the sonority of the word, its musical aspect; 2. its material significations with their nuances and variants; 3. its verbal connections; 4. its
emotional, intonational and volitional aspects; 5. the feeling of verbal activity in the active generation of a sig
nifying sound, including motor elements of articulation,
gesture, mime; the feeling of a movement in which the
whole organism together with the activity and soul of the
word are swept along in the�r concrete unity.
And it is this last aspect, declares Bakhtin, that encompasses all
the others.9
These penetrating analyses can lead to an extension of our
approach to partial subjectivation. Equally, we find with
Bakhtin the idea of irreversibility of the aesthetic object and
implicitly the idea of autopoiesis - notions truly necessary to
the analysis of Unconscious formations, pedagogy, psychiatry,
and more generally to a social field devastated by capitalist sub
jectivity. Thus it is not only in the context of music and poetry
that we see the work of such fragments detached from content,
fragments which I place in the category of "existential
refrains." The polyphony of modes of subjectivation actually
�orresIJonds to a multiplicity of ways of "keeping time." Other
1'-.__,, ---,,, --" �
.

rhythmics are thus led to crystallise existenUal assemblages,


which they embody and singularise.
The simplest examples of refrains delimiting existential
Territories can be found in the ethology of numerous bird
species. Certain specific song sequences serve to seduce a sexual
partner, warn off intruders, or announce the arrival of preda tors.10 Each time this involves marking out a well-defined func
tional space. In archaic societies, it is through rhythms, chants,
dances, masks, marks on the body, ground and totems, on ritu al occasions and with mythical references, that other kinds of
collective existential Territories are circumscribed.11 One finds
1 6 Chaosmosis

these sorts ofrefrains in Greek Antiquity with the "nomes" that

constituted, in a way, the "signature tunes" the banners and

seals for professional associations. But we all familiar with such

crossings of subjective thresholds triggered by a catalysing tem

poral module that plunges us into sadness or indeed, into an ambience of gaiety and excitement. What we are aiming at

with this concept of refrain aren't just massive affects, but

hyper-complex refrains, catalysing the emergence of incorpore al Universes such as those of music or mathematics, and crys

tallising the most deterritorialised existential Territories. This

type of transversalist refrain evades strict spatio-temporal

delimitation. With it, time ceases to be exterior in order to become an intensive nucleus [foyer] of temporalisation. From

this perspective, universal time appears to be no more than a

hypothetical projection, a time of generalised equivalence, a

"flattened" capitalistic time; what is important are these partial

modules of temporalisation1 operating in diverse domains (bio

logical, ethological, socio-cultural, machinic, cosmic ... ), and

out of which complex refrains constitute highly relative exis

tential synchronies. /�o illustrate this mode of production of polyphonic subjec- . tivity, where a complex refrain plays a dominant role, consider

the example of televisual consumption. When I watch televi sion, I exist at the intersection: 1. of a perceptual fascination

provoked by the screen's luminous animation which borders on the hypnotic,12 2. of a captive relation with the narrative content of the program,
associated with a lateral awareness of

surrounding events (water boiling on the stove, a child's cry, I \ the telephone ... ), 3. of a world of fantasms occupying my day � j dreams. My

feeling of personal identity is thus pulled in differ- l ent directions. How can I maintain a relative sense of unicity, I despite the diversity of

components of subjectivation that pass l!hr9�ugh me? It's a question of the refrain that fixes me in front
On the production of subjectivity 1 7
of the screen, henceforth constituted as a projective existential

node. My identity has become that of the speaker, the person who speaks from the television. Like Bakhtin, I would say that

the refrain is not based on elements of form, material or ordi

nary signification, but on the detachment of an existential

"motif" (or leitmotiv) which installs itself like an "attractor"

within a sensible and significational chaos. The different com

ponents conserve their heterogeneity, but are nevertheless cap

tured by a refrain which couples them to the existential

Territory of my self. In the case of neurotic identity, sometimes

the refrain develops into a "hardened" representation, for

example, an obsessive ritual. If for any reason this machine of

subjectivation is threatened, the whole personality may

implode; this occurs in psychosis where the partial components

move off on delirious, hallucinatory lines .... The paradoxical

concept of a complex refrain will enable us, in psychoanalytic

treatment, to refer an interpretive event, no longer to Universals or mathemes, nor to preestablished structures of

subjectivity, but rather to what I call a constellation of

Universes. This does not involve Universes of reference in gen eral, but incorporeal domains of entities we detect at the same

time that we produce them, and which appear to have been

always there, from the moment we engender them. Here is the

real paradox of these Universes: they are given in the creative

moment, like a hecceity freed from discursive time - nuclei of

eternity lodged between instants. What's more, over and above the elements of the situation {familial, sexual, conflictual), they

involve accounting for the projection of all the lines of virtuali ty opening up from the event of their appearance. Take a sim ple example: a patient
in the course of treatment remains stuck

on a problem, going around in circles, and coming up against a

wall. One day he says, without giving it much thought: "I've been thinking of taking up driving lessons again, I haven't dri-
1 8 Chaosmosis

ven for years"; or, "I feel like learning word processing." A

remark of this kind may remain unnoticed in a traditional con

ception of analysis. However, this kind of singularity can

become a key, activating a complex refrain, which will not only

modify the immediate behaviour of the patient, but open up

new fields of virtuality for him: the renewal of contact with

long lost acquaintances, revisiting old haunts, regaining self

confidence .... In this, a rigid neutrality or non-intervention

would be negative; it's sometimes necessary to jump at the

opportunity, to approve, to run the risk of being wrong, to give

it a go, to say, "yes, perhaps this experience is important. "

Respond to the event as the potential bearer of new constella


tions of Universes of reference. This is why I have opted for

pragmatic interventions orientated towards the construction of

subjectities, towards the production of fields of virtualities

which wouldn't simply be polarised by a symbolic hermeneutic

centered on childhood.

In this conception of analysis, time is not something to be

endured; it is activated, orientated, the object of qualitative

change. Analysis is no longer the transferential interpretation

of symptoms as a function of a preexisting, latent content, but

the invention of new catalytic nuclei capable of bifurcating

existence. A singularity, a rupture of sense, a cut, a fragmenta

tion, the detachment of a semiotic content - in a dadaist or

surrealist manner - can originate mutant nuclei of subjectiva

tion. Just as chemistry has to purify complex mixtures to

extract atomic and homogeneous molecular matter, thus creat

ing an infinite scale of chemical entities that have no prior exis

tence, the same is true in the "extraction" and "separation" of

aesthetic subjectivities or partial objects, in the psychoanalytic

sense, that make an immense complexification of subjectivity

possible - harmonies, polyphonies, counterpoints, rhythms


On the production of subjectivity 1 9

and existential orchestrations, until now unheard and

unknown. An essentially precarious, deterritorialising com

plexification, constantly threatened by a reterritorialising sub

sidenGe; above all in the contemporary context where the pri

macy of information fluxes that are machinically engendered threaten to lead to a generalised dissolution of old existential

Territorialities. In the early phases of industrial society the

"demonic" still continued to flower, but since then mystery has

become a rarer and rarer commodity. One need only evoke the

desperate quest of Witkiewicz to grasp an ultimate "strange

ness of being" which literally appeared to slip between his fin

gers. In these conditions, the task of the poetic function, in an

enlarged sense, is to recompose artificially rarefied, resingu

larised Universes of subjectivation. For them, it's not a matter

of transmitting messages, investing images as aids to identifica

tion, patterns of behaviour as props for modelisation proce

dures, but of catalysing existential operators capable of acquir

ing consistence and persistence.


This poetic-existential catalysis that we find at work in the

midst of scriptural, vocal, musical or plastic discursivities

engages quasi-synchronically the enunciative crystallisation of

the creator, the interpreter and the admirer of the work of art,

like analyst and patient. Its efficiency lies in its capacity to pro

mote active, processual ruptures within semiotically struc

tured, significational and denotative networks, where it will put emergent subjectivity to work, in Daniel Stern's sense.

When it is effectively triggered in a given enunciative area -

that is, situated in a historical and geo-political perspective -

such an analytico-poetic function establishes itself as a mutant

nucleus of auto-referentiality and auto-valorisation. This is why we must always consider it in two ways: 1. as a molecular rupture, an imperceptible
bifurcation capable of overthrowing
20 Chaosmosis

the framework of dominant redundancies, the organisation of the "already classified" or, if one prefers, the classical order. 2.

in the way that it selects certain segments of these very chains of

redundancy, to confer on them the a-signifying existential func

tion I have just evoked, thereby "refraining" them and producing

virulent, partial fragments of enunciation operating as "shifters"

of subjectivation. The quality of the base material matters little

here, as one can see in repetitive music or Butoh dance, which, as Marcel Duchamp would have wished, are turned entirely

towards "the spectator." What does matter is the mutant rhyth

mic impetus of a temporalisation able to hold together the het

erogeneous components of a new existential edifice.

Beyond the poetic function, the question of the apparatuses

of subjectivation presents itself. And, more precisely, what

must characterise them so that they abandon seriality - in

Sartre's sense - and enter into processes of singularisation

which restore to existence what we might call its auto-essen

tialisation. With the fading antagonisms of the Cold War, we

enter a period when serious threats, posed by our productivist

society to the human species, appear more distinctly. Our sur

vival on this planet is not only threatened by environmental

damage but by a degeneration in the fabric of social solidarity

and in the modes of psychical life, which must literally be re

invented. The refoundation of politics will have to pass through

the aesthetic and analytical dimensions implied in the three

ecologies - the environment, the socius and the psyche. We

cannot conceive of solutions to the poisoning of the atmosphere

and to global warming due to the greenhouse effect, or to the

problem of population control, without a mutation of mentali ty, without promoting a new art ofliving in society. We cannot
conceive of international discipline in this domain without

solving the problem of hunger and hyperinflation in the Third

World. We cannot conceive of a collective recomposition of the


On the production of subjectivity 21

socius, correlative to a resingularisation of subjectivity, with

out a new way of conceiving political and economic democra

cies that respect cultural differences - without multiple molec

ular -revolutions. We cannot hope for an amelioration in the

living conditions of the human species without a considerable

effort to improve the feminine condition. The entire division of

labour, its modes of va:lorisation and finalities need to be

rethought. Production for the sake of production - the obses

sion with the rate of growth, whether in the capitalist market

or in planned economies - leads to monstrous absurdities. The

only acceptable finality of human activity is the production of a

subjectivity that is auto-enriching its relation to the world in a

continuous fashion. The productive apparatuses of subjectivity

can exist at the level of mega poles as easily as at the level of an

individual's language games. And to learn the intimate work

ings of this production, these ruptures of meaning that are

auto-foundational of existence - poetry today might have

more to teach us than economic science, the human sciences

and psychoanalysis combined.

That contemporary social transformations happen on a

large scale by a relatively progressive mutation of subjectivity,

or in the moderately conservative fashion one sees in the

Eastern bloc, or in the clearly reactionary, indeed neo-fascistic manner in the Middle East, and that, at the same time, such

changes can take place on a molecular level, microphysical in

Foucault's sense, in political activity, in analytic treatment, in

establishing an apparatus changing the life of the neighbour

hood, the way a school or psychiatric institution functions -

the synergy of these two processes calls for a departure from

structuralist reductionism and a refoundation of the problem atic of subjectivity. A partial subjectivity - pre-personal, poly

phonic, collective and machinic. Fundamentally, the question

of enunciation gets decentered in relation to that of human


22 Chaosmosis

individuation. Enunciation becomes correlative not only to the

emergence of a logic of non-discursive intensities, but equally to a pathic incorporation-agglomeration of these vectors of par

tial subjectivity. Thus it involves rejecting the habitually uni


versalising claims of psychological modelisation. The so-called

scientific content of psychoanalytic or systemic theories (as

well as mythological or religious modelising, or even the

mythological models of systematic delire ... ) are essentially valuable for their existentialising function, that is, for the pro

duction of subjectivity. In these conditions, theoretical activity

is reorientated towards a metamodelisation capable of taking into account the diversity ofmodelising systems. In particular it

involves situating the concrete incidence of capitalistic subjec

tivity (the subjectivity of generalised equivalence) within the

context of the continued development of the mass media,

Collective Equipment and the information revolution - a sub jectivity which seems likely to blot out, with its greyness, the

faintest traces and last recesses of the planet's mysteries.

So we are proposing to decentre the question of the sub

ject onto the question of subjectivity. Traditionally, the sub

ject was conceived as the ultimate essence of individuation,

as a pure, empty, prereflexive apprehension of the world, a

nucleus of sensibility, of expressivity - the unifier of states

of consciousness. With subjectivity we place the emphasis

instead on the founding instance of intentionality. This involves taking the relation between subject and object by the middle and foregrounding the
expressive instance (or

the interpretant of the Peircean triad). Hereafter, this is

where the question of Content will reside. Content partici

pates in subjectivity by giving consistency to the ontological

quality of Expression. It is in this reversibility of Content and

Expression where what I call the existentialising function

resides. Thus, we will start with the primacy of enunciative


On the production of subjectivity 23

substance over the couplet of Expression and Content.

I believe I've found a valid alternative to the structuralism

inspired by Saussure, one that relies on the Expression/Content

distinction formulated by Hjelmslev,13 that is to say, based pre cisely on the potential reversibility of Expression and Content.

Going beyond Hjelmslev, I intend to consider a multiplicity of

expressive instances, whether they be of the order ofExpression

or Content. Rather than playing on the Expression/Content

opposition which, with Hjelmslev, still repeats Saussure's signi

fier/signified couplet, this would involve putting a multiplicity of components of Expression, or substances of Expression in

parallel, in polyphony. There is a difficulty in that Hjelmslev

himself used the category of substance in a tripartite division

between matter, substance and form relating on one hand to Expression and on the other to Content. With Hjelmslev, the

connection between Expression and Content is realised at the


level of the form of Expression and form of Content, which he

identified with each other. This common and commuting form is a bit strange but it represents, in my opinion, a brilliant intu

ition, posing the question of the existence of a formal machine,

transversal to every modality of Expression and Content. There is then, a bridge, a transversality between on one side the

machine of phonemic and syntagmatic discursivity of Expression proper to language, and on the other, the division of

semantic unities of Content (for example, the way classification

of colours or animal categories is established). I call this com mon form a deterritorialised machine, an abstract machine.

The notion of an abstract semiotic machine isn't new: we find it in Chomsky who postulates its existence at the root of lan

guage. But this concept, this Expression/Content opposition -

as well as the Chomskian concept of the abstract machine - remained too bound up with language. For our part, we would
24 Chaosmosis

like to resituate semiology within the scope of an expanded,

machinic conception which would free us from a simple lin guistic opposition between Expression/Content, and allow us to

integrate into enunciative assemblages an indefinite number of

substances of Expression, such as biological codings or organi

sational forms belonging to the socius. From this perspective,

the question of enunciative substance should also be outside

the framework of Hjelmslev's tripartite division, matter-sub stance-form (form casting itself "like a net" over matter, there

by engendering the substance of Expression and Content). It

would involve shattering the concept of substance in a pluralis

tic manner, and would promote the category of substance of

Expression not only in semiology and semiotics, but in domains

that are extra-linguistic, non-human, biological, technological,

aesthetic, etc. The problem of the enunciative assemblage

would then no longer be specific to a semiotic register but

would traverse an ensemble of heterogeneous expressive mate

rials. Thus a transversality between enunciative substances

which can be, on one hand, linguistic, but on the other, of a

machinic order, developing from "non-semiotically formed

matter," to use another of Hjelmslev's expressions. Machinic

subjectivity, the machinic assemblage of enunciation, agglom

erates these different partial enunciations and installs itself, as

it were, before and alongside the subject-object relation. It has,

moreover, a collective character, it is multi-componential, a

machinic multiplicity. Finally, it includes incorporeal dimen sions, which perhaps constitutes its most problematic aspect,

and one that Noam Chomsky only touches on in his attempt to

make use of the Medieval concept of Universals.

Expressive, linguistic and non-linguistic substances install

themselves at the junction of discursive chains (belonging to a


finite, preformed world, the world of the Lacanian Other) and

incorporeal registers with infinite, creationist virtualities


On the production of subjectivity 25

(which have nothing to do with Lacanian "mathemes"). It is in

this zone of intersection that subject and object fuse and estab

lish their foundations. It concerns a given that phenomenolo

gists have addressed when they demonstrate that intentionali ty is inseparable from its object and involves a "before" in the

discursive, subject-object relation. Some psychologists have

focused on the relations of empathy and transitivism in infancy

and psychosis. Lacan, in his early works, when still influenced

by phenomenology, evoked the importance of this type of phe

nomenon. Generally, one can say that psychoanalysis is born

at this point of object-subject fusion that we see at work in sug

gestion, hypnosis and hysteria. It is an attempt at reading sub

jective transitivism that is at the origin of Freudian theory and

practice. Moreover, anthropologists, since the era of Levi Bruhl, Priezluski, etc., have shown that in archaic societies, there was what they call
"participation," a collective subjectivi

ty investing a certain type of object, and putting itself in the

position of an existential group nucleus. In studies on new

forms of art (like Deleuze's on cinema) we will see, for example,

movement-images and time-images constituting the seeds of the production of subjectivity. We are not in the presence of a

passively representative image, but of a vector of subjectiva

tion. We are actually confronted by a non-discursive; pathic

knowledge, which presents itself as a subjectivity that one

actively meets, an absorbant subjectivity given immediately in

all its complexity. We can trace this intuition to Bergson, who

shed light on the non-discursive experience of duration by

opposing it to a time cut up into present, past and future,

according to spatial schemas. It is true that this pathic subjec

tivity, before the subject-object relation, continues to self-actu

alise through energetico-spatio-temporal coordinates, in the

world of language and through multiple mediations; but what

allows us to grasp the force involved in the production of sub-


26 Chaosmosis

jectivity is the apprehension through it of a pseudo-discursivity,

a detournement of discursivity, which installs itself at the foun dation of the subject-object relation, in a subjective pseudo

mediation.

This pathic subjectivation, at the root of all modes of subjec

tivation, is overshadowed in rationalist, capitalistic subjectivity


which tends to systematically circumvent it. Science is con

structed by bracketing these factors of subjectivation, which

achieve Expression only when certain discursive links are put

outside of signification. Freudianism, although impregnated

with scientism, can, in its early stages, be characterised as a

rebellion against a positivist reductionism which tended to do

without these pathic dimensions. In Freudianism the symptom,

the lapsus or joke are conceived as detached objects allowing a

mode of subjectivity, which has lost its consistency, to find the

path to a "coming into existence." The symptom through its

own repetitiveness functions like an existential refrain. The paradox resides in the fact that pathic subjectivity tends to be

constantly evacuated from relations of discursivity, although

discursive operators are essentially based on it. The existential

function of assemblages of enunciation consists in this utilisa

tion of links of discursivity to establish a system of repetition, of

intensive insistence, polarised between a territorialised existen

tial Territory and deterritorialised incorporeal Universes - two

metapsychological functions we can describe as onto-genetic.

The Universes of referential value confer their own texture on

machines of Expression articulated in machinic Phylums.

Complex refrains, beyond the simple refrains of territorialisa

tion, restates the singular consistency of these Universes. (For

example, the pathic apprehension of harmonic resonances

based on the diatonic scale deploys the "foundation" of consis

tency of polyphonic music, just as in another context the

apprehension of the possible concatenation of numbers and


On the production of subjectivity 27

algorithms deploys the foundation of mathematical idealities.)

The abstract machinic consistency which is thus conferred on

assemblages of enunciation resides in the layering and ordering

of partial levels of existential territorialisation. What's more,

the complex refrain functions as an interface between actu

alised registers of discursivity and non-discursive Universes of

virtuality. It is the most deterritorialised aspect of the refrain, its

dimension of incorporeal Universes of value which takes con

trol of the most territorialised strata. It does this through a

movement of deterritorialisation that develops fields of the pos

sible, tensions in value, relations of heterogeneity, ofalterity, of

becoming other. The difference between these Universes of


value and Platonic Ideas is that the former do not have a fixed

character. They involve constellations of Universes, within

which a component can affirm itself over others and modify the

initial referential configuration and dominant mode ofvalorisa

tion. (For example, we can see throughout the course of

Antiquity the primacy of a military machine based on metal

weapons affirming itself over the despotic State machine, the

writing machine, the religious machine, etc.) The crystallisa

tion of such constellations can be "overtaken" during the

course of historical discursivity, but never wiped out since it is

an irreversible rupture in the incorporeal memory of collective

subjectivity. Thus we are situated totally outside the vision of a

Being moving unchanged through the universal history of

ontological formations. There are singular incorporeal constel

lations which belong to natural and human history and at the

same time escape them by a thousand lines of flight. The

moment mathematical Universes started to appear, it is no

longer possible to act as though the abstract machines which

support them had not always existed everywhere and for all

time and as though they do not project themselves onto future

possibles. We can no longer act as though polyphonic music


28 Chaosmosis

had not been in vented for the rest of time, both past and future. Such is the first stratum of ontological consistency of this func

tion of existential subjectivation, which is situated within the

perspective of a certain axiological creationism.

The second is the embodiment of these values in the irre

versibility of the being-there of existential Territories, which

confer their character of autopoiesis and singularity on to the

zones of subjectivation. In the logic of discursive ensembles

which dictates the domains of Fluxes and machinic Phylums,

there is always a separation between the poles of subject and

object. The truth of a proposition answers to the law of the

excluded middle; each object appears in a relationship of binary

opposition with a "foundation." Whereas in pathic logic, there

is no extrinsic global reference that can be circumscribed. The

object relation is destabilised, and the functions of subjectiva

tion are put into question. An incorporeal universe is not sup

ported by coordinates embedded in the world, but by ordinates,

by an intensive ordination coupled for better or worse to these


existential Territories. Territories which claim to encompass, in

a single movement, the sum of everyday existence but which

are in fact only based on derisory refrains, indexing if not their

vacuity then at least the degree zero of their ontological intensi

ty: thus Territories never given as object but always as inten

sive repetition, as piercing existential affirmation. And I repeat,

this operation is effected through the borrowing of semiotic

links, detached and diverted from their signifying and coding

tasks. Here, an expressive instance is based on a matter-form

relation, which extracts complex forms from a chaotic material. The logic of discursive sets finds a kind of desperate fulfil

ment in Capital, the Signifier, and Being with a capital B.

Capital is the referent for the generalised equivalence between

labour and goods; the Signifier the capitalistic referent for semi-
On the production of subjectivity 29

ological expression, the great reducer of ontological polyvocality.

The true, the good, the beautiful are "normalising" categories

for processes which escape the logic of circumscribed sets. They

are empty referents, they create a void, they install transcen

dence in the relations of representation. To choose Capital, the

Signifier or Being, is to participate in a similar ethicopolitical

option. Capital smashes all other modes of valorisation. The

Signifier silences the infinite virtualities of minor languages

and partial expressions. Being is like an imprisonment which

blinds us to the richness and multivalence of Universes of value

which, nevertheless, proliferate under our noses. There is an

ethical choice in favour of the richness of the possible, an ethics

and politics of the virtual that decorporealises and deterritori

alises contingency, linear causality and the pressure of circum

stances and significations which besiege us. It is a choice for

processuality, irreversibility and resingularisation. On a small

scale, this redeployment can turn itself into the mode of entrap

ment, of impoverishment, indeed of catastrophe in neurosis. It can take up reactive religious references. It can annihilate itself

in alcohol, drugs, television, an endless daily grind. But it can

also make use of other procedures that are more collective,

more social, more political ...

In order to question dualist oppositions, such as Being-being or

Subject-Object, and systems of Manichean bipolar valorisa

tions, I have proposed the concept of ontological intensity. It

implies an ethico-aesthetic engagement with the enunciative


assemblage, both in actual and virtual registers. But another

element of the metamodelisation proposed here resides in the

collective character of machinic multiplicities. There is no per son o logic al totalisation of the different components of

Expression, or the self-enclosed totalisation of Universes of ref

erence, either in the sciences, the arts or in society. There is an


30 Cha osmosis

agglomeration of heterogeneous factors of subjectivation.

Machinic segments refer to a detotalised, deterritorialised

mecanosphere, to an infinite play of interface. There is no Being

already installed throughout temporality. This questioning of

dual, binary relations (Being-being, or Conscious-Unconscious)

implies a questioning of semiotic linearity - which always

seems to be beyond question. Pathic expression is not placed in a

relation of discursive succession in order to situate the object on

the basis of a clearly delimited referent. Here we are in a register

of co-existence, of crystallisation of intensity. Time does not exist

as an empty container (a conception which remains at the root

of Einsteinian thought). The relations of temporalisation are

essentially those of machinic synchrony. There is a deployment

of axiological ordinates, without the constitution of a referent

exterior to this deployment. Here we are before the relation of

"extensionalising" linearity, between an object and its represen

tative mediation within an abstract machinic complexion.

Will we say of the incorporeal and virtual part of assem blages of enunciation that it is in voce according to a "termin

ist," nominalist viewpoint, which makes semiotic entities the tributaries of a pure subjectivity; or will we say that they are in re within the
framework of a realist conception of the world,

subjectivity being only an illusory artefact? But maybe it's nec

essary to affirm both these positions concurrently: the domain

of virtual intensities establishing itself prior to distinctions

being made between the semiotic machine, the referred object

and the enunciative subject. It's from a failure to see that

machinic segments are autopoietic and ontogenetic that one

endlessly makes universalist reductions to the Signifier and to scientific rationality. Machinic interfaces are heterogenetic;

they summon the alterity of the points of view we might have

on them and, as a consequence, on the systems of metamodeli

sation which allow us to account, in one way or another, for the


On the production of subjectivity 31

fundamentally inaccessible character of their autopoietic nuclei.

We need to free ourselves from a solitary reference to technolog


ical machines and expand the concept of machine so as to situ

ate the machine's adjacence to incorporeal Universes of refer

ence. Note that the categories of metamodelisation proposed

here - Fluxes, machinic Phylums, existential Territories,

incorporeal Universes - are only of interest because they come in fours and allow us to break free of tertiary descriptions

which always end up falling back into dualisms. The fourth

term stands for an nth term: it is the opening onto multiplicity.

What distinguishes metamodelisation from modelisation is the

way it uses terms to develop possible openings onto the virtual

and onto creative processuality.

1 Daniel Stern, The Interpersonal World of the Infant, Basic Books,

New York, 19 85. See later pp. 65-6.

2 Francisco Varela, Autonomie et Connaissance, Le Seuil, Paris, 1989.

[This is a revised French edition of Principles of Biological

Autonomy, North Holland Press, New York, 19 79 .]

3 Mony Elkaim, If You Love Me, Don't Love Me, Basic Books, New

York, 1990.

4 Felix Guattari, Cartographies schizoanalytiques, Galilee, Paris, 1989.

5 "Of all these three kinds of delight (in the agreeable, the beautiful,

and the good), that of taste in the beautiful may be said to be the

one and only disinterested and free delight; for, with it, no interest,

whether of sense or reason extorts approval." Immanuel Kant, The

Critique ofludgement, trans. James Creed Meredith, Clarendon

Press, Oxford, 1982, p.49 .

6 MikhaYl Bakhtin, "Content, Material, and Form in Verbal Art," in

Art and Answerability: Eary Philosophical Essays by M.M.Baktin,

edited by Michael Hoquist and V adim Liapunov, University of

Texas Press, Austin, 1990.

7 Ibid., p.306.

8 Ibid .. p.307.

9 Ibid., p.307.
32 Chaosmosis

10 Felix Guattari, L'Inconscient mac/1inique, Recherche, Paris, 19 79.

11 See the role of dreams in the mythical cartographies of Australian

Aborigines. Barbara Glocewski, Les Reveurs du desert, Pion, Paris,

19 89.

12 For a re-examination of hypnosis and suggestion, see Leon

Chertok and Isabelle Stengers, A Critique of Psychoanalytic Reason:

Hypnosis as a Scientific Problem from Lavoisier to Lacan, trans.

Martha N Evans, Stanford University Press, Stanford, 199 2 .

1 3 Louis Hjelmslev, Prolegomena to a Theory of Language, trans. Francis

J. Whitfield, University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, 1969);


Language: an introduction, Wisconsin University Press, Madison,

1 9 70; Bssais linguistiques, Minuit, Paris, 1 97 1; Nouveaux Bssais,

PUF, Paris, 1 98 5.

2 Machinic heterogenesis

Common usage suggests that we speak of the machine as a sub

set of technology. We should, however, consider the problemat

ic of technology as dependent on machines, and not the inverse.

The machine would become the prerequisite for technology

rather than its expression. Machinism is an object of fascination,

sometimes of delire, about which there's a whole historical "bes

tiary." Since the origin of philosophy, the relationship between

man and machine has been the object of interrogation. Aristotle

thought that the goal of techne was to create what nature found

impossible to accomplish. Being of the order of "knowledge" and

not of "doing," techne interposes a kind of creative mediation between nature and humanity whose status of intercession is a

source of perpetual ambiguity. "Mechanist" conceptions of the

machine empty it of everything that would enable it to avoid a simple construction partes extra partes. "Vitalist" conceptions

assimilate the machine to living beings; unless it is living beings

that are assimilated to machines. The "cybernetic" perspective

developed by Norbert Wiener1 envisages living systems as par

ticular types of machines equipped with the principle of feed

back. More recent "systemic" conceptions (Humberto Maturana


34 Chaosmosis

and Francisco Varela) develop the concept of autopoiesis (auto

production), reserving it for living machines. Following

Heidegger, a philosophical fashion entrusts techne - in its

opposition to modern technology - with the mission of

"unmasking the truth" that "seeks the true in the exact." Thus it nails techne to an ontological plinth - to a grund and com
-

promises its character of processual opening.

Through these positions, we will attempt to discern various levels of ontological intensity and envisage machinism in its

totality, in its technological, social, semiotic and axiological

avatars. And this will involve a reconstruction of the concept of

machine that goes far beyond the technical machine. For each
type of machine, we will pose a question, not about its vital

autonomy - it's not an animal - but about its singular

power of enunciation: what I call its specific enunciative con

sistency. The first type of machine we are going to consider is

the material apparatus. They are made by the hand of man -

itself taken over by other machines - according to conceptions

and plans which respond to the goals of production. These dif

ferent stages I will call finalised, diagrammatic schemas. But

already this montage and these finalisations impose the neces sity of expanding the limits of the machine, stricto sensu, to the

functional ensemble which associates it with man. We will see

that this implies taking into account multiple components:

- material and energy components

- semiotic, diagrammatic and algorithmic components (plans,

formulae, equations and calculations which lead to the fabrica tion of the machine);

components of organs, influx and humours of the human body; - individual and collective mental representations and infor

mation;

-investments of desiring machines producing a subjectivity

adjacent to these components;


Machinic heterogenesis 35

- abstract machines installing themselves transversally to the

machinic levels previously considered (material, cognitive,

affective and social).

When we speak of abstract machines, by "abstract" we can

also understand "extract" in the sense of extracting. They are

montages capable of relating all the heterogeneous levels that they traverse and that we have just enumerated. The abstract

machine is transversal to them, and it is this abstract machine

that will or will not give these levels an existence, an efficiency,

a power of ontological auto-affirmation. The different compo-

• nents are swept up and reshaped by a sort of dynamism. Such a

functional ensemble will hereafter be described as a machinic

assemblage. The term assemblage does not imply any notion of bond, passage, or anastomosis between its components. It is an

assemblage of possible fields, of virtual as much as constituted

elements, without any notion of generic or species' relation. In

this context, utensils, instruments, the most basic tools and the

least structured pieces of a machine acquire the status of a

pro to-machine.

Let us take an example. If we take a hammer apart by

removing its handle, it is still a hammer but in a "mutilated"

state. The "head" of the hammer - another zoomorphic


metaphor - can be reduced by fusion. It will then cross a

threshold of formal consistency where it will lose its form; this

machinic gestalt works moreover as much on a technological

plane as on an imaginary level, to evoke the dated memory of

the hammer and sickle. We are simply in the presence of metal

lic mass returned to smoothness, to the deterritorialisation

which precedes its appearance in a machinic form. To go

beyond this type of experiment - comparable to the piece of

Cartesian wax - let us attempt the inverse, to associate the ham mer with the arm, the nail with the anvil. Between them they main

tain relations ofsyntagmatic linkage. And their "collective dance"


36 Chaosmosis

can bring to life the defunct guild of blacksmiths, the sinister

epoch of ancient iron mines, the ancestral use of metal-rimmed

wheels ... Leroi-Gourhan emphasised that the technical object

was nothing outside of the technical ensemble to which it

belonged. It is the same for sophisticated machines such as

robots, which will soon be engendered by other robots. Human

action remains adjacent to their gestation, waiting for the

breakdown which will require its intervention: this residue of a

direct act. But doesn't all this suggest a partial view, a certain

taste for a dated period of science fiction? Curiously, in acquir

ing more and more life, machines demand in return more and

more abstract human vitality: and this has occurred through

out their evolutionary development. Computers, expert systems

and artificial intelligence add as much to thought as they sub

tract from thinking. They relieve thought of inert schemas. The

forms of thought assisted by computer are mutant, relating to other musics, other Universes ofreference.2

It is, then, impossible to deny the participation of human

thought in the essence of machinism. But up to what point can

this thought still be described as human? Doesn't technico-sci

entific thought fall within the province of a certain type of men

tal and semiotic machinism? What we need here is a distinction

between on the one hand semiologies that produce significa tions, the common currency of social groups - like the

"human" enunciation of people who work with machines -

and on the other, a-signifying semiotics which, regardless of

the quantity of significations they convey, handle figures of

expression that might be qualified as "non-human" (such as

equations and plans which enunciate the machine and make it

act in a diagrammatic capacity on technical and experimental apparatuses). The semiologies of signification play in keys with
distinctive oppositions of a phonematic or scriptural order which transcribe enunciations into materials of signifying
Machinic heterogenesis 37

expression. Structuralists have been content to erect the

Signifier as a category unifying all expressive economies: lan guage, the icon, gesture, urbanism or the cinema, etc. They

have postulated a general signifying translatability for all forms

of discurt'ivity. But in so doing, have they not misunderstood

the essential dimension ofmachinic autopoiesis? This continual

emergence of sense and effects does not concern the redundan

cy of mimesis but rather the production of an effect of singular

sense, even though indefinitely reproducible.

This autopoietic node in the machine is what separates and dif


ferentiates it from structure and gives it value. Structure

implies feedback loops, it puts into play a concept oftotalisation

that it itself masters. It is occupied by inputs and outputs whose purpose is to make the structure function according to a princi

ple of eternal return. It is haunted by a desire for eternity. The

machine, on the contrary, is shaped by a desire for abolition. Its

emergence is doubled with breakdown, catastrophe - the

menace of death. It possesses a supplement: a dimension of

alterity which it develops in different forms. This alterity differ entiates it from structure, which is based on a principle of

homeomorphism. The difference supplied b y machinic

autopoiesis is based on disequilibrium, the prospection of virtu

al Universes far from equilibrium. And this doesn't simply

involve a rupture of formal equilibrium, bu.t a radical ontologi

cal reconversion. The machine always depends on exterior ele

ments in order to be able to exist as such. It implies a comple

mentarity, not just with the man who fabricates it, makes it

function or destroys it, but it is itself in a relation of alterity with other virtual or actual machines - a "non-human" enuncia

tion, a proto-subjective diagram.

This ontological reconversion dismisses the totalising scope

of the concept of the Signifier. Because the signifying entities


38 Cha osmosis

which operate the diverse mutations of the ontological referent

- that makes us move from the Universe of molecular chem

istry to the Universe of biological chemistry, or from the

acoustic world to the world of polyphonic and harmonic music

- are not the same. Of course, lines of signifying decoding,

composed of discrete figures - binarisable, syntagmatisable

and paradigmatisable - sometimes appear in one Universe or


another. And we can have the illusion that the same signifying

network occupies all these domains. It is, however, totally dif

ferent when we consider the actual texture of these Universes

of reference. They are always stamped with the mark of singu

larity. From acoustics to polyphonic music, there is a diver

gence of constellations of expressive intensity. They involve a

certain pathic relationship, and convey irreducibly heteroge

neous ontological consistencies. We thus discover as many

types of deterritorialisation as traits of expressive materials. The

signifying articulation hanging over them - in its indifferent

neutrality - is incapable of imposing itself as a relation of

immanence to machinic intensities, to this non-discursive,

auto-enunciating, auto-valorising, autopoietic node. It does

not submit to any general syntax of the procedures of deterrito

rialisation. No couplet - Being-being, Being-Nothingness,

being-other - can claim the status of an ontological binary digit. Machinic propositions elude the ordinary games of dis

cursivity and the structural coordinates of energy, time and

space.
Yet an ontological transversality does nonetheless exist in

them. What happens at a level of the particulate-cosmic is not

without relation to the human soul or events in the socius. But not according to harmonic universals of the Platonic type (Sophist). The
composition of deterritorialising intensities

is incarnated in abstract machines. We should bear in mind

that there is a machinic essence which will incarnate itself in a


Machinic heterogenesis 39

technical machine, and equally in the social and cognitive

environment connected to this machine - social groups are

also machines, the body is a machine, there are scientific, theo

retical and information machines. The abstract machine passes

through all these heterogeneous components but above all it heterogenises them, be,yond any unifying trait and according

to a principle of irreversibility, singularity and necessity. In this

respect the Lacanian signifier is struck with a double lack: it is

too abstract in that it makes heterogeneous, expressive materi

als translatable, it lacks ontological heterogenesis, it gratu

itously uniformises and syntaxises diverse regions of being,

and, at the same time, it is not abstract enough because it is

incapable of taking into account the specificity of these

machinic autopoietic nodes, to which we must now return.

Francisco Varela characterises a machine by "the set of

inter-relations of its components independent of the compo


nents themselves." 3 The organisation of a machine thus has no

connection with its materiality. He distinguishes two types of

machines: "allopoietic" machines which produce something

other than themselves, and "autopoietic" machines which

engender and specify their own organisation and limits.

Autopoietic machines undertake an incessant process of the

replacement of their components as they must continually

compensate for the external perturbations to which they are

exposed. In fact, the qualification of autopoietic is reserved by

Varela for the biological domain: social systems, technical

machines, crystalline systems, etc., are excluded. This is the

sense of his distinction between allopoiesis and autopoiesis. But

autopoiesis, which uniquely defines autonomous entities -

unitary, individuated and closed to input/output relationships

- lacks characteristics essential to living organisms, like the fact that they are born, die and survive through genetic

phylums. Autopoiesis deserves to be rethought in terms of


40 Cha osmosis

evolutionary, collective entities, which maintain diverse types

of relations of alterity, rather than being implacably closed in on themselves. In such a case, institutions and technical

machines appear to be allopoietic, but when one considers

them in the context of the machinic assemblages they consti

tute with human beings, they become ipso facto autopoietic.

Thus we will view autopoiesis from the perspective of the onto

genesis and phlyogenesis proper to a mecanosphere superposed

on the biosphere.

The phylogenetic evolution of machinism is expressed, at a

primary level, by the fact that machines appear across "genera tions," one suppressing the other as it becomes obsolete. The fil

iation of previous generations is prolonged into the future by

lines of virtuality and their arborent implications. But this is

not a question of a univocal historical causality. Evolutionary

lines appear in rhizomes; datings are not synchronic but hete

rochronic. Example: the industrial "take off" of steam engines happened centuries after the Chinese Empire had used them as

children's toys. In fact, these evolutionary rhizomes move in

blocks across technical civilisations. A technological innova

tion may know long periods of stagnation or regression, but

there are few cases in which it does not "restart" at a later date.

This is particularly clear with military technological innova

tions: they frequently punctuate long historical periods that

they stamp with the seal of irreversibility, wiping out empires


for the benefit of new geopolitical configurations. But, and I repeat it, this was already true of the most humble instruments,

utensils and tools which don't escape this phylogenesis. One

could, for example, dedicate an exhibition to the evolution of

the hammer since the Iron Age and conjecture about what it will

become in the context of new materials and technologies. The

hammer that one buys today at the supermarket is, in a way, "drawn out" on a phylogenetic line of infinite, virtual extension.
Machinic heterogenesis 41

It is at the intersection of heterogeneous machinic

Universes, of different dimensions and with unfamiliar ontolog

ical textures, radical innovations and once forgotten, then

reactivated, ancestral machinic lines, that the movement of

history singularises itself. Among other components, the

Neolithic machine associates the machine of spoken language,

machines of hewn stone, agrarian machines based on the selec

tion of grains and a village proto-economy. The writing

machine will only emerge with the birth of urban mega

machines (Lewis Mumford) correlative to the spread of archaic

empires. Parallel to this, the great nomadic machines constitut

ed themselves out of the collusion between the metallurgic

machine and new war machines. As for the great capitalistic

machines, their foundational machinisms were prolific: urban

State machines, then royal machines, commercial and banking

machines , navigation machines, monotheist religious

machines, deterritorialised musical and plastic machines, sci

entific and technical machines, etc.


The question of the reproducibility of the machine on an

ontogenetic level is more complex. Maintaining a machine's

operationality - its functional identity - is never absolutely

guaranteed: wear and tear, fine balance, breakdowns and

entropy demand a renewal of its material components, its ener

gy and information components, the latter able to be lost in

"noise." Equally, the maintenance of a machinic assemblage's

consistency demands that the element of human action and intelligence involved in its composition must also be renewed.

The man-machine alterity is thus inextricably linked to a machine-machine alterity which operates in relations of com

plementarity or agonistic relations (between war machines) or

again in the relations of parts or apparatuses. In fact, the wear

and tear, accident, death and resurrection of a machine in a new copy or model are part of its destiny and can become central to
42 Chaosmosis

its essence in certain aesthetic machines (the "compressions" of


Cesar, the "metamechanics," the happening machines, the

delirious machines of Jean Tinguely). The reproducibility of the

machine is not a pure programmed repetition. The scansions of

rupture and indifferentiation, which uncouple a model from

any support, introduce their own share of both ontogenetic and

phylogenetic difference. It is in this phase of passage to a dia

grammatic state, a disincarnate abstract machine, that the "supplements of the soul" of the machinic node are distin

guished from simple material agglomerates. A heap of stones is

not a machine, whereas a wall is already a static proto

machine, manifesting virtual polarities, an inside and outside,

an above and below, a right and left ... These diagrammatic vir

tualities take us beyond Varela's characterisation of machinic

autopoiesis as unitary individuation, with neither input nor

output; they direct us towards a more collective machinism

without delimited unity, whose autonomy accommodates

diverse mediums of alterity. The reproducibility of the technical

machine differs from that of living beings, in that it is not based

on sequential codes perfectly circumscribed in a territorialised

genome. Obviously every technological machine has its own

plans for conception and assembly. But while these plans keep

their distance from the machine, they also move from one

machine to another so as to constitute a diagrammatic rhizome

which tends to cover the mecanosphere globally. The relations

of technological machines between themselves, and the way

their respective parts fit together, presuppose a formal serialisa

tion and a certain perdition of their singularity - stronger

than that of living machines - correlative to a distance

between the machine manifested in energetico-spatio-temporal

coordinates and the diagrammatic machine which develops in

more deterritorialised coordinates.


Machinic heterogenesis 43

This deterritorialising distance and loss of singularity needs to be related to a reciprocal smoothing of the materials constitu

tive of the technical machine. Of course, singular rough patch

es belonging to these materials can never be completely abol ished but they must only interfere with the machine's "play" if

they are required to do so by its diagrammatic functioning. Let

us examine these two aspects of machinic separation and

smoothing, taking an apparently simple machinic apparatus - the couple formed by a lock and i�s key. Two types of form, with

ontologically heterogeneous textures are at work here: 1)

materialised, contingent, concrete and discrete forms, whose


singularity is closed in on itself, embodied respectively in the

profile Fl of the lock and by the profile Pk of the key. Fl and Pk

never quite coincide. They evolve through time, due to wear

and oxidation, but both forms must stay within the framework of a separation-type limit beyond which the key would cease to

be operational; 2) "formal," diagrammatic forms, subsumed within this separation-type, which appear as a continuum

including the whole range of profiles Fl, Pk, compatible with the effective operation of the lock.

One quickly notices that the machinic effect, the passage to

the possible act, is entirely concerned with the second type of

form. Although ranged across the most restrained separation type limit possible, these diagrammatic forms appear infinite in

number. In fact, it is a matter of an integral of forms Pk, Fl.

This infinite integral form doubles and smooths the contin gent forms Fl and Pk which only have value machinically inas

much as they belong to it. A bridge is thus established "above" the concrete, authorised forms. I call this operation deterritori

alised smoothing and it applies as much to the normalisation of

the machine's constitutive materials as it does to their "digital"

and functional description. Ferric ore which has been insuffi

ciently worked, or deterritorialised, retains irregularities from


44 Chaosmosis

the milling of the original material, which would distort the

ideal profiles of the lock and key. The smoothing of the material has to remove excessive aspects of contingence from it, and

make it behave in a way that accurately moulds the formal

imprints extrinsic to it. We should add that this moulding - in a way comparable to photography- should not be too evanes

cent and should conserve a properly sufficient consistency.

Here again we find a separation-type phenomenon, putting

into play a theoretical diagrammatic consistency. A lead or

golden key risks bending in a steel lock. A key that is changed

into a liquid or gaseous state immediately loses its pragmatic

efficiency and departs from the field of the technical machine.

This phenomenon of a formal threshold can be found at all

levels of intra- or inter-machine relations, and in particular

with the existence of spare parts. The components of the tech

nical machine are thus like the units of a currency, and this has

become more evident since computers started to be used in

their conception and design. These machinic forms, these smoothings of material, of a separation-type limit between

parts and their functional adjustments, would suggest that

form takes precedence over consistency and over material sin

gularities - the technological machine's reproducibility

appearing to dictate that each of its elements fit into a pre

established definition of a diagrammatic order. Charles Sanders

Peirce, who described the diagram as an "icon of relation" and assimilated it to the function of algorithms, proposed a broader
vision that is worth developing further in the present perspec

tive. Here, the diagram is conceived as an autopoietic machine which not only gives it a functional and material consistency,

but requires it to deploy its diverse registers of alterity, freeing it from an identity locked into simple structural relations. The

machine's proto-subjectivity installs itself in Universes of virtu

ality which extend far beyond its existential territoriality. Thus


Machinic heterogenesis 45

we refuse to postulate a formal subjectivity intrinsic to dia

grammatic semiotisation, for example, a subjectivity "lodged"

in signifying chains according to the well-known Lacanian

principle: "a signifier represents the subject for another signifi

er." For the machine's diverse registers, there is no univocal

subjectivity based on cut, lack or suture, but there are ontologi

cally heterogeneous modes of subjectivity, constellations of

incorporeal Universes of reference which take the position of

partial enunciators in multiple domains of alterity, or more pre

cisely, domains of alterification.

We have already encountered a certain number of these

registers of machinic alterity:

- the alterity of proximity between different machines and

between different parts of the same machine; - the alterity of an internal, material consistency;

- the alterity of formal. diagrammatic consistency;

- the alterity of the evolutionary phylum; - the agonistic alterity between machines of war, whose pro-

longation we could associate with the "auto-agonistic" alterity

of desiring machines which tend towards their own collapsus

and abolition.

Another form of alterity which has only been approached

very indirectly, is the alterity of scale, or fractal alterity, which

establishes a play of systematic correspondences between

machines at different levels. 4 We are not, however, in the

process of drawing up a universal table of forms of machinic

alterity because, in truth, their ontological modalities are infinite.

They organise themselves into constellations of incorporeal

Universes ofreference with unlimited combinatories and creativity.

Archaic societies are better equipped than White, male, capital

istic subjectivities to produce a cartography of this multiva

lence of alterity. With regard to this, we could refer to Marc


46 Chaosmosis

Auge's account of the heterogeneous registers relating to the fetish object Legba in African societies of the Fon. The Legba
comes to being transversally in:

- a dimension of destiny;

- a universe of vital principle;

- an ancestral filiation;

- a materialised god;

- a sign of appropriation;

- an entity of individuation;

- a fetish at the entrance to the village, another at the portal of

the house and, after initiation, at the entrance to the bedroom ...

The Legba is a handful of sand, a receptacle, but it's also the

expression of a relation to others. One finds it at the door, at the

market, in the village square, at crossroads. It can transmit

messages, questions, answers. It is also a way of relating to the

dead and to ancestors. It is both an individual and a class of

individuals; a name and a noun. "Its existence corresponds to

the obvious fact that the social is not simply of a relational

order but of the order of being." 5 Marc Auge stresses the impos

sible transparency and translatability of symbolic systems. "The Legba apparatus [ ... ] is constructed on two axes. One is

viewed from the exterior to the interior, the other from identity

to alterity. Thus being, identity and the relation to the other are

constructed, through fetishistic practice, not only on a symbol

ic basis but also in an openly ontological way. "6

Contemporary machinic assemblages have even less stan

dard univocal referent than the subjectivity of archaic societies. But we are far less accustomed to the irreducible heterogeneity,

or even the heterogenetic character, of their referential compo

nents. Capital, Energy, Information, the Signifier are so many

categories which would have us believe in the ontological

homogeneity of referents (biological, ethological, economic,

phonological, scriptural, musical, etc.)


Machinic heterogenesis 47

In the context of a reductionist modernity, it is up to us to redis

cover that for every promotion of a machinic intersection there

corresponds a specific constellation of Universes of value from

the moment a partial non-human enunciation has been insti

tuted. Biological machines promote living Universes which dif

ferentiate themselves into vegetable becomings, animal becom

ings. Musical machines establish themselves against a back ground of sonorous Universes which have been constantly

modified since the great polyphonic mutation. Technical

machines install themselves at the intersection of the most


complex and heterogeneous enunciative components.

Heidegger, who turned the world of technology into a kind of

malefic destiny resulting from a movement of distancing from

being, used the example of a commercial plane on a runway:

the visible object conceals "what and how it is." It unveils itself

"only as standing-reserve inasmuch as it is ordered to insure

the possibility of transportation" and to this end, "it must be in

its whole structure and in every one of its constituent parts on

call for duty, i.e., ready for take-off'. 7 This interpellation, this

"ordering" which reveals the real as "standing-reserve" is

essentially operated by man and understood in terms of a uni

versal operation, travelling, flying ... But does this "standing

reserve" of the machine really reside in an already-there, in

terms of eternal truths, revealed to the being of man? In fact the

machine speaks to the machine before speaking to man and the

ontological domains that it reveals and secretes are, on each

occasion, singular and precarious.

Let us reconsider the example of a commercial plane, this

time not generically but using the technologically dated model

baptised as the Concorde. The ontological consistency of this

object is essentially composite; it is at the intersection, at the

point of constellation and pathic agglomeration of Universes

each of which have their own ontological consistency, traits of


48 Chaosmosis

intensity, their ordinates and coordinates, their specific

machinisms. Concorde simultaneously involves: - a diagrammatic Universe with plans of theoretical "feasibility";

- technological Universes transposing this "feasibility" into

material terms;

- industrial Universes capable of effectively producing it;

- collective imaginary Universes corresponding to a desire suf-

ficient to make it see the light of day;

- political and economic Universes leading, amongst other things, to the release of credit for its construction ...

But the bottom line is that the ensemble of these final, mater

ial, formal and efficient causes will not do the job! The Concorde

object moves effectively between Paris and New York but remains nailed to the economic ground. This lack of consistency of one of its components has
decisively fragilised its global onto

logical consistency. Concorde only exists within the limited

reproducibility of twelve examples and at the root of a possibilist

phylum of future supersonics. And this is hardly negligible!

Why are we so insistent about the impossibility of establish


ing the general translatability of diverse referential and partial

enunciative components of assemblage? Why this lack of rever

ence towards the Lacanian conception of the signifier?

Precisely because this theorising which stems from structural

linguistics forbids us from entering the real world of the

machine. The structuralist signifier is always synonymous with

linear discursivity. From one symbol to another, the subjective effect happens without any other ontological guarantee. As

opposed to this, heterogeneous machines, as envisaged from our schizonanalytical perspective, do not produce a standard

being at the mercy of a universal temporalisation. To clarify this point we should establish some distinctions between the

different forms of semiological, semiotic and coded linearity: - the codings of the "natural" world, which operate on several
Machinic heterogenesis 49

spatial dimensions (for example those of crystallography) and

which do not imply the extraction of autonomised operators of coding;

- the relative linearity of biological codings, for example, the

double helix of DNA which, starting from four basic chemical

radicals, develops equally in three dimensions;

- the linearity of pre-signifying semiologies, which develop on

relatively autonomous, parallel lines, even ifthe phonological

chains of spoken language appear to always overcode all the

others;

- the semiological linearity of the structural signifier which

imposes itself despotically over all the other modes of semiotisa

tion, expropriates them and even tends to make them disappear

within the framework of a communicational economy domi nated by informatics (please note: informatics in its current

state, since this state of things is in no way definitive);

- the superlinearity of a-signifying substances of expression,

where the signifier loses its despotism. The informational lines

of hypertexts can recover a certain dynamic polymorphism and

work in direct contact with referent Universes which are in no

way linear and, what is more, tend to escape a logic of spa

tialised sets.

The indicative matter of a-signifying semiotic machines is con

stituted by "point-signs"; these on one hand belong to a semi

otic order and on the other intervene directly in a series of material machinic processes. Example: a credit card number

which triggers the operation of a bank auto-teller. The a-signi fying semiotic figures don't simply secrete significations. They

give out stop and start orders but above all activate the "bring

ing into being" of ontological Universes. Consider for a moment

the example of the pentatonic musical refrain which, with only


a few notes, catalyses the Debussyst constellation of multiple
50 Chaosmosis

Universes: - the Wagnerian Universe surrounding Parsifal, which

attaches itself to the existential Territory constituted by

Bayreuth;

- the Universe of Gregorian chant; -that of French music, with the return to favour of Rameau

and Couperin; -that of Chopin, due to a nationalist transposition (Ravel, for

his part, appropriating Liszt);

- the Javanese music Debussy discovered at the Universal Exposition of 18 8 9;

- the world of Manet and Mallarme, which is associated with Debussy's stay at the Villa Medicis.

It would be appropriate to add to these past and present

influences the prospective resonances which constituted the

reinvention of polyphony from the time of the Ars Nova, its

repercussions on the French musical phylum of Ravel, Duparc,

Messiaen, etc., and on the sonorous mutation triggered by

Stravinsky, his presence in the work of Proust ...

We can clearly see that there is no bi-univocal correspon

dence between linear signifying links or archi-writing, depend

ing on the author, and this multireferential, multidimensional

machinic catalysis. The symmetry of scale, the transversality,

the pathic non-discursive character of their expansion: all these

dimensions remove us from the logic of the excluded middle

and reinforce us in our dismissal of the ontological binarism we

criticised previously. A machinic assemblage, through its

diverse components, extracts its consistency by crossing onto

logical thresholds, non-linear thresholds of irreversibility, onto

logical and phylogenetic thresholds, creative thresholds of het

erogenesis and autopoiesis. The notion of scale needs to be

expanded to consider fractal symmetries in ontological terms.

What fractal machines traverse are substantial scales. They


Machinic heterogenesis 51

traverse them in engendering them. But, and this should be

noted, the existential ordinates that they "invent" were always already there. How can this paradox be sustained? It's because

everything becomes possible (including the recessive smooth

ing of time, evoked by Rene Thom) the moment one allows the

assemblage to escape from energetico-spatio-temporal coordi

nates. And, here again, we need to rediscover a manner of

being of Being - before, after, here and everywhere else -

without being, however, identical to itself; a processual, poly


phonic Being singularisable by infinitely complexifiable tex

tures, according to the infinite speeds which animate its virtual

compositions.

The ontological relativity advocated here is inseparable from an enunciative relativity. Knowledge of a Universe (in an astro

physical or axiological sense) is only possible through the medi

ation of autopoietic machines. A zone of self-belonging needs to

exist somewhere for the coming into cognitive existence of any

being or any modality of being. Outside of this

machine/Universe coupling, beings only have the pure status

of a virtual entity. And it is the same for their enunciative coor

dinates. The biosphere and mecanosphere, coupled on this

planet, focus a point of view of space, time and energy. They

trace an angle of the constitution of our galaxy. Outside of this

particularised point of view, the rest of the Universe exists (in

the sense that we understand existence here-below) only

through the virtual existence of other autopoietic machines at

the heart of other bio-mecanospheres scattered throughout the

cosmos. The relativity of points of view of space, time and ener gy do not, for all that, absorb the real into the dream. The cate

gory of Time dissolves in cosmological reflections on the Big

Bang even as the category of irreversibility is affirmed. Residual

objectivity is what resists scanning by the infinite variation of


52 Chaosmosis

points of view constitutable upon it. Imagine an autopoietic

entity whose particles are constructed from galaxies. Or, con

versely, a cognitivity constituted on the scale of quarks. A dif

ferent panorama, another ontological consistency. The

mecanosphere draws out and actualises configurations which

exist amongst an infinity of others in fields of virtuality.

Existential machines are at the same level as being in its intrin

sic multiplicity. They are not mediated by transcendent signi

fiers and subsumed by a univocal ontological foundation. They

are to themselves their own material of semiotic expression.

Existence, as a process of deterritorialisation, is a specific inter

machinic operation which superimposes itself on the promo

tion of singularised existential intensities. And, I repeat, there is

no generalised syntax for these deterritorialisations. Existence

is not dialectical, not representable. It is hardly livable!

Desiring machines which break with the great interpersonal


and social organic equilibria, which invert orders, play the role

of the other as against a politics of auto-centering on the self.

For example, the partial drives and perverse polymorphic

investments of psychoanlysis don't constitute an exceptional and deviant race of machines. All machinic assemblages har

bour - even if in an embryonic state - enunciative zones

which are so many desiring proto-machines. To clarify this

point we need to extend our transmachinic bridge and under

stand the smoothing of the ontological texture of machinic

material and diagrammatic feedbacks as so many dimensions

of intensification that take us beyond the linear causalities of

the capitalistic apprehension of machinic Universes. We also

need to abandon logics based on the principles of the excluded

middle and sufficient reason. Through this smoothing there

appears a being beyond, a being-for-the-other which gives con

sistency to an existent beyond its strict delimitation, here and


Machinic heterogenesis 53

now. The machine is always synonymous with a nucleus con

stitutive of an existential Territory against a background of a

constellation of incorporeal Universes of reference (or value).

The "mechanism" of this turning around of being consists in

the fact that some of the machine's discursive segments do not

only play a functional or signifying role, but assume the exis

tentialising function of pure intensive repetition that I have

called the refrain function. The smoothing is like an ontological

refrain, and thus, far from apprehending a univocal truth of

being through techne - as Heideggerian ontology would have

it - it is a plurality of beings as machines which give them

selves to us the moment we acquire the pathic and cartograph

ic means of reaching them. The manifestations - not of Being,

but of multitudes of ontological components - are of the order

of the machine. And this, without semiological mediation,

without transcendent coding, directly as "being's giving of

itself," as giving. Acceding to such a "giving" is already to par ticipate ontologically in it as a full right. The term right does

not occur here by chance, since at this proto-ontological level it

is already necessary to affirm a proto-ethical dimension. The

play of intensity of the ontological constellation is, in a way, a

choice of being not only for self, but for the whole alterity of the

cosmos and for the infinity of times.

If there's choice and freedom at certain "superior" anthropo


logical stages, it's because we will also find them at the most

elementary strata of machinic concatenations. But the notions

of elements and complexity are susceptible here to being brutal

ly inverted. Those that are most differentiated and undifferenti ated coexist within the same chaos which, at infinite speed,

plays its virtual registers - one against the other and one with the other. The machinic-technical world, at the "terminal" of

which present-day humanity structures itself, is barricaded by


54 Chaosmosis

horizons of constants and the limitation of the infinite velocities

of chaos (the speed of light, the cosmological horizon of the Big

Bang, Planck's constant and the elementary quantum of action

in quantum physics, the impossibility of going below absolute

zero ... ). But, this very same world of semiotic constraints is doubled, tripled and infinitised by other worlds which under

certain conditions seek only to bifurcate out of their Universes

ofvirtuality and engender new fields of the possible.

Just as scientific machines constantly modify our cosmic frontiers, so do the machines of desire and aesthetic creation.

As such, they hold an eminent place within assemblages of

subjectivation, themselves called to relieve our old social

machines which are incapable of keeping up with the effiores

cence ofmachinic revolutions that shatter our epoch.

Rather than adopting a reticent attitude with respect to the

immense machinic revolution sweeping the planet (at the risk

of destroying it) or of clinging onto traditional systems of value

- with the pretence of re-establishing transcendence - the movement of progress, or if one prefers, the movement of

process, will endeavour to reconcile values and machines.

Values are immanent to machines. The life of machinic Fluxes

is not only manifested through cybernetic feedback; it is also

correlative to a promotion of incorporeal Universes stemming from an enunciative Territorial incarnation, from a valorising

consciousness of being. Machinic autopoiesis asserts itself as a

non-human for-itself through zones of partial proto-subjectiva

tion and it deploys a for-others under the double modality of a

"horizontal" eco-systemic alterity (the machinic systems posi

tion themselves in a rhizome of reciprocal dependence) and

phylogenetic alterity (situating each actual machinic stasis at

the conjunction of a passeist filiation and a Phylum of future

mutations). All systems of value - religious, aesthetic, scientif

ic, ecosophic ... - install themselves at this machinic interface


Machinic heterogenesis 55

between the necessary actual and the possibilist virtual. Thus

Universes of value constitute incorporeal enunciators of


abstract machinic complexions compossible with discursive

realities. ,The consistency of these zones of proto-subjectivation

is then only assured inasmuch as they are embodied, with more

or less intensity, in nodes of finitude, Territories of chaosmic

grasping, which guarantee, moreover, their possible recharg

ing with processual complexity. Thus a double enunciation:

finite, territorialised and incorporeal, infinite.

Nevertheless, these constellations of Universes of value do

not constitute Universals. The fact that they are tied into singu

lar existential Territories effectively confers upon them a power of heterogenesis, that is, of opening onto singularising, irre

versible processes of necessary differentiation. How does this

machinic heterogenesis, which differentiates each colour of

being - which makes, for example, from the plane of consis

tency of a philosophical concept a world quite different from the

plane of reference of the scientific function or the plane of aes

thetic composition - end up being reduced to the capitalistic

homogenesis of generalised equivalence, which leads to all val ues being valued by the same thing, all appropriative territories

being related to the same economic instrument of power, and

all existential riches succumbing to clutches of exchange value? The sterile opposition between use value and exchange

value will here be relinquished in favour of an axiological com

plexion including all the machinic modalities of valorisation:

the values of desire, aesthetic values, ecological, economic val

ues ... Capitalistic value which generally subsumes the ensem

ble of these machinic surplus values, proceeds with a reterrito

rialising attack, based on the primacy of economic and mone

tary semiotics, and corresponds to a sort of general implosion of

all existential Territories. In fact, capitalistic value is neither

separate nor tangential to systems ofvalorisation; it constitutes


56 Cha osmosis

their deathly heart, corresponding to the crossing of the ineffa

ble limit between a controlled, chaosmic deterritorialisation -

under the aegis of social, aesthetic and analytical practices -

and a vertiginous collapse into the black hole of the aleatory,

understood as a paroxysmically binary reference, implacably

dissolving the whole consistency of Universes of value which

would claim to escape capitalistic law. It is thus only abusively

that one could put economic determinations in a primary posi

tion with respect to social relations and productions of subjec

tivity. Economic law, like juridical law, must be deducted from


the ensemble of Universes of value, for whose collapse it contin

ually strives. Its reconstruction, from the scattered debris of

planned economies and neo-liberalism and according to new

ethico-political finalities (ecosophy) calls for, in contradistinc

tion, an untiring renewal of the consistency of machinic assem

blages ofvalorisation.

1 Norbert Wiener, Cybernetics, or, Control and communication in the

animal and the machine, Technology Press, Cambridge, Mass.,

1948.

2 Cf. Pierre Levy, Les Technologies de l'intelligence, La Decouverte,

Paris, 1 990, Plissefractal. Ideographie dynamique (memoire d'habili

tation a diriger des recherches en sciences de !'information et de la

communication) et L 'ideographie dynamique, La Decouverte, Paris,

1 9 91 .

3 F. Varela op. cit.

4 Leibniz, in his concern to render homogeneous the infinitely large

and the infinitely small, thought that the living machine, which he

assimilated to a divine machine, continued to be a machine in its

smallest parts until infinity (which would not be the case with a

machine made by the art of men), in Monadologie, pp. 1 78-9,

Delagrave, Paris, 1962.

5 M. Auge, "Le fetiche et son obj et" in L'Objet en psychanalyse, pre

sented by Maud Mannoni, Denae!, "L' espace analytique," Paris,

1986.
Machinic heterogenesis 7 Martin Heidegger, Basic Writings, edited by David Farrell Krell,

Harper, San Francisco, 19 77, p.298.


57
6 Ibid.

3 Schizoanalytic metamodelisation

Psychoanalysis is in crisis; it is bogged down in routine prac

tices and ossified conceptions. Social movements are also at an

impasse due to the collapse of communist regimes and the con

version of social-democrats to liberalism. In each case, individ

ual and collective subjectivity lack modelisation. And it is quite

obvious that neither Freudianism, even when revisited by

structuralism, nor Freudo-Marxism, have anything worth


while to offer at this level. In fact, an immense site of theoretical

recomposition and invention of new practices has opened up. I

have tried to show that questioning subjectivity's foundation

on personological Universals, structural mathemes, biological

or economic infrastructures, involves a redefinition of machin

ism. From now on the machine will be conceived in opposition to structure, the latter being associated with a feeling of eterni

ty and the former with an awareness of finitude, precarious

ness, destruction and death.

Beneath the diversity of beings, no uni vocal ontological

plinth is given, rather there is a plane of machinic interfaces.

Being crystallises through an infinity of enunciative assem

blages associating actualised, discursive components (material


Schizoanalytic metamodelisation 59

and indicative Fluxes, machinic Phylums) with non-discursive,

virtual components (incorporeal Universes and existential

Territories). Thus the singular points of view on being, with

their precariousness, uncertainty and creative aspects take

precedence over the fixity of structures so distinctive of univer salist visions. In order to establish an intensive bridge between

these actual and virtual functions we are inclined to postulate

the existence of a deterministic chaos animated by infinite

velocities. It is out of this chaos that complex compositions,

which are capable of being slowed down in energetico-spatio

temporal coordinates or category systems, constitute them

selves.

Rather than beginning with automatic systems of articula

tion between a plane of Expression and a plane of Content, we

will stress the partial operators of their assemblage. For exam ple, the mechanical aspect of the linguistic double articulation

between signifying, monemic unities and non-signifying,

phonemic unities will be replaced by abstract machines which

traverse these two heterogeneous registers and are capable of

bifurcation and the production of new associations. It is not

evident that Universes of value function in concert with semi

otic machines, or that semiotic machines combine with con

crete machines, that existential Territories cut out points of

view on the world .... By making assemblages of enunciation

open, chaotically determined, the concatenation of the four

ontological functions of Universe, machinic Phylum, Flux and

Territory, preserve their pragmatic processuality. The struc

turalist mode wanted to bracket out the problematics of the sig


nified, the icon, the Imago and the imaginary, to the advantage

of syntagmatic articulations. Attention was focused on interac

tional, structural mechanics, which supposedly animated the

phenomenal landscape. Thus the points of ontological crystalli

sation emerging from this landscape were lost from sight. The
60 Chaosmosis
phonological. gestural, spatial, musical...discursivities, all annexed by the same signifying economy, had to have absolute
control over the contents they were supposed to divide into dis
crete paradigmatic figures. But what gives consistency to these
discursive systems, what authorises the erection of enunciative
monads should be sought on the side of Content; that is, on the
side of this existential function which, taking support from cer
tain discursive links, diverts them from their signifying, denota
tional and propositional incidences, making them play the role
of a refrain of ontological affirmation.
The assemblage of the four ontological functions.
Expression Content actual virtual enunciative nuclei (discursive) (non-discursive)
U incorporeal
possible <I> machinic discursivity
=
=

complexity
F energetico-spatio- T chaosmic
real = =

temporal discursivity incarnation


The functions F, <I>, T, U have the task of conferring a dia
grammatic, conceptual status (pragmatic cartography) on the virtual enunciative nuclei stuck within manifest Expression.
Their matricial concatenation should preserve, as much as pos sible, their radical heterogeneity, which can only be sensed
through a discursive, phenomenological approach. They are
described here as metamodelisers to indicate that their primary
purpose is to take account of the way in which the diverse
existing systems ofmodelisation (religious, metaphysical, scien
tific, psychoanalytic, animistic, neurotic ... ) nearly always skirt
around the problem of self-referential enunciation. Schizo analysis
Schizoanalytic metamodelisation 61

does not thus choose one modelisation to the exclusion of

another. Within the diverse cartographies in action in a given

situation, it tries to make nuclei of virtual autopoiesis dis

cernible, in order to actualise them, by transversalising them,

in conferring on them an operative diagrammatism (for exam

ple, by a change in the material ofExpression), in making them

themselves operative within modified assemblages, more open,

more processual, more deterritorialised. Schizoanalysis, rather

than moving in the direction of reductionist modelisations

which simplify the complex, will work towards its complexifica

tion, its processual enrichment, towards the consistency of its

virtual lines of bifurcation and differentiation, in short towards

its ontological heterogeneity.

The location of nuclei of partial life, of that which can give an

enunciative consistency to phenomenal multiplicities, is not a matter of a pure objective description. A monad's knowledge of

being-in-the-world, of a sphere of for-itself, implies a pathic


apprehension which escapes energetico-spatio-temporal coor

dinates. Knowledge here is first of all existential transference,

non-discursive transitivism. The enunciation of this transfer

ence always occurs through the diversion of a narration whose

primary function is not to engender a rational explanation but

to promote complex refrains, supports of an intensive, memori

al persistence and an event-centred consistency. It is only

through mythical narratives (religious, fantasmatic, etc.) that

the existential function accedes to discourse. But this discourse

is not a simple epiphenomenon; it is the stake of ethico-political

strategies of avoidance of enunciation. The four ontological

functions, like safety barriers or warning lights, have the task

of making visible the stakes of these strategies.

For example, the incorporeal Universes of classical Antiquity which were associated with a polytheistic compro-
62 Cha osmosis

mise relating to a multitude of clanic and ethnic Territorialities,

underwent a radical reshaping with the trinitary revolution of

Christianity, indexed on the refrain of the sign of the cross,

which will recentre not only the ensemble of social, existential

Territories, but also the corporeal, mental, familial assem

blages, on the unique existential Territory of Christie incarna

tion and crucifixion. This extraordinary attack of subjective

subjection obviously goes far beyond purely theological consid

erations! The new subjectivity of guilt, contrition, body mark

ings and sexuality, of redemptive mediation, is also an essential

piece of the new social apparatuses, the new machines of sub jection which had to construct themselves from the debris of

the late Roman Empire and the reterritorialisations of feudal

and urban orders yet to come.

Closer to us, the mythico-conceptual narrative of

Freudianism has effected a reshaping of the four ontological

quadrants. A whole dynamic and topical machinery of repres sion governs the economy of the Fluxes of the libido; while a

zone of enunciative nuclei (that the clinical approach had bypassed) - of an oneiric, sexual, neurotic and infantile order

relating to the lapsus and jokes - invades the right hand side

of our picture. The Unconscious presented as a universe ofnon

contradiction, of the heterogenesis of opposites, envelops the

manifest Territories of the symptom, whose tendency towards

autonomisation, autopoietic, pathic and pathogenic repetition

threatens the unity of the self. And this will reveal itself more

over during the history of the analytical clinic to be increasing


ly precarious, indeed fractalised. Freudian cartography is not

only descriptive; it is inseparable from the pragmatics of trans

ference and interpretation. In any event, I would argue that it

should be disengaged from a significational perspective and

understood as a conversion of expressive means and as a muta

tion of ontological textures releasing new lines of the possible


Schizoanalytic metamodelisation 63

- and this from the simple fact of putting into place new

assemblages of listening and modelisation. The dream, as an

object ofrenewed interest, recounted as a story concealing keys

to the Unconscious, put through the screen of free association,

undergoes a profound mutation. Just as after the revolution of

the Ars Nova in Fourteenth Century Italy music will no longer

be heard in the same way within the European cultural atmos

phere, so too the nature of the dream and oneiric activity will

intrinsically change within their new referential assemblage. And, at the same time, a multitude of psychopathological

refrains will no longer be lived, and consequently modelised, in the same way. And the obsessive who washes his hands a hun

dred times a day exacerbates his solitary anguish within the

context of a profoundly modified Universe of reference.

With the invention of the analytic apparatus, Freudian modeli

sation brought about a clear enrichment in the production of

subjectivity, an enlargement of its referential constellations, a

new pragmatic opening. But it quickly encountered limits with

its familial and universalising conceptions, with its stereotyped

practice of interpretation, but above all with its inability to go

beyond linguistic semiology. While psychoanalysis conceptu

alises psychosis through its vision of neurosis, schizoanalysis

approaches all modalities of subjectivation in light of the mode

of being in the world of psychosis. Because nowhere more than

here is the ordinary modelisation of everyday existence so

denuded; the "axioms of daily life" stand in the way of the a-sig

nifying function, the degree zero of all possible modelisation. With neurosis, symptomatic matter continues to bathe in the

environment of dominant significations while with psychosis the world of standardised Dasein loses its consistency. Alterity,

as such, becomes the primary question. For example, what

finds itself fragilised, cracked up, schizzed, in delire or halluci-


64 Chaosmosis

nating when confronted with the status of the objective world,

is the point of view of the other in me, the recognised body in


articulation with the lived body and the felt body; these are the

normalised coordinates of alterity which give their foundation to sensible evidence.

Psychosis is not a structural object but a concept; it is not

an irremovable essence but a machination which always starts

up again during any encounter with the one who will become,

after the event, the psychotic. Thus here the concept is not an

entity closed in on itself, but the abstract, machinic incarnation

of alterity at the point of extreme precariousness; it is the indeli

ble mark that everything in this world can break down at any

time. The Unconscious is intimately connected with the con

cept: it too is an incorporeal construction which takes posses

sion of subjectivity at the point of its emergence. But it is a con

cept which at every moment risks becoming clogged up, and which must be constantly cleared of the cultural scoria which

threatens to reterritorialise it. It requires reactivating, rnachinic

recharging, due to the virulence of events which set subjectivi

ty into action. The schizo fracture is the royal road of access to

the emergent fractality of the Unconscious. What could be

called the schizo reduction goes beyond all the eidetic reduc

tions of phenomenology - it leads to an encounter with the a

signifying refrains which give back to the narrative, which recast in artifice, existential narrativity and alterity, albeit

delirious ones. Note the curious chasse-croise between psycho analysis and phenomenology: while the first essentially lacked

psychotic alterity (in particular, because of its reifying concep

tions about identification and its incapacity to think intensive becomings), the second, although having produced the best

descriptions of psychosis, did not know how to bring to light, through it, the foundational role of narrative modelisation, the

medium for the uncircumventable existential function of the

You might also like