The Language of Typology
The Language of Typology
The Language of Typology
arq (2019), 23.2, 149–156. © Cambridge University Press 2019 theory arq . vol 23 . no 2 . 2019 149
doi: 10.1017/S1359135519000198
The concept of typology has recurred in A precedent is a single instance or isolated example in
architectural discourse since the term’s conception contrast to a type, which is a non-physical entity, or a
in the early nineteenth century. To describe an typology, which refers to the means of categorising.
architectural object usually involves an act of Acknowledging that any given architectural
typifying; a generalisation of built form to common singularity has some common characteristics with
characteristics. Both the analysis of architecture and another and its situational nature makes it unique,
its creation require this abstraction, which offers identifying its type provides a way of connecting the
the potential to form types and expose initially particular to the universal.
unapparent relationships. Typology’s Type’s relationship to practice is complicated
Enlightenment origins sought to link architecture further by the ill-defined nature of the process of
to a natural order, but its terminology has design. Design methods, design methodology, and design
subsequently been adopted in modernist rejections thinking have all been used to describe the specific
of mass culture and Neo-Rationalist pursuits of processes that designers go through in the creation
continua and meaning. Despite widespread use of the of new artefacts. This evolving field encompasses
term, the role typology plays in the process of design diverse approaches such as deterministic processes,
remains unclear. Attempts to link its academic reflective practice, and heuristic methods. Of the
origins to the creation of architectural form multiple attempts to classify these cognitive
(notably by Gottfried Semper in the nineteenth processes, Designerly Ways of Knowing, introduced by
3
century, and Guilio Carlo Argan and Aldo Rossi in Nigel Cross, and its more recent incarnation as
the twentieth century) have done little to synthesise Design Thinking, bears remarkable similarities with
the two and merely succeeded in alienating it the paradoxical relationship between the particular
from practice. and the universal embodied by typology. Design
While theorists of type have debated its origins, Thinking, as described by Kees Dorst, utilises a mode
4
the use of the term in practice has often been of logical operation known as abduction. In contrast
reduced to naive functional approximations that to deduction and induction, abduction involves the
represent little in common other than a similarity generation of concrete reality from a set of general
of use. This oversimplification was legitimised in principles and specific values. It is this relationship
Nikolaus Pevsner’s A History of Building Types in which that lies at the core of both typological design and
buildings were categorised and arranged from ‘the design thinking. As this article will set out, type
most monumental to the least monumental, from formation is a necessary component of design
the most ideal to the most utilitarian, from national production.
1
monuments to factories’. Yet Pevsner exposes the Although the formal study of typology has only
challenge of this categorisation, firstly through the been apparent in architectural theory since the
5
almost unmanageable number of types a enlightenment, this notional historical genesis
comprehensive catalogue would need to contain, undermines the all-encompassing nature of
and secondly, the seemingly endless appearance of typological thought that has permeated architecture
novel functional requirements. since antiquity. The establishment of architecture as
Pevsner inadvertently raises the problem of an autonomous field in which architectural form
terminology and the ambiguity of type. Indeed, acquires specific definition necessitates type
typology and type are often used interchangeably yet formation, yet its use as a means of interpreting and
6
they represent distinct concepts. The former refers structuring the process of design has been limited.
to the system, the categorical structure or the means In part this may be due to a rejection of
2
of defining the field of the latter. The method of simultaneous typological concepts as well as the
categorisation may vary and that gives rise to embodiment of ideological stances that exclude
different typologies that may host a variety of types. multiple interpretive categorisation.
type through function, he isolated forms from their typology, implicitly placing design at its core.
archetypal meanings. Vidler draws from the work of the Neo-
Durand’s version of universality is one of model Rationalists, especially Aldo Rossi whose own
form. In his diagrammatic approach, rooms writings and works present a case for typological
supporting functions are mapped onto abstracted thinking. Like Quatremère, Rossi saw type as a
circulation structures. Durand assumed the city was principle prior to form, however he seeks not to
a static entity and accordingly does not account for uncover abstracted values, but those that have come
changing functional requirements. His work implies about through shared creation of the city. Rossi’s
a neutrality of form, yet it is the relationship types were empirically derived and focused on
between mass and space that embody archetypal reusing the urban form, which was seen as a
ideals underpinning our reading of the architecture. continuous morphology. Types emerged from built
This highlights the inherent problem associated structure as a product of social order rather than a
with the instrumentality of type. His diagrams direct result of primitive human conditions. He
struggle to escape the status of the model; they are considered type as being the very idea of architecture
indicative of form, failing to capture all the possible and that all theories of architecture were
20
spatial configurations. Whether deduced from typological. Any one type may manifest itself in any
function or abstracted spatial conditions, as soon as number of forms and all forms are reducible to type.
pen is put to paper, the type becomes a singularity, Rossi saw construction as the process through
undermining the multiplicity that the type which analysis could become concrete, elevating
embodies. If Quatremère presents an alienated type from a theoretical ideal. His built work
abstraction of type, Durand shows us an presents a tension between the general (type) and
instrumentalised yet limiting version of the concept. specific memory. He saw it as some kind of
21
Carlo Argan’s 1963 article ‘On the Typology of manifestation of fundamental being. In his early
Architecture’ marked the beginning of renewed career, Rossi’s application of type was both a
interest in the field and its relationship to the design conscious and scientific act initiated by deep
process. He sought to make a stage-based model of analysis of the city. The quest for objectivity led him
design (plan to structural system to surface to an architecture of primary forms and
treatment) analogous with, as he saw it, the three inextricably links type to the very determinism that
22
major classification systems of architecture Colquhoun is reacting to. Despite radically
(configuration, structure, and decorative different conceptions of typology, Rossi’s approach
16
elements). Argan’s rather mechanised and linear shares similarities with Gottfried Semper’s Doctrine
version of the design process nevertheless of Style, which suggested that fundamental types
recognises the interrelationship between were given form through the process of craft. It is in
typological thought and design creation. He the act of making, the application of available
believed that any project that had its demands technologies and materials, that type is given form
rooted in the past requires a critical development of and becomes an expression of base human
previous solutions embodied by its type. conditions. Rossi comes close to generating a more
Argan understood both the repetition and the complex vision. His work suggests a uniqueness of
ignorance of type to be unacceptable, however he type to cultural context and, by focusing on the
assumed the possibility of each. Six years later, Alan forms of the city as the lens through which to reveal
Colquhoun suggested architects could never be freed type, analytical study becomes a precursor to
from the forms of the past, thus to ignore typology is typological thought.
to lose control of the communicative power of
17
architecture. To Colquhoun, purely deterministic Design thinking
processes brought about by modernism and To limit typological thought to those protagonists
functionalism were inadequate and left a void in the that actively engaged with its terminology is to
design process, which ran the risk of being filled by undermine its pervasiveness in architectural
free expression, stripping architecture of its thinking. Design is a process of abstraction, whereby
meaning. potential reality is codified, manipulated and
This debasing of the modernist type was taken up restructured. Type utilisation may be a conscious
by Anthony Vidler in his article ‘The Third Typology’ action in which the designer selects a type
published in 1977, in which he articulates a appropriate to context and function that can convey
18
typological position that uses the city as its source. specific meaning, however, it may also be an
Unlike functionalism or theories of natural origins, unconscious act that arises in the creation of form.
he saw this typology as one founded in the autonomy Understanding the design process is key to
of urban form. This empirical typology had the realising the relationship between typological
capacity to embed ‘three levels of meaning’:
the first, inherited from the ascribed means of the past
existence of the forms; the second, derived from the
‘To limit typological thought to those
specific fragment and its boundaries, and often protagonists that actively engaged with its
crossing between previous types; the third, proposed by terminology is to undermine its
19
a recomposition of these fragments in a new context.
Vidler saw a need to reclaim a ‘critical role to public pervasiveness in architectural thinking.’
architecture’ through the vehicle of this new
thought and design. In the 1970s, interest in design but also to provide shape to the underlying values
theory gave rise to numerous cognitive models and formal possibilities. In the conjecture/analysis
describing its cognitive processes, in part due to a model of design, the project frame provides a
desire to apply scientific methodologies to design. framework for both the conjecture of new proposals
Herbert Simon’s Science of the Artificial, written in and the assessment of trial solutions.
1969, outlined a problem-solving theory of design in It is in the act of framing that the designer
which designs were considered problems that were confronts the paradox of the universal and specific.
23
first analysed and then solutions proposed. In
Simon’s model, any complex problem could be
broken down into consistently smaller ones that ‘The relationship between the underlying
could be tackled individually. It relied on the
assumption that design arose as a response to a
values of a design situation and the
particular need and could therefore be considered principles that govern formal creation
problematic. represent the inherent typological
Simon’s analysis/synthesis approach became
untenable in the light of research into the problems reasoning of design.’
designers actually face. Very few design problems
involve straightforward analysis of an issue followed
by the creation of a solution. More often than not, Through restructuring the design situation, general
design problems have undefined desired outcomes, principles are made synonymous with specific
the processes to produce solutions are unclear, and it aspirational value in order to form concrete reality.
is not apparent when a successful solution has been Donald Schön’s description of framing, written in
achieved. Horst Rittel and Melvin Webber described the early 1980s, describes a dialogue between a critic
such problems as wicked, requiring a whole new kind and a student in which they enter into a frame
24
of thinking. discourse, in this case ‘the spaghetti bowl’ versus ‘the
34
Alternatives to the problem-solving model arose, Renaissance order’. These seemingly
which embraced the heuristic approach of actual straightforward metaphors are the mechanisms not
designers including Donald Schön’s reflective only through which the design is created but which
25 26
practice, the hermeneutic models of Bill Hillier, also allow it to be analysed. As Dorst notes, the frame
and the participatory approaches described by Nigel actually embodies a complex set of statements that
27
Cross. Of considerable influence on the field was enable the desired value to be achieved through a
the restructuring of the scientific method embarked series of generic principles.
upon by Karl Popper, in which he questioned The relationship between the underlying values of
prevailing inductive methodologies in favour of one a design situation and the principles that govern
28
based around the concept of falsification. His formal creation represent the inherent typological
theory of Critical Rationalism outlined a conjecture/ reasoning of design. In whatever way a project is
analysis approach to scientific discovery in which framed, the designer is engaged in a form of type
scientists made informed guesses that they then creation, the identification of a transferable
attempted to prove false. Popper’s theory was metaphor that captures the potential for the
29
adapted to design, notably by Jane Darke, and creation of meaning. By implication, types are
30
Michael Brawne. Problematic in the application of infinite, personal, and arbitrary. In Schön’s design
Popperian science to design is the lack of formal studio, it is difficult not to engage in a discussion on
frameworks for assessing the success of a conjectured frame validity; this is the very mechanism through
solution. While in classical science, one is able to which the design is critiqued. The typological
make observations to attempt to validate hypotheses, question is not whether the spaghetti bowl is in itself
in design this is often not possible. Moreover, when a type, but rather, how valid is this type? Making
faced with wicked problems, it may not even be clear frames and types synonymous underpins the
when this has been achieved. In order to tackle this, relevancy of typology in the process of space
the designer is required to engage in design thinking, a creation. It has the potential to engender conjecture
mode of cognitive processing outside of the and structure critique of the design process.
traditional deductive/inductive dichotomy.
The first discussion of design thinking could be Type and language
attributed to Nigel Cross’s 1982 article ‘Designerly In a given design situation, adopting a type is
Ways of Knowing’, which set out the case for treating analogous to using a language in which that
31
design as an autonomous academic discipline. At building speaks, governed by a set of structural
the heart of Cross’s design thinking is the ability of rules; a grammar. A spoken language is expressed in
the designer to transform abstract patterns into utterances, each individual and potentially unique
concrete ones through the use of internalised codes constructs. In the structuralism of Ferdinand de
or the adoption of a language. This can be described Saussure, these parts are termed langue (the set of
as framing, a concept that has its roots in the social rules and codes that constitute a language) and
32 35
sciences. Framing involves synthesising the parole (a unique utterance). Similarly, an
aspirational values of a project with the principles architectural type may be considered in these terms;
33
that govern its formal creation. The designer the canon of built work within a type forms parole,
constructs a project frame in order to reveal a solution defined by principles particular to the desired
Furthermore, one must ask if the prison and arcade morphological principles runs into issues, as often
is the appropriate metaphor to frame the social they require radically new ways of dwelling to
conditions of civility. facilitate inhabitation. Steadman argues that types
follow ‘morphological trajectories’, an evolution of
Type formation form to shifting usage patterns. This moderate shift
The historical focus on the discovery of types, either in design principles echoes the evolutionary
through rational or empirical means, is called into versions of architectural history advanced by
question when framing design as a mode of Semper and Quatremère and questions the
typological thinking. The implications of project necessity, or even possibility, of generating totally
frame and type synthesis suggest that types are new formal conditions.
almost infinitely numerous. Indeed, new languages Despite this, the advance in building technologies
may be artificially created or evolve from existing draws into question the principles of formal
languages. Given the tripartite relationship between creation that have governed spatial form. To deny
archetypal conditions, morphological principles, historical influence in favour of either pseudo-
and type grammar, three distinct possibilities arise. determinism or total free will undermines the
First, the definition of new modes of being, second grammar that ties meaning to form. The built work
the creation of novel formal relationships, and third compromises its ability to carry value, as there is no
the reassigning of meaning to form. shared link between the work and its purpose. As
The creation of new archetypal conditions requires Colquhoun notes,
the architect to define new ways of dwelling. In the It would seem that we ought to accept a value system
history of typology, those dealing with fundamental which takes account of the forms and the solutions of
human conditions have sought to reveal these either the past, if we are to retain control over concepts which
through rationalism (Quatremère de Quincy, for will obtrude themselves into the creative process,
44
example) or through empirical study (exemplified by whether we are aware of it or not.
Rossi). Quatremère’s attempt to deconstruct To create a new grammar of type is to re-establish the
architectural history generates artificial relationship between meaning and form. Yet despite
anthropological states that have seemingly little attempts to do so, architects are rarely able to escape
relevance to contemporary meaning. Rossi’s broader underlying cultural forces that tie the two together.
attempt to uncover meaning through looking at pre- Overt attempts in postmodernism succeeded only in
existing form provides a more grounded approach to subverting the denotive properties of architecture
archetypal selection yet is limited by the possibilities and inevitably failed to restructure the underlying
of the city as a source of cultural legitimacy. archetype/morphology relationship. Indeed, as a
Archetypal conditions cannot be created but conscious act this involved the recognition of the
represent some fundamental act of being embodied existence of the initial type to allow the possibility of
by built work and revealed by the designer. subversion. Conversely, the complete ignorance or
Arguably the prototypical architecture of rejection of a grammar undermines the possibilities
modernism, itself a reaction to the vagaries of to consciously control the communicative
popular culture, was an attempt to herald new ways possibilities of a work.
of inhabitation, deriving new archetypal conditions Making design itself an act of typological
from mechanised production. Modernism’s overt reasoning suggests that types themselves are specific
departure from historicism allowed the invention of and unique, yet these are bound by the conditions of
41
type as a social and ideological tool. The reduction human experience and the possibilities of building.
of the individual to the typical justified repetitive To frame a design situation typologically involves
formal units. In a further departure from precedent, the creation of a unique type, one that embodies
functionalism promoted a causal relationship aspired value, morphological principles linked by a
between use and form. As Argan asserts, contextual grammar. The creativity of the designer
industrialisation gave rise to new functional is to draw specific conditions from the vast array of
requirements that previous building types were ill- human experience, to recognise contextual
equipped to deal with and to the emergence of new possibilities and to realise appropriate principles of
42
types. The failing of the modernist ‘type’ is the construction. In this formulation of type, the
assumed link between type and function, which is historical preoccupation with its origins is rejected
undermined both by the reappropriation of in favour of a pluralist approach in which type may
buildings and the variance of form between embody a rich array of meaning. Once the need
buildings of a similar function. for the absolute universality of type is disregarded,
The creation of new formal relationships and a far wider pool of human experience may be
strategies appears at first to be a distinct possibility drawn from.
in the creation of type. However, as Philip Steadman
points out, the generic functions of building (the
need for shelter, ventilation, light, technology, etc.) ‘In this formulation of type, the historical
have necessitated a relatively limited number of preoccupation with its origins is rejected in
43
formal arrangements. His analysis recognises
favour of a pluralist approach in which type
consistent formal strategies in a variety of building
functions due to these universal demands. While may embody a rich array of meaning.’
theoretically possible, generating a novel series of
Architectural Design, 12 (1963), 564–5. 28 Karl R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Project: Types, Typical Objects
17 Alan Colquhoun, ‘Typology and Discovery (London: Hutchinson, and Typologies’, Architectural
Design Method’, Perspecta, 12 (1969), 1959). Design, 81 (2011), 24–31.
71–4. 29 Jane Darke, ‘The Primary 42 Argan, ‘On the Typology of
18 Anthony Vidler, ‘The Third Generator and the Design Process’, Architecture’.
Typology’, Oppositions, 7 (1977), 288– Design Studies, 1 (1979), 36–44. 43 Philip Steadman, Building Types
94. 30 Michael Brawne, Architectural and Built Forms (Kibworth
19 Ibid., 292. Thought: The Design Process and the Beauchamp: Troubador, 2014).
20 Aldo Rossi, Peter Eisenman, Diane Expectant Eye (Oxford: Architectural 44 Colquhoun, ‘Typology and
Ghirardo, Joan Ockman, The Press, 2003). Design Method’, p. 74.
Architecture of the City (Cambridge, 31 Cross, ‘Designerly Ways of 45 Ibid.
MA: MIT Press, 1982), p. 41. Knowing’.
21 Vincent Scully, ‘Postscript: Ideology 32 Erving Goffman, Frame Analysis: An Authors’ biographies
in Form’, in Aldo Rossi, A Scientific Essay on the Organization of Experience Robert Grover is an architect and
Autobiography (Cambridge, MA: MIT (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Teaching Fellow researching design
Press, 1981), pp. 111–16. University Press, 1974). process and pedagogy at the
22 Rafael Moneo and Gina Cariño, 33 Dorst, ‘The Core of “Design University of Bath, Department of
Theoretical Anxiety and Design Thinking”’. Architecture and Civil Engineering.
Strategies in the Work of Eight 34 Donald Schön, ‘Problems, Frames
Contemporary Architects (Cambridge, and Perspectives on Designing’, Professor Stephen Emmitt is
MA: MIT Press, 2004). Design Studies (1984), 132–6. Director of the Centre for Advanced
23 Herbert A. Simon, ‘The Science of 35 Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in Studies in Architecture at the
Design: Creating the Artificial’, in General Linguistics, ed. by Charles University of Bath, Department of
The Sciences of the Artificial Bally, Albert Sechehaye, Albert Architecture and Civil Engineering.
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1969), Reidlinger, Wade Baskin, rev. edn
pp. 111–38. (London: Owen, 1974). Dr Alex Copping is Senior Lecturer
24 Horst W. J. Rittel and Melvin M. 36 Alan Colquhoun, Essays in in Construction Project
Webber, ‘Dilemmas in a General Architectural Criticism: Modern Management at the University of
Theory of Planning’, Policy Sciences, 4 Architecture and Historical Change Bath, Department of Architecture
(1973), 155–69. (Cambridge, MA: London: MIT and Civil Engineering.
25 Donald Schön, The Design Studio Press, 1981).
(London: RIBA Publications, 1985). 37 Vidler, ‘The Third Typology’. Authors’ addresses
26 Bill Hillier, John Musgrove, Pat 38 Ibid., p. 293. Robert Grover
O’Sullivan, ‘Knowledge and Design’, 39 Rossi, A Scientific Autobiography. r.j.grover@bath.ac.uk
in Environmental Design Research and 40 Alan Lipman and Pawel Surma,
Practice, ed. by W. J. Mitchell ‘Aldo Rossi, Architect, Scientist – A Stephen Emmitt
(Oakland, CA: University of Storm of Silence … An Architecture s.emmitt@bath.ac.uk
California, 1972), pp. 1–14. of Alienation’, Design Studies, 7
27 Nigel Cross, Design Participation (1986), 58–66 (p. 58). Alex Copping
(Michigan: Academy Editions, 1972). 41 Marina Lathouri, ‘The City as a a.g.a.copping@bath.ac.uk