Spinoza and Consciousness
Spinoza and Consciousness
Spinoza and Consciousness
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Mind Association and Oxford University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness
STEVEN NADLER
conclude either that he does not have an account of consciousness, or that he does
have one but that it is at best confused, at worst hopeless. I argue, in fact, that people
have been looking in the wrong place for Spinoza's account of consciousness, namely,
at his doctrine of 'ideas of ideas: Indeed, Spinoza offers the possibility of a fairly so-
and capacities of the body. Consciousness for Spinoza, I suggest, is a certain com-
plexity in thinking that is the correlate of the complexity of a body, and human con-
Spinoza anticipates the conception of mind that is presently emerging from studies
in the so-called 'embodied mind' research program. Moreover, this research pro-
gram, in turn, may hold out hope for a clearer understanding of some of Spinoza's
century, at least before Leibniz comes on the scene and introduces his
and Spinoza. The first two may appear to be obvious candidates for this
honour, and with good reason. But it is generally believed that Spinoza,
while he has much to say of value regarding the nature of the mind
In fact, while I am not willing to say that Spinoza has an explicit and
still, well ahead of his time in this domain as well. Spinoza does indeed
program. Moreover, this research program, in turn, may hold out hope
doi:10.1093/mind/fzn048
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
576 Steven Nadler
1.
nomenon that is independent of the body. While there are many con-
the conscious states themselves are modes of the mind, of thinking sub-
stance; and there are many conscious states that bear no relationship to
p. 113).
mainly for being the author of the 'Fourth Set of Objections' to the
Meditations and the so-called Port Royal Logic, who takes the study of
in the structure and function of conscious states, and especially the way
in which they are both known in consciousness and make known exter-
tially reflective on itself, or, as it is said more aptly in Latin, est sui
never know a square without knowing that I know it' (Arnauld 1775,
the locus of consciousness per se. Express reflection, on the other hand,
is what happens when one mental act is made the explicit object of
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 577
explains why I can think about my thinking about x and make it the
directedness is not only a feature of all mental states, but is in fact the
1775, p. 184).2
point of view. But what all this descriptive work really does is set the
challenge, one that has been haunting the philosophy of mind ever
since: how is one to explain consciousness? What gives rise to it? And
why are some beings conscious while others, apparently, are not? While
with these questions, they were, in fact, first raised directly for Des-
exactly is that thing that thinks, and what is the nature of its substance
When you go on to say that you are a thinking thing, then we know what you
are saying; but we knew it already, and it was not what we were asking you
to tell us. Who doubts that you are thinking? What we are unclear about,
what we are looking for, is that inner substance of yours whose property is
to think. Your conclusion should be related to this inquiry, and should tell
us not that you are a thinking thing, but what sort of thing this 'you' who
thinks really is. If we are asking about wine, and looking for the kind of
enough for you to say 'wine is a liquid thing, which is compressed from
grapes, white or red, sweet, intoxicating', and so on. You will have to attempt
can be seen to be manufactured from spirits, tartar, the distillate, and other
Similarly, given that you are looking for knowledge of yourself which is su-
perior to common knowledge (that is, the kind of knowledge we have had up
till now), you must see that it is certainly not enough for you to announce
that you are a thing that thinks and doubts and understands etc. You should
less be able to investigate whether or not you are better known than the body
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
578 Steven Nadler
here. After all, Descartes' point is that, because of the essential differ-
makes the cause and origin of consciousness and its properties as clear
ter and motion, but it must do the same kind of explanatory work and
that Gassendi issues here, a request for the scientific basis of conscious-
ness, and it is a shame that Descartes does not take it more seriously.3
Spinoza, I believe, does take this challenge seriously, more so than any-
2.
the human mind itself and its relationship to the human body. In
Spinoza's metaphysics, there is, of course, the one, infinite, eternal, nec-
the attribute of Thought. This is the upshot of IIP3:4 'In God, there is
ily follows from his essence.' For our purposes, what this means is that
for every finite mode of the attribute of Extension that is, every indi-
3 Descartes does, it seems, miss Gassendi's point and accuses him of making a category mistake;
see Descartes 1974-83, Vol. 7, pp. 359-6o; Descartes 1985, Vol. 2, pp. 248-9.
4 My references to the Ethics employ the standard notation, with the following abbreviations:
ten.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 579
`idea'-in Thought. That idea has that body as its object, and is its
of which is itself a body and thus will have a corresponding idea within
the macro-idea (or mind) of the macro-body. (Note that this doctrine
also implies that for every finite mode of the attribute of Thought, there
for every idea, there is an idea that has that first idea as its object.) The
the one hand, and minds and states of minds, on the other hand, is, of
course, Spinoza's monism: 'a mode of extension and the idea of that
mode are one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways ... For
example, a circle existing in nature and the idea of the existing circle ...
are one and the same thing, which is explained through different
attributes' (IIP7s).
What this means is that every single body in nature has a corre-
ship, 'the things we have shown so far are completely general and do
not pertain more to man than to other Individuals, all of which, though
be an idea of that thing in the mind. All bodies, in other words, have
tational states are of, at least in the most immediate sense, what they are
ative body.'
It follows from this that the human mind is nothing but the mode in
body. Or, more simply, the human mind is nothing but the idea of the
extension and a certain relatively stable ratio of motion and rest among
its parts-no different from any other kind of extended entity. And
' There has been much debate in the Spinoza literature on the differences and relationship be-
tween what an idea is 'of' (what it represents) and what is its 'object'; see, for example, Radner 1971
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
580 Steven Nadler
We thus have the following setup: all physical bodies in nature are
3.
There are two main schools of thought when it comes to the question of
flawed, even a failure.6 The other school says that there is no account of
prepared to argue that there is a single coherent and fully detailed and
also believe that it is not, in fact, the program that is most often identi-
has called 'what it is like to be'.8 The second meaning is that of a mental
state that one is at the same time aware of being in, thus importing an
6 Curley 1969, pp. 126-29; Curley 1988, pp. 71-3; Matheron 1994; and Wilson 1999. What is par-
ticularly interesting is how few contributions to the question of consciousness in Spinoza there re-
ally are.
' See Bennett 1984, pp. 184-91; Della Rocca 1996, p. 9; Matson 1971; and Miller forthcoming.
8 Tyler Burge (2007, pp. 383-4), following Ned Block, calls this 'phenomenal consciousness' (to
distinguish it from what he calls 'access consciousness'), and insists that it is 'the core notion of
consciousness.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 581
have a conscious state. This is true even if, for Spinoza, all intentional
states, all mental states are indeed conscious states; even if they are all
but also conscious. Many things that Spinoza says appear strongly to
that as it may, my main point in this paper does not depend on the
iss for what seems to be the more popular way of understanding what
least among those writers who do think that Spinoza does indeed have
this aspect of his system does indeed seem perfectly well-suited for
making sense of the awareness of ourselves and of our mental states (as
consciousness consists.
of Thought, for every idea or mode of Thought, with the former having
9 Wilson (1999, pp. 134-5) agrees with this; so does Curley (1969, p. 128). On the other hand,
that being conscious is identical to having an idea for Spinoza has been argued for by Garrett 2008.
1- For example, in IIIPus, where it is suggested that an affect in the mind (i.e. an idea) may, at
11 This is the view adopted by Curley, Wilson, and Matheron, in the works cited above. Bennett
(1984, p. 188), on the other hand, insists that the 'idea of idea' doctrine is a theory of self-knowl-
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
582 Steven Nadler
mind, which follows in God in the same way and is related to God in the
Dem.: Thought is an attribute of God (by ITN, and so (by IIP3) there must
necessarily be in God an idea both of [NS: thought] and of all its affections,
and consequently (by IIPii) of the human mind also. Next, this idea, or
knowledge, of the mind does not follow in God insofar as He is infinite, but
insofar as He is affected by another idea of a singular thing (by IIP9). But the
order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of
causes (by IIP7). Therefore, this idea, or knowledge, of the mind follows in
God and is related to God in the same way as the idea, or knowledge, of the
body, q.e.d.
In the scholium to IIP21, after demonstrating that 'this idea of the mind
is united to the mind in the same way as the mind is united to the body,
Spinoza notes that 'the idea of the mind ... and the mind itself follow in
God from the same power of thinking and the same necessity. For the
idea of the mind, i.e., the idea of the idea, is nothing but the form of the
to the object. And what is true of the mind qua idea of the body is also
true of every idea within (or constitutive of) the mind: each is also
told that 'the human mind perceives [percipit] not only the affections of
the body, but also the ideas of these affections'; but the ideas of the
affections of the body just are the constitutive ideas of the mind, and so
for the mind to 'perceive' them is just for each of them to be the object
of an idea. Finally, IIP23 states that 'the mind does not know itself,
that every idea is the object of a distinct, second-order idea. But this, I
believe, cannot be right. Spinoza claims that there is, at some level, an
identity between the idea of an idea and the idea that is its object. Just
as an extended body and the idea of that extended body are one and
the same thing conceived under two different attributes, so too the
idea of the mind or of any other idea and the idea that is its object 'are
one and the same thing [una eademque] which is conceived under one
and the same attribute, viz. Thought' (IIP2is). This does not necessar-
ily mean that the idea of an idea and its idea-ideatum are numerically
idea of an idea and its idea-ideatum are `united'; the idea of an idea is
nothing but the 'form of the idea, and thus is in one sense inseparable
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 583
the same event as the occurrence of the idea, that one cannot exist
tinct from the idea that is its object, with the latter capable in princi-
not-it will have more in common with what Arnauld means by 'vir-
involved,' albeit one that occurs at the same level or order as the
original idea and is inseparable from it (just as the mind and the
body, while identical and inseparable, are still two different modal
expressions).
There is some highly suggestive evidence that Spinoza sees the 'ideas
that 'the knowledge of good and evil is nothing but an affect of Joy or
idea of the joy or sadness in the mind that is the correlate of the affect in
the body caused by the external thing. To explain what this idea of a
affect he refers the reader back to IIP21, where he explains the notion
of an idea of an idea.
particular theses: first, the thesis that every thing in nature is a con-
scious being, or that all minds or all ideas correlated with all bodies are
12 In fact, there will be an infinite number of ideas involved, since an idea of an idea, because it
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
584 Steven Nadler
conscious minds; and second, the thesis that all states or ideas in the
the first thesis but accepts the second. But what about Spinoza?
conscious ideas in the human mind; and some of these further believe
doing so!' Others argue that Spinoza does not intend any such distinc-
ness.14
The reason why this is relevant to the issue at hand is that if Spinoza
mind, then the 'ideas of ideas' doctrine will not serve him well as an
If one believes that the 'ideas of ideas' doctrine is the closest that
accept that for Spinoza all minds, all beings in nature, are conscious,
and that all ideas or mental states in the human mind are conscious.
But perhaps this conclusion, as odd as this may seem, can be given an
B Curley (1969, pp. 126-8), for example, initially argues that Spinoza does successfully make the
distinction. However, recognizing the validity of Wilson's critique of his explanation of this dis-
tinction (Wilson 1999), he later realizes that such a reading is untenable (Curley 1988, p. 72). Wil-
son thinks that Spinoza intends to uphold such a distinction, but has no coherent way of doing so.
15 In fact, this is precisely why Bennett (1984, p. 188) rejects the 'ideas of ideas' doctrine as
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 585
of the nature of its consciousness. Thus, it would seem that if any inter-
that all beings are equally conscious and in the same way, and that all
ideas in the human mind are equally conscious, then I say so much the
But that is precisely where the 'ideas of ideas' account leads. Just as
degree, as is every idea in every mind. I do not see how the 'ideas of
4.
16 Garrett (2008), for one, rejects the 'ideas of ideas' doctrine as an account of consciousness in
' Thus Wilson (1999, p. 133) denies that (Spinoza's theory of "minds" can admit of rational dis-
tinctions between conscious and non-conscious entities, or between conscious and non-conscious
states of a particular individual'; and Bennett (1984, p. 189) insists that while Spinoza 'urgently
needs a theory of [conscious] awareness ... unfortunately the Ethics does not contain one.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
586 Steven Nadler
What we find in Spinoza, in fact, are some very suggestive remarks for a
mind.
must look beyond the 'ideas of ideas' doctrine, I argue, and toward a
especially, are crucial. The first occurs at II1313s, and takes as its starting
points the already established parallelism between the human body and
the additional claim that the human body is indeed 'more excellent'
than any other kind of body in nature. Here is what Spinoza says in the
first passage:
things at once, or being acted upon in many ways at once, so its mind is more
the actions of a body depend more on itself alone, and as other bodies concur
(III313s)
This, Spinoza concludes, will help us understand the way in which the
Because human bodies are capable [apta] of a great many things, there is no
doubt but that they can be of such a nature that they are related to minds which
have a great knowledge of themselves and of God ... He who, like an infant or
18 It might be suggested that the 'ideas of ideas' doctrine is intended to explain self-conscious-
ness rather than mere phenomenal consciousness; after all, when he introduces the doctrine, he
explains that 'as soon as someone knows something, he thereby knows that he knows it ...'
(IIPzis). But when Spinoza later appears to relate consciousness to bodily complexity, as I discuss
below, it is also clear that what is at stake is a person (or, rather, a mind) being 'conscious of itself'
(VP39s)
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 587
child, has a body capable of very few things and very heavily dependent on ex-
ternal causes, has a mind which considered solely in itself is conscious [conscia]
has a body capable of a great many things, has a mind which considered only
The second passage tells us that not only is the human mind 'more
excellent' than other minds because its body surpasses other bodies in
its own aptitudes or capacities, but that the mind of any individual
human being becomes more excellent as its body becomes more active
But I want to suggest that, in fact, they hold the key: human or higher
ratio of motion and rest among the particles and collections of particles
of matter composing it. It is the body it is because its parts, while per-
haps in motion relative to each other (or to groups of each other), none
size, are so constrained by other bodies that they lie upon one another, or they
so move, whether with the same degree or different degrees of speed, that they
say that those bodies are united with one another and that they all together
this union of bodies. (Spinoza 1925, Vol. 2, pp. 99-10o; Spinoza 1984, p. 46o)
The human body is no different from any other kind of body in this
bodies by its superior capacities. And I suggest that these greater capac-
ities of the human body are to be understood as (or reducible to) that
19 Thus, Wilson (1999, p. 137) insists that 'Spinoza offers us no way at all of understanding why
the adult body's fitness for many things should be linked to consciousness in the adult mind. Gar-
rett (2008, p. 9) similarly notes that these passages ' [do] not seem to offer a promising approach to
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
588 Steven Nadler
parts and motions. And this variety goes deep, since the body's largest
active, and responsive than what is found in any other physical existent.
than any other finite mode of that attribute. Or, at least, this is how I
Now the passages quoted above (II1313s and VP39s) make no direct
apt' or 'more capable' of. But for Spinoza, a body's aptitudes are a func-
tion of the constitutional makeup of the body: its material parts and the
ratios of motion and rest between them (that is, their structures and
of Part Two that to understand the difference between the human body
and other kinds of body and just how the former surpasses the latter, it
these it is above all necessary to understand what body is, and what it is
another kind of body. In the Short Treatise, he says that 'the differences
between [one body and another] arise only from the different propor-
tions of motion and rest, by which this one is so, and not so, and this
and not that' (Spinoza 1925, vol. 1, p. 52; Spinoza 1984, p. 95). In the Eth-
vidual body 'retains its nature ... so long as each part retains its motion,
of a body and its passive capabilities 'by this we see how a com-
posite individual can be affected in many ways, and still preserve its
nature' (II, Lemma 7). The upshot, then, is that the references of IIPl3s
extension.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 589
(i.e. the human mind) of the greater complexity, flexibility, and respon-
also corresponding to the relations among the bodily parts. And any
individual idea in that mind holds within itself a superbly rich concate-
parts and their relations). Consciousness, on this view, just is that rich
any particular idea in the mind, a mental reflection of the rich tangle of
makes an idea conscious occurs within the first-order idea itself; it does
not require a second-order idea directed at the first. While the 'ideas of
idea either, the approach for which I am arguing does not even require
an 'idea of an idea, that is, an idea that has another idea as its object.
Admittedly, this is all very vague and sketchy. But here is one way of
cashing it out. Consider what Spinoza says in the passage from IIN3s:
the more capable the body is the more 'capable [the mind is] than oth-
ers of perceiving many things at once. One way of looking at this is that
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
590 Steven Nadler
Is it not, at the same time and through the same act, both the percep-
Notice that this account does not require that only human beings are
conscious for Spinoza. All bodies have some degree of complexity, and
all minds have some degree of consciousness. But the increased con-
while possibly implying that all minds are conscious to some degree,
does not imply that all minds are conscious to the same degree.
gent property that certain mental systems take on only when their cor-
not fit well with what Don Garrett has called Spinoza's 'incremental
naturalism, or the view that there are no leaps in nature, that important
lesser degrees (Garrett 2008, p. 18). For that reason, I believe any talk of
adults, since their bodies, while possessing much of the right neurolog-
ical hardware, have not yet quite activated all of the human body's
this way, there may indeed lie here a reply to Margaret Wilson's chal-
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 591
remarks about bodily complexity, when she insists that 'Spinoza offers
us no way at all of understanding why the adult body's fitness for many
1999, p- 137).
human body does not causally explain consciousness in the mind. This
would violate the causal and explanatory separation that exists between
have God for their cause only insofar as he is considered under the
under any other attribute' (IIP6). Rather, what I am claiming is that for
5.
There has been only one other attempt seriously to relate consciousness
relying on precisely the same passages I have cited, argues that for
to persevere in its being, and that this striving to persevere that charac-
Garrett says, 'is the degree of its perfection, which is also the degree of
also true of the same thing over time. The power or perfection of any
its conatus. These changes in conatus just are, according to Spinoza (in
IIId3 and Illpost.i), the passive and active affects (depending, respec-
it means to say the human mind is 'more excellent' than other minds,
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
592 Steven Nadler
once' (just because its body 'is more capable than others of doing many
things at once, or being acted upon in many ways at once') is that it has
a greater power of thinking than other minds; it also follows that its
ver, he notes, this is true of particular ideas within the human mind.
`The more power an idea has to determine how the singular thing
whose idea it is does or does not exercise its power or conatus at a given
time, the greater will be the power of thinking of that idea in that par-
and of other things to the extent that it has 'a body capable of a great
lar mind can be more or less conscious at different times (as its power
of thinking varies); and why some ideas are more conscious than others
in a given mind.
lows that every idea in the mind is conscious simply by virtue of being
power of thinking).
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 593
increase or decrease in itchiness; but it does not follow that the rash's
colour and its itchiness are identical. These just happen to be two con-
Similarly, all that seems implied by the conjunction of IIP13s and VP39s
Extension), but not the conclusion that consciousness is the same thing
as power of thinking.
implies that if a and b in the mind are both parallel to c in the body,
then both a and b are identical to c, and thus (by the transitivity of
power of thinking are parallel to one and the same bodily feature, then
Garrett is right and consciousness and power of thinking are the same
severing.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
594 Steven Nadler
What this shows is not only that, on the basis of those passages, Gar-
rett concludes more than he is justified in concluding, but also that his
for Spinoza and what constitutes its grounding in the body. I agree with
This correlation follows from III313s and VP39s. But the question is, why
complexity's activation. In the mind, there will, for that increase in bod-
thinking (i.e. consciousness); there will, for that increase in bodily com-
is, the more active and powerful it is, not because consciousness is iden-
tical with power but because both of these features of the mind are
power of thinking) in the same fact about the body, namely, its com-
plexity.
VP39s Spinoza draws the direct line from consciousness not to bodily
mind to the human body's being 'more capable than others of doing
20 Given Spinoza's elimination of causal relations across the attributes, the type of explanation
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 595
the human body consists not only in its higher capability of doing
many things at once, but also in its higher capability of being acted on
6.
Of course, many questions remain questions for which there may not
be clear and ready answers. Among these, there is the question of how
the 'ideas of ideas' doctrine. It seems hard to believe that Spinoza's talk
of consciousness, so natural seems the fit between the two. This incre-
since every idea is equally endowed with an idea of an idea, there can be
said, in part, of IVP8, although here he also explicitly uses the word 'con-
scious'.) Through an idea of an idea, the mind 'knows' itself and it 'per-
ceives' the ideas of the affections of the body. Perhaps, in Spinoza's mind,
things), on the one hand, and a cognition of oneself and of one's mental
states.22 What that difference is, however, seems very hard to articulate.23
21 The rest of the paragraph of III)13s suggests that what is a function of increased power in the
body (`as the actions of a body depend more on itself alone ...') is not consciousness, but adequate
23 Bennett (1984, p. 188) tries to do something along these lines, but not, as far as I can see, very
clearly.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
596 Steven Nadler
But what exactly is that mental complexity that is its correlate? Can we
identifiable relations among our ideas (and especially among the sub-
ideas of any conscious idea) that provide its proper analysis? The idea of
This latter issue is, of course, Chalmers's 'hard question' about con-
is one thing to refer to the structures and dynamics that obtain among
structures in the body (the brain and the nervous system) -`give rise'
ity among and within our ideas -`perceiving many things at once'-
depend not only on whether Spinoza can specify what exactly is the
of himself and of God, i.e., the more perfect and blessed he is.' How can
and insisting that it, like other varieties of reductionism, fails to capture exactly the intuitive fea-
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 597
7.
so far as the nature of the human mind and its functions are grounded
appears to offer us, his naturalism about the mind opens the way to a
the human body's makeup that are the ground of human consciousness.
his belief that the key to understanding the nature of consciousness lies
in the investigation of the body, and particularly in what I see as his sug-
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
598 Steven Nadler
bodies are so thoroughly integrated that the hope that one might study
and states of conscious awareness have the properties they do not just
but-if researchers like Damasio (1994) and Lakoff and Johnson (1999)
are correct because of the form our body has (for example, the fact
that our posture is vertical, that we have four limbs, two eyes, etc.) and
would never have connected with our mental lives (for example, our
human minds and human consciousness are what they are because
human bodies are what they are. Like Spinoza, embodied mind theo-
rists reject what has been called 'body neutrality, or the idea that the
defend the claim that any such integration of mind and body is not just
of Spinoza's claims (for example, that minds and bodies are simply
ously have no place in the contemporary study of mind. But his sugges-
tion that minds and bodies are two expressions of a single substance
from which they can begin to articulate more exactly the nature of the
relationship between mind and body and in a way that makes clearer
how, on their view, the connection goes beyond a simple causal one.
26 Shapiro 2004.
' The term 'body neutrality' was coined by Shapiro (2004) to describe a thesis held by certain
functionalists.
28 Ned Block (2005), for example, has charged some embodied mind advocates with confusing
the radical idea that bodies are in some sense constitutive of minds with the less exciting idea that
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 599
ophy of mind. With respect to the topic of this paper, for instance, how
Number of cells? Number of neurons? Spinoza says that for every part
of the human body there is a corresponding idea in the mind. But do all
parts more important than others? I have conjectured that for Spinoza
mind and consciousness take into account a body's interaction with its
parts in terms of a ratio of motion and rest are very abstract and go
hardly any distance toward answering such questions. But these are just
the kinds of questions for which one should expect answers if Spinoza's
ever relevant to the embodied mind program it proves to be, the fact
that that program might well offer empirical support for some ele-
answer to Gassendi's challenge? Not quite. There are still too many
29 I am very grateful to Maria Seidl, Stefanie Gri.ine, and Julia Borcherding for this insight (and
others) in their commentary on my presentation of this paper to the Leibniz Prize Research
' My thanks to Larry Shapiro, Don Garrett, Michael Della Rocca, Elliott Sober, and two anony-
mous referees for this journal for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. I am
also grateful to Ed Curley, Dan Garber, and Jon Miller for sharing their thoughts on the issues; and
to audiences at the conferences 'Spinoza and the Sciences, held at the Royal Netherlands Academy
from 1500-1750, held at Humboldt University, Berlin (June, 2007); and 'Spinoza Day, held at Prin-
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
600 Steven Nadler
STEVEN NADLER
Department of Philosophy
University of Wisconsin-Madison
Madison, WI 53711
USA
smnadler@wisc.edu
References
Hackett.
Block, Ned 2005: Review of Alva Noe's Action in Perception, in The Jour-
pp. 383-4.
sity Press.
2001: Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow and the Feeling Brain. New
York: Harcourt.
pp. 4-25.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Spinoza and Consciousness 601
Lakoff, George and Mark Johnson 1999: Philosophy in the Flesh: The
Basic Books.
pp. 83-91.
pp. 568-78.
forthcoming.
Press.
Spinoza, Baruch 1925: Spinoza Opera (4 Vols), ed. Carl Gebhardt. Hei-
1984: The Collected Works of Spinoza (Vol. 1), trans. Edwin Curley.
pp. 126-4o.
This content downloaded from 159.178.22.27 on Tue, 15 Mar 2016 22:06:47 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions