Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

On Computable Numbers With An Application To The Alanturingproblem

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

Artif Intell Law (2017) 25:181–203

DOI 10.1007/s10506-017-9200-2

ORIGINAL RESEARCH

On computable numbers with an application


to the AlanTuringproblem

C. F. Huws1 • J. C. Finnis2

Published online: 13 May 2017


 The Author(s) 2017. This article is an open access publication

Abstract This paper explores the question of whether or not the law is a com-
putable number in the sense described by Alan Turing in his 1937 paper ‘On
computable numbers with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem.’ Drawing
upon the legal, social, and political context of Alan Turing’s own involvement with
the law following his arrest in 1952 for the criminal offence of gross indecency, the
article explores the parameters of computability within the law and analyses the
applicability of Turing’s computability thesis within the context of legal decision-
making.

Keywords Statutory interpretation  Decision making  Machine learning  Criminal


law  Legal certainty  Homosexuality

In a recent article, ‘Command Theory, Control and Computing: A Playwright’s


Perspective on Alan Turing and the Law’ (Huws 2014), Huws posed the question of
whether the legal system could be compared to a Turing-compliant machine as
described by Turing in ‘On Computable Numbers with an Application to the
Entscheidungsproblem’ (hereafter ‘On Computable Numbers’) (Turing 1937).
Instinctively, the law is something that ought to be computable, in that it ought to be
possible to convert the processes of legal decision-making into an algorithm—a set
of simple instructions and decisions—and thus render it computable.

& C. F. Huws
trh@aber.ac.uk
J. C. Finnis
jcf1@aber.ac.uk
1
Aberystwyth Law School, Elystan Morgan Building, Llanbadarn Fawr, Ceredigion SY23 3AS,
UK
2
Department of Computer Science, Aberystwyth University, Llandinam Building, Penglais,
Aberystwyth, Ceredigion SY23 3DB, UK

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
182 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

In essence, the notion that law should be computable is the appeal to legal
certainty that forms the basis of Hohfeld’s conception of law as a formal system
(Hohfeld 1913), and emphasised by Liebwald (2015) as a justification for devising
laws that are sufficiently precise and unambiguous in a way that would enable a
more extensive use of machine–lawyers.
There is indeed much within the legal process that may be undertaken by
machines, and this ranges from identifying whether the process-based elements of
litigation have been completed within the required timescale, to identifying
potentially relevant precedents (Prakken and Sartor 1996), to calculating the
probabilities of different possible causes of a crime or a tort (Vlek et al. 2016).
Furthermore, a machine may learn to identify relevant factors from a fact
scenario, and predict the probability of a particular outcome, by identifying
precedents and weighting them based on relevance and currency (Berman and
Hafner 1987; Hafner and Berman 2002) then applying those precedents to a new
case using case-based reasoning, a well-known machine learning technique
(Aamodt and Plaza 1994). More recent variants have been able to create a
hierarchy of relevant factors, including weighting recent cases more heavily than
earlier cases to take account of changing social mores, taking account of the
objective to be achieved by the legislation and also taking into account the
procedural context of the decision—such as whether it was heard before a first
instance court or before an appellate court (Aleven and Ashley 1997; Ashley and
Brüninghaus 2009). Within these parameters, it is possible to conclude that some
areas of the law are computable according to Turing’s conception of computability.
However, the success of machine learning used in this way presupposes that legal
decision-making occurs solely with reference to factors internal to the law—the
relevant legislation and the applicable precedents, and the policy that informed
those precedents (Loui 2016).
In this article therefore, by combining the methodology of ‘On Computable Num-
bers,’ and Alan Turing’s own involvement with the law as a result of being
prosecuted for the offence of gross indecency in 1952, we intend to demonstrate that
there are limitations on the computability of the law and therefore on the scope of
machine lawyers to replace human lawyers:
(a) firstly, because the systems of the law, as equivalents of the m-configurations
of Turing machines, are constant over neither time nor space;
(b) and secondly, because the information upon which the ‘machine’ of the law
works—analogous to the input of a Turing machine—consists of considerably
more than the bare facts of the case, incorporating societal and indeed
personal aspects that vary across time and place, and that these cannot be
known to a putative decision machine. Therefore, although the law has the
capacity to be a formal system where algorithms can be used to predict
(reasonably accurately in many cases) issues of culpability and liability, as in
the examples explored by Hafner and Berman (2002) using the HYPO
system, these do not, and cannot take into account, the abundance of factors
that exist outside the law.

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 183

1 On computable numbers and the law

In the early twentieth century, mathematics was in the throes of a ‘foundational


crisis’. Mathematicians of the ‘formalist’ school (led by David Hilbert) believed that
mathematics could ultimately be reduced to a set of mechanical rules by developing
a ‘formal system’ within which all mathematical statements could be stated. Such a
system consists of a set of symbols (letters, numbers, arithmetical signs etc.) which
can be organised into sequences called ‘strings’. The system also has an initial set of
strings called ‘axioms’, and a set of simple typographical rules for transforming
strings into new strings. If the symbols, axioms and rules have interpretations
consistent with mathematics, then any strings thus derived (‘theorems’) are also true
statements of mathematics. Hilbert referred to this as a ‘formula game’, with strict,
game-like moves (Hilbert 1967).
Attempts to find such a foundation of mathematics had run into difficulties, one
of which, providing a flavour of such problems, is Russell’s paradox: does the set of
all sets which do not contain themselves contain itself? If it does contain itself, then
it cannot be a member of the set and so should not contain itself; and if it is a
member of the set, then it cannot contain itself and so should not be a member of
that set. Hilbert’s programme (Zach 2016) was a proposed pathway to a solution of
this crisis. The key outcomes would be:
• a formalisation for all mathematics: the set of axioms and rules described above;
• a completeness proof that all true mathematical statements can be proved using
the formalisation: starting from the axioms, one can use the simple rules
provided to arrive at any true statement;
• a consistency proof that no contradiction can be similarly derived;
• a decidability proof that an algorithm (a ‘mechanical’ method with well-defined
steps and decisions) exists for determining the truth or falsity of any
mathematical statement.

Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem (Gödel 1931) showed that there is no


consistent (i.e. contradiction-free) formalisation whose theorems can be listed by
some algorithm which can prove all true statements about the arithmetic of the
natural numbers (0, 1, 2 and so on). Crudely speaking, Gödel achieved this by
showing that it was possible to produce an analogue of the paradoxical statement
‘this statement is not derivable in this system’ in any formal system sufficiently
powerful to encompass arithmetic. If it is true, then it is not derivable (thus the
system is incomplete), if it is false then it should be derivable (which it should not
be, since it is false). Thus, such systems must be incomplete: they contain
statements whose truth cannot be established. The second incompleteness theorem
built on this by showing that such a system cannot prove its own consistency.
Thus, two planks of the Hilbert program were removed: there can be no formal
system (in the sense defined above, made up of simple rules applied to axioms)
sufficiently powerful to perform even basic arithmetic, which can be complete (able
to generate all true statements) and provably consistent.

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
184 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

In 1936, two independent papers by Alan Turing and the American mathemati-
cian Alonzo Church removed the last plank of the Hilbert program by demonstrating
that within a formal system as defined above, there can be no general algorithm for
the determination of truth (i.e. derivability) of a statement. Although Church’s proof
was published slightly earlier than Turing’s (Church 1936), Alan Turing’s methods,
using the analogy of a simple machine, were the more intuitive and almost
immediately had wide-ranging consequences, showing that even a very simple
machine could compute anything that was ‘effectively computable’ (the ‘Church–
Turing Thesis’). ‘Effectively computable’ here is a term of art in computability
theory: a process M is effectively computable if and only if:
1. ‘M is set out in terms of a finite number of exact instructions (each instruction
being expressed by means of a finite number of symbols);
2. M will, if carried out without error, produce the desired result in a finite number
of steps;
3. M can (in practice or in principle) be carried out by a human being unaided by
any machinery save paper and pencil;
4. M demands no insight or ingenuity on the part of the human being carrying it
out’ (Copeland 1996).

The computing machine Turing hypothesised about provided a boost for early
computer designs, demonstrating that while such machines might have limitations, a
very simple machine could perform any task which could be performed by a far
more advanced machine, given enough storage space (although it might require far
more time).
There are interesting parallels between Gödel’s and Turing’s approaches to their
respective problems: both approaches involve encoding an entity as a number (a
statement in Gödel’s case, a ‘machine’ or algorithm in Turing’s), so that statements
can be made about encoded statements, or machines designed to operate on encoded
machines—or their own encoded descriptions. Gödel uses this encoding to create an
(indirectly) self-referential statement, while Turing uses it to describe algorithms
which operate on descriptions of themselves.
Much of Turing’s paper ‘On computable numbers’ (Turing 1937) is taken up
with the definition of the ‘Turing machine’, his chosen formal system. A Turing
machine operates on symbols printed on a finite, but unbounded, length of tape. It
can read, print and erase these symbols, but can only operate on the current symbol,
and it can move one step left or right on the tape. The machine has a finite table of
what are now called states, but Turing termed ‘m-configurations’. The machine can
only be in one state at a time, and one of these is the initial state. There may also be
final or ‘accepting’ states, at which the machine will stop, its calculation being
complete. This state table, together with the initial state, constitute the machine’s
description or ‘program’.
Each state contains actions to perform after a particular symbol is read: print (or
erase) the symbol; then move along the tape left, right or not at all; then change to a
new state (or remain in the current state). The operation of the machine consists of
writing the starting symbols on the tape (which constitute the input of the machine),

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 185

setting the initial tape position, setting the initial state, then repeatedly reading the
current symbol and performing the appropriate action given the current state.
A simple example of a state table is given below. This table adds one to the
binary number given on the tape. Thus, if the number on the tape is ‘1011’ and the
machine is pointing at the first 1, then the result will be ‘1100’ (i.e. denary 11 to
denary 12). State a moves the machine until it is operating on the last digit, state
b moves left, switching 0 with 1 and vice versa until we reach a 0, state c moves
right until we are back at the last digit.

State Symbol read Write Move New state

a (initial) Blank Blank L b


a 0 0 R a
a 1 1 R a
b Blank 1 R c
b 0 1 L c
b 1 0 L b
c Blank Blank L STOP
c 0 0 R c
c 1 1 R c

This is an extremely simple model of computation, but given an appropriate state


table and set of symbols it can perform any algorithm. One important feature is that
a Turing machine’s description (the state table) and its input can be encoded as
symbols and provided as input to another Turing machine, called the Universal
Turing Machine (UTM). The UTM is programmed in such a way that it can
‘emulate’ the Turing machine whose description it has been given, and produce the
output that machine would have produced. Turing provides a description of a UTM
as part of his proof.
Turing’s actual proof is famously complex and nothing more than the barest
outline will be given here. An extensively annotated version by Petzold (2008)
allows the proof to be followed and provides a great deal of background detail on
the ideas Turing uses. He begins by describing and demonstrating the Turing
machine, and discusses the concept of ‘computable numbers’—those numbers
which can be output by an appropriately programmed Turing machine. Because
each machine producing such a number can itself be described by a ‘description
number’ (for reading and emulation by a UTM), and such numbers are finite, they
can be enumerated. Since each description number produces one computable num-
ber, these must also be enumerable. However, if there were a process actually to find
the nth computable number, Cantor’s diagonal argument (Cantor 1891) could be
applied to make this sequence non-enumerable (by producing a new number not in
the enumeration) (Simmons 1993). Therefore, the computable numbers, and the
description numbers with which they are associated, cannot be enumerated.

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
186 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

Dissatisfied with this proof (‘…it may leave the reader with the feeling that
‘‘there must be something wrong’’…’ (Turing 1937), Turing turns his attention to
enumerating the ‘satisfactory’ machines: those which produce infinite streams of
numbers, and shows that a machine which could enumerate the satisfactory
machines is impossible. Simply put, such a machine would fall into an infinite
regression when asked to test its own satisfactoriness (as it must at some point do).
Thus, while the satisfactory machines are enumerable, they cannot be enumerated
by finite means. Additionally, no program can tell whether another program is
‘satisfactory’, a very similar finding to that of the later Halting Problem: no program
can tell whether another program will run forever or eventually stop.
Turing uses this result to show that there can be no program which can infallibly
tell whether another program will print a particular symbol—if there were, we could
combine these to show whether the machine could print any symbol infinitely, and
this would be logically equivalent to telling if it were ‘satisfactory’ and so must be
impossible.
Finally, he constructs a statement in mathematical logic equivalent to determin-
ing whether a machine ever prints a given symbol. Given that this determination is
not possible, he has now produced a mathematical statement whose result cannot be
determined, and thus has his counterexample: he has shown that ‘the Entschei-
dungsproblem cannot be solved’ (Turing 1937).
Turing, in showing that there could be no solution to the Entscheidungsproblem,
demonstrated that it was impossible to devise an algorithm that would indicate
whether a mathematical statement was provable from a set of axioms given a set of
rules—in essence, whether it was true or false, given it had total knowledge within
its domain. If the law is a formal system—that is, if a legal decision can be arrived at
by processing a given a set of axioms (the facts of a case) with a set of rules for their
manipulation—then the law is subject to the Entscheidungsproblem. If the law is not
a formal system (because the information required or the processing rules cannot be
enumerated), then there can also be no decision process, and again we cannot
predict the decision by algorithmic means. The legal system is partially formal in
that some of the processing rules can be enumerated. Examples include whether
eligibility requirements based on age, duration of employment, submission of
relevant documents within the required timeframe etc. have been fulfilled. However,
other areas of law cannot be enumerated so precisely—questions such as whether a
person is a trespasser for the purposes of the offence of burglary (Theft Act 1968,
s.9) may require more nuanced arguments in situations where the delineation
between where a person is legitimately entitled to be, and where they exceed the
bounds of the permission granted and become a trespasser may be subject to equally
compelling arguments from both advocates. As Sctutton LJ explained The
Calgarth [1926] P. 93:
When you invite a person into your house to use the staircase you do not invite
him to slide down the banisters.
Our contention in this article is that the question of whether the individual’s
conduct, let us say, of sliding down the staircase on a tin tray, is more analogous to
the use of the staircase (because the mischief that the property owner seeks to

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 187

prevent is injury caused by undue reliance on a rickety balustrade), or whether it is


more analogous to the use of the bannisters (because the mischief the property
owner seeks to prevent is unruly and undecorous behaviour), and whether or not the
quality of the staircase is material to the decision, is not a question whose answer is
computable in Turing’s terms because the immediate context of the instant case
cannot be predicted. For a Turing machine to emulate another machine precisely, it
must have identical configurations (i.e. legal rules) and input (i.e. facts, both
ponderable and imponderable). If the facts of one case are even slightly different
from the facts of another case, the output of the machine could be wildly different
from that which was predicted: legal rules are such that ‘even slight differences in
the facts of cases result in wildly disparate judicial outcomes’ (Scott 1993).

2 The Criminal Law Amendment Act 1885

Let us explain this with reference to a specific law. Given that the legislation under
which Alan Turing was prosecuted for gross indecency in 1952 was s.11 of the
Criminal Law Amendment Act (1885), this is the example we shall use. The
m-configurations of the legal system can therefore be identified as incorporating the
following:
(a) The enactment of legislation by an authorised legislature.
(b) Investigation by an authorised investigative authority.
(c) Prosecution by an authorised prosecutor.
(d) Hearing before a properly constituted court.
(e) Verdict.
(f) Sentence authorised by law.
(g) Implementation of appeal process.

The operation of these states causes the legal system to operate according to
certain behaviours whose results may be expressed as symbols: for example, Y and
N can be used to express the result of each test. The legal system thus computes
whether a person’s actions constitute a criminal offence, whether they should be
prosecuted, whether they are found guilty and how they should be punished.
Accordingly, in principle a person would only be found guilty of gross indecency if
the elements of the offence are fulfilled, namely
(a) that the defendant is a male person;
(b) that the act is committed in public or private;
(c) that an act of gross indecency is committed;
(d) or the defendant is a party to an act of gross indecency;
(e) or the defendant attempts to procure the commission of an act of gross
indecency;
(f) that the other party is a male person.

Thus, the legal process in this context contains many features of computability
such as the finite range of possible decisions on evidence (admissible/inadmissible),

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
188 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

a finite range of possible decisions on outcome (proved on the balance of probability


or beyond reasonable doubt, or not thus proved) and the finite range of the possible
means of redress (a fine or a period of imprisonment for example may be possible
outcomes, but being placed in stocks for the purposes of public humiliation may
not).
If the binary configurations of the legislation were the whole of the law, it would
be possible to conclude that the law is computable in accordance with Turing’s
analysis. What this analysis overlooks however is twofold. Firstly, the m-config-
urations of the law cannot be explained in a sufficiently unambiguous way to allow
it to be computable—much as McCulloch (1955) concluded in 1955 in relation to
the human brain and Turing-equivalent machines. Many of the decisions which
make up legal ‘computation’ are hidden processes within the minds of human
beings who are members of society, and these societal and personal decisions
cannot be analysed with accuracy. A decision on criminal liability is attributable to
far more than the statutory elements of an offence, as will be demonstrated later in
this article.
Secondly, because the outcome of litigation is influenced by too many factors
that rest outside of the legislation that render it impossible to predict whether earlier
conditions will be replicated in later cases. In essence, in order for the law to be
computable, the tape must contain the whole of society. By using the analogy of an
individual case as an input to a putative predictive legal Turing machine it becomes
apparent that it is impossible to predict the outcome of a specific case—it is
impossible to effectively generate the data required as the input to permit accurate
prediction, and it is impossible to generate the description of the machine because of
the ‘unknowable’ human factors involved in the processing.
In order to illustrate this proposition, we will explain how Alan Turing’s own
experience of the law was determined with reference to a wide range of factors
beyond the legislation, and that the timing of his arrest and prosecution came about
as a result of a combination of factors that were not replicated either earlier or
later—if R v Turing were to be encoded as a Turing machine, its outcome could not
be predicted from the outcomes of similar machines encoded for previous cases,
because no previous case precisely matched those of R v Turing in every respect.
These external influences may be categorised as
(a) a wider conception of the legal system beyond the statutory rules of the
legislation,
(b) the political environment,
(c) the social structure, and
(d) Alan Turing’s personal circumstances.

The combination of all of these factors underpin the fact, as Weeks (1990) explains,
that capture and conviction of criminal conduct is not solely attributable to the
wording of statutes, and that the law, unlike a computable number, is not calculable
by finite means. Thus, although the law aims to be an internally complete system,
decidable only with reference to its own materials, external factors operate on its
decision-making processes that obstruct the predictability of a legal outcome

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 189

because it is not possible to know all the factors which should be added to the input.
It is also not possible to know these factors will affect the system’s decisions: thus,
the m-configurations of the law in the previous cases may be subtly different from
those in the later cases, in ways not reflected in statute or precedent, or indeed ways
that are possible to predict.

3 Alan Turing and the law

In 1952, Alan Turing was convicted of six counts of gross indecency contrary to
s.11 of the Criminal Law Amendment Act (1885), and was ordered to be given a
course of hormone therapy as a condition of his probation order. Despite s.11 having
been in force for 67 years before Alan Turing’s conviction, and that it remained in
force for some fifteen years after he was convicted, the period between 1948 and
1953 represents a high-water mark in terms of the political, legal and social factors
that opposed homosexual behaviour. It was in 1885 that homosexuality was first
criminalised. Earlier common law and and legislation had criminalised buggery
(Buggery Act 1533) and attempted buggery (Offences Against the Person Act 1861,
s.62), but these had not been specifically homosexual offences, as both the pre-1533
common law and the statutes of 1533 and 1861 prohibited all anal sexual intercourse
irrespective of the gender of the participants. On the other hand, the Criminal Law
Amendment Act (1885), by virtue of s.11, specifically prohibited acts of gross
indecency between men.
Despite this law having been in force for 82 years, the conviction statistics (HM
Government 2015) show interesting patterns for the crimes of gross indecency,
sexual assault, and buggery. Conviction rates for gross indecency did not exceed
300 convictions until 1936. However, there was a significant spike (over 1000
convictions) between 1951 and 1955, and a second spike is seen between 1971 and
1984. Convictions for buggery follow a similar pattern. Only in 1929 do we see
more than 100 convictions for buggery, but again this escalates from 1941 onwards,
and again the high point is in 1954 followed by a subsequent diminution. The third
crime is that of indecent assault against a male, and here again, there is a rapid
increase in the rate of convictions seen from 1943 onwards and a high point is
reached in 1951.
Alan Turing’s arrest in 1952 therefore occurred just at the point when convictions
for homosexual offences reached their zenith. What this demonstrates is that the
legislation—the configurations that compute whether a person has been grossly
indecent—remain constant, yet the calculations in respect of liability vary. The
variations, we submit, is because of the effects of politics, and the effects of societal
and personal factors on the decision-making powers of the courts. Despite the law
remaining constant for nearly 100 years, the irregularity in the pattern of conviction
statistics demonstrates that the likelihood of being pursued and thereafter found
guilty is not possible to predict. As such, while the configurations of the legislation
remain constant, the data upon which they act is subtly different due to the wide-
ranging external effects described above, and thus it is impossible to predict whether
a later case would follow an earlier one. What follows therefore is an exploration of

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
190 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

the range of factors that caused the early 1950s to be a period where the risk of
being convicted of a homosexual offence was much greater than it had been earlier,
and also much greater than it was to be later in the decade, and why these factors
inhibit the capacity of the law to be computable.

4 The legal influences that led to Alan Turing’s conviction

Three legal factors beyond the legislation may be identified as creating a situation in
the early 1950s where homosexuality was more likely to lead to a criminal
conviction. The first of these was the police, the second was the courts and the third
was the expansion of probation as an alternative to imprisonment.
During the early 1950s the police were investigating homosexual offences more
frequently (Report of the Departmental Committee on Homosexual Offences and
Prostitution para. 33), and s.11 of the Criminal Law Amendment act (1885)
provided the police with an opportunity to pursue an offence that, unlike buggery,
was easy to prosecute but difficult to defend. Buggery was difficult to prove
because, in many cases, only the parties involved could provide the necessary
evidence of the offence having taken place, and where the activity was consensual,
such evidence was unlikely to be forthcoming. Furthermore, the prosecution had to
prove that a specific activity and specific conduct (i.e. anal sexual intercourse) had
taken place.
Gross indecency on the other hand was a much more nebulous offence. Any type
of conduct could be construed as being grossly indecent and this included acts
undertaken in private. Furthermore, gross indecency did not even require physical
contact to have taken place between the participants, as the case of R v Hunt [1950]
2 All ER 291 confirms, where all that was required was that the conduct was such
that it could be regarded as indecent in the perception of a hypothetical beholder, as
Lord Goddard CJ further explains in Hunt:
If a third person had walked into this shed, he would have seen the most
shocking indecency between the appellants.
This meant that the courts could hypothesise about the sort of person who could find
the defendants’ conduct to be grossly indecent, and it would be very difficult for the
defendants to argue that such a person did not exist.
The availability of a range of similar offences also meant that the police had the
scope to charge a defendant with multiple offences (buggery, indecent assault and
gross indecency, as well as their inchoate equivalents of attempt and procurement),
and then persuading the defendant to plead guilty to the lesser charge of gross
indecency if the more serious charge were to be withdrawn (Westwood 1960). This
type of bargaining was particularly attractive to the police in the late 1940s and
early 1950s because arrest rates by the police began to be monitored and austerity
meant that police forces were keen to justify their continued existence (Higgins
1996). Accordingly, behaviours that could constitute multiple criminal offences
were investigated more extensively than had been the case in previous years and
offences that did not require any specific conduct were particularly attractive to

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 191

pursue. Gross indecency was one such offence particularly as each grossly indecent
act was the subject of four separate charges. Accordingly, when Alan Turing
reported the burglary of his home to the police, the police were able to press charges
for 12 counts of gross indecency on the basis of 3 encounters between Turing and
his lover, Arnold Murray. The pressure on the police to increase arrest rates
introduced an additional configuration into the legal process that could not have
been predicted by the Criminal Law Amendment Act (1885).
The second influential factor outside the legislation, but within the parameters of
the legal process, was the courts. Within the court process, there was a high degree
of circularity to the prosecution of homosexual offences. More prosecutions meant a
greater number of guilty pleas partly because the police encouraged defendants to
plead guilty to a lesser charge; gross indecency rather than buggery, and partly
because legal representatives sought to minimise the impact of a by using the guilty
plea as a basis for arguing in favour of a lower sentence. Once medical treatment
was permitted as an alternative to a criminal conviction (as a result of the Criminal
Justice Act 1948), more men were advised to plead guilty at the earliest opportunity,
and to accept treatment as an alternative to imprisonment. This then justified the
continued reliance on gross indecency as the preferred charge by prosecutors,
because there was a greater likelihood of securing a conviction.
The attitudes of the courts towards the punishment of offenders was also
influential. The expansion of probation (Green 2014) as an alternative to
imprisonment had significant consequences for homosexual defendants—although
these may be viewed as both positive and negative in their effects. Although a
probation order had the positive effects of allowing homosexual men to avoid
imprisonment, and thus to maintain their connection with their family and to remain
in employment, it also meant that the courts were more willing to return a guilty
verdict (Arnot and Usborne 2002) because the consequences of a guilty verdict were
less severe.
Also, because homosexuality was perceived at the time as having a medical
cause, it meant that a guilty verdict could be justified more easily because it enabled
those who were, by the nature of the offence they had committed, classified as ‘ill’
to have access to medical treatment. From 1948 onwards, the combination of the
existence of the criminal offence of gross indecency and the availability of a
probation order introduces new configurations to the legal system—there is a viable
and attractive alternative to imprisonment that makes a guilty verdict seem less
harsh and therefore more willingly contemplated than might have been the case
earlier in the 1940s when imprisonment was the only possible sentence. This means
that the experiences of homosexual defendants after 1948 cannot be predicted with
reference to what occurred previously. The availability of alternative sentences
dilutes the predictability of the courts’ decision-making process as harsher
punishments may encourage more robust defences, while more lenient outcomes
may encourage a greater willingness to pled guilty but thereafter to present pleas in
mitigation. Again, these inputs into the legal process change the behaviour of the
law machine and cause it—potentially at least, to behave differently from that which
has been encountered earlier.

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
192 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

This lack of predictability presumes that, at the very least, the courts are applying
the law correctly and consistently within these new parameters. However, even
within the context of a legal system where homosexual men were more likely to be
caught and thereafter more likely to be found guilty of gross indecency, Alan
Turing’s experiences do not appear to be something that can have been predicted
from the behaviour of Knutsford Assizes at the time. Turing (2015) explains, for
example, that others convicted of the same offence on the same day were treated far
less harshly than Alan Turing, with sentences ranging from a £15 fine to a 3-year
period of probation. Significantly, Alan Turing was sentenced far more harshly than
his co-defendant Arnold Murray, who was given a conditional discharge, despite the
fact that Murray was also being sentenced for the offence of theft.
Dermot Turing’s view on this (Turing 2015) is that the Knutsford Assizes erred
on the law applicable in relation to the orders available to the court. In Alan
Turing’s case, a probation order was imposed under s.3 of the Criminal Justice Act
(1948), a provision which specified that the order could also require the defendant to
comply with any specific conditions considered necessary in order to ensure the
defendant’s good conduct. However, s.3 makes no specific reference to medical
treatment as being one of those conditions. On the other hand, s.4 of the 1948 Act
does refer to a requirement to undergo treatment, but specifies that medical
treatment may only be ordered for a mental condition, and it was as a result of s.4,
not s.3 that oestrogen injections were administered to Alan Turing. However, no
evidence had been put to the court that Alan Turing had any form of mental
disorder. Dermot Turing concludes that the court should not have made an order for
treatment because it had not established that a mental condition that would justify
such a treatment existed. It is doubtful that this argument would have succeeded if
Turing’s conviction had been the subject of an appeal because it is possible that no
medical evidence needed to be adduced regarding any mental condition because the
World Health Organisation had classified homosexuality as a mental illness in 1948
(World Health Organisation 1968) and therefore there was no need for this to be
proved specifically in individual cases. Nevertheless, the principle that the
predictability of the law’s configurations may be undermined by a misunderstanding
of the law is a further significant restriction on the computability of the law. A
computer cannot compute the possibility that the law may, legitimately or
otherwise, be interpreted in a different manner from that which is expected, or from
that which occurred in another case, decided by a different judge.

5 The political influences that led to Alan Turing’s conviction

In addition to the decision-making processes—the m-configurations—of the law


however, Alan Turing’s capture and conviction was attributable as much to the
influences of politics as it was to the legal system, and the political landscape of the
early 1950s affected both the processes by which guilt or innocence were
established, and the hidden societal and personal data upon which those processes
acted, just as much as the law.

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 193

The early 1950s saw the birth of the welfare state, but with it came the rhetoric of
selflessness, of making sacrifices for the greater good, and of working together to
build a better world (Higgins 1996). The Wildean stereotype of the flamboyantly
dressed homosexual (Hornsey 2010) was demonised as being a frivolous spendthrift
who was more concerned with his own appearance than with contributing to the
common purse (David 1997). Not all homosexuals were aesthetes of course, and
beauty does not preclude generosity, but the popular logic was that all homosexuals
are aesthetes, and all aesthetes are selfish, therefore all homosexuals are selfish
(Higgins 1996).
Society was also more restrictive than it had been 10 years earlier or that it would
be 10 years later. This was compounded by the fact that marriage and family values
were social priorities and the unmarried man was seen as a threat to this ideal
(David 1997), especially as political rhetoric also sought to connect homosexuality
and paedophilia in people’s minds (Higgins 1996). In truth, homosexuality was
probably no more or less prevalent in the 1950s than it had been at any other time,
but presenting it as a threat to a social order that had been fragmented by wartime
separations and deaths meant that the first half of the 1950s was a period when the
association of homosexuality and ‘badness’ played on people’s fears about
fragmented families and moral collapse and there was therefore an increased
feeling of justification by politicians that they should be seen to be doing something
about a perceived problem.
The personalities in politics at the time were also relevant. Sir David Maxwell
Fife was the Home Secretary, Sir John Nott-Bower was the Commissioner of the
Metropolitan Police, and Theobald Mathew was the Director of Public Prosecutions.
The former is on record as stating that he was greatly concerned there had been a
‘serious increase’ in homosexual offences since the war (Maxwell-Fife 1954), while
Nott-Bower was the Commissioner of the Metropolitan Police at a time when the
Metropolitan police were using agents provocateurs in order to entrap men into
soliciting (Hyde 1970) Mathew meanwhile was very vocal in his objection to
homosexuality, and Higgins (1996) explains that there was a sharp increase in the
number of prosecutions instigated by the office of the Director of Public
Prosecutions for offences involving homosexuality, during Mathew’s tenure in that
role. This meant that there was a very powerful homophobic vein in the very
sections of the administration that could implement harsh policies to pursue and
punish homosexuals (McGhee 2001). According to David (1997), Maxwell-Fife for
example, was responsible for bringing about the resignation of William Field MP
after he had been found guilty of importuning, and is also suspected to have been
instrumental in encouraging the police to prosecute both the writer, Rupert Croft-
Cooke and the actor, John Gielgud (Vincent 2014). Yet, personalities in power at a
given time are like shifting sands—those in power during one administration are on
the opposition benches in the next, and therefore the attitudes of one tranche of
politicians may have very little influence once there has been a change of
Government or even a Cabinet reshuffle. The consequence is that whose influence is
stamped on policing and judicial policy at any given time is impossible to measure.
Transgressions of the law that may have been dismissed as being unimportant
during the tenure of one Government is magnified and problematized in another,

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
194 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

and in 1952, one such problem was homosexuality. One specific reason for the
characterisation of homosexuality as a societal problem was that, by 1952, being a
homosexual was perceived as a risk to state security, and therefore a homosexual
man working for the secret services, as Alan Turing did, was particularly vulnerable
to being removed from a position where he might be privy to State secrets.
The Criminal Law Amendment Act (1885) had long been regarded as a
blackmailer’s charter (Higgins 1996), but the events of 1951 had compounded this.
After the spies, Guy Burgess and Donald Maclean, defected to the Soviet Union,
their lifestyles, including Burgess’s homosexuality were luridly described in the
press (David 1997), and as a result the term ‘homosexual’ came to be perceived as a
euphemism for traitor. It was suggested at the time that the Burgess and Maclean
scandal caused the British Government to institute a purge of homosexuals from
strategically significant roles—roles that were therefore vulnerable to attempts by
enemy organisations to expose weaknesses that could lead to the disclosure of
classified information (David 1997). Weeks (1990) further comments that the US
State department had ‘already conducted a purge on homosexuals in its own
echelons’ and argues that it is conceivable that this may have influenced the UK
Government. If this is perception is accurate, then Alan Turing would have been a
particular target, not only because of his work with the British secret services, but
also because of his work with the American civil service as well, and there would
have been a very strong incentive to remove him from Government work if his
sexuality (which Turing was not reticent about disclosing to those around him) was
a perceived threat.
Although Turing (2015) considers the possibility of a threat to state security to
have been unlikely to have influenced the Manchester police at the time of his arrest,
it is significant nevertheless that there was a volte face in the court’s attitude
between Turing’s committal on February 27 and the trial on March 31. At the
committal proceedings, Turing was bailed, while his co-defendant Arnold Murray
was remanded in custody. However, at trial, it was Turing who was more harshly
treated, while Murray was released. Furthermore, the circumstances of his capture
and arrest also has some curious features that suggest that it is at least possible that
his capture is attributable to something more than misfortune. His office at the
University of Manchester had been broken into a short time before the burglary of
his home (Turing 1952) suggesting that this was not the work of an opportunistic
thief. The very personal character of the items stolen from Turing’s home (2 medals,
3 clocks, 2 shavers, 2 pairs of shoes, 1 compass, 1 watch, 1 suitcase, 1 part bottle of
sherry, 1 shirt, 1 pullover and 1 case of fish knives and forks) (Turing 2015) also
suggests that the burglary was undertaken in order to intimidate its victim as
opposed to having been undertaken for some financial gain. There is of course no
way of knowing what either the Manchester police or the Knutsford Assizes knew
of such sensitive information concerning Alan Turing’s work, and therefore all this
article is able to claim is that the possibility of their having been influenced by fears
about State security cannot be entirely discounted.
In the political landscape of the early 1950s therefore, the homosexual man that
undertook confidential work for the Government was at a far greater risk than he
would have been five years earlier or even five years later. By 1957, the Wolfenden

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 195

Committee’s recommendations had made it acceptable to express the view that the
private conduct of two individuals was not the business of the criminal courts, and
that homosexuality should be decriminalised (Report of the Departmental
Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution 1957). The other factors that
had caused the early 1950s to be a perfect storm, such as the defections of Burgess
and Maclean and the influence of personalities such as Maxwell-Fife and Nott-
Bower, had diminished in importance. Thus, although the legislation remained
constant, the role of politics and political personalities introduces significant
elements of inconsistency into the legal process making it incapable of being
computed and incomparable with other similarly configured instances of legal
intervention, and is the equivalent in a Turing machine of introducing changes to the
tape.

6 The societal influences that led to Alan Turing’s conviction

Outside the spheres of law and politics, a number of societal influences were also
significant in terms of increasing the likelihood that a homosexual man would be
caught and punished for his homosexuality. Firstly, the medicalisation of
homosexuality meant that from the 1940s onwards several different medical and
therapeutic approaches were developed which purportedly cured homosexuality—or
promised at least to enable patients better to cope with (i.e. to conceal) their
sexuality. As the belief that homosexuality had a medical cause became more
prevalent, further research, including the work of Glass et al. (1940), sought to
demonstrate that it could also be cured by medicine. The perception of
homosexuality as having an underlying medical cause is likely to have resulted in
more guilty pleas by those who believed that being cured would improve their
quality of life, more pleas in mitigation by legal representatives expressing the
willingness of the defendant to undergo medical treatment (as in Alan Turing’s
case) and possibly a greater willingness on the part of the courts to convict because
it would facilitate access to treatment. The medicalisation of homosexuality in the
1950s was something that the legislation of 1885 could not have predicted, and
therefore the behaviour of the legal system in 1952 cannot be predicted with
reference to its behaviour prior to this date, again demonstrating that the
configurations of the legal rules do not represent the totality of the factors in
judicial decision-making.
This unpredictability is further manifested by the fact that, by 1955, the medical
profession was beginning to doubt its assertions that homosexuality could be cured
(Davidson 2009). Doctors became concerned about the consequences of hormone
injections and began to view their use as extremely damaging (Evidence of Drs Inch
and Boyd to the Wolfenden Committee PRO HO345/15 HP Trans 4). Furthermore,
many argued that psychoanalysis was less successful than had been claimed because
those who were treated had been very carefully selected to create a positive
feedback loop. Furthermore, it was of course possible—indeed probable- that some
of those who has been treated were likely to have claimed that the treatment had

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
196 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

been successful, in order to ensure that the treatments were discontinued (Westwood
1960).
The second societal factor was the press. The press fuelled public antipathy
towards homosexuality, and its reporting practices at the time comprised of a
curious combination of silence and scurrility. Higgins (1996) comments that some
newspapers did not report trials for gross indecency, claiming that their readers
would find them distasteful. Others were more willing to portray homosexuality as a
growing problem (HC Deb 03 November 1949, vol. 469 cc577–9) and were using
the criminal convictions statistics for gross indecency to substantiate those claims.
At the same time, the more scandal-focused sections of the press provided more
lurid accounts of prosecutions (Mort 1988) for gross indecency with the result that
some readers were being presented with a narrative of homosexuality as vice-ridden
immorality while others were being influenced by a more middle-class sense of
distaste that was fuelled by the suspicion that vice was taking place (because it was
being reported in ‘other’ newspapers) but that it must be extremely sordid because it
was not being reported in ‘the sort of newspaper they read’ (Lewis 2013).
An appropriate analogy here may be the case of R v Penguin Books [1961] Crim
LR 176 where the concern of the prosecution centred around the impact of D.H.
Lawrence’s novel Lady Chatterley’s Lover on more impressionable members of
society—the question was not whether the book would deprave and corrupt the
jurors themselves, but rather whether it would deprave or corrupt one’s servants.
That homosexuality was a problem (Altman 1972) that needed to be solved was a
strong element of public and political rhetoric with the perceptions of the one
influencing the behaviour of the other. A strong emphasis was placed on identifying
instances of homosexuality among those who worked with children, thus fostering
the perception that homosexuality and paedophilia were synonymous (Higgins
1996: 176) and the nomenclature of the Wolfenden Committee (Report of the
Departmental Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution) also caused the
public to conflate homosexuality and prostitution. Public opinion, despite being
diverse also has a tendency to converge on the same conclusion despite applying
different processes. Those who opposed homosexuality argued that those practising
homosexuality should be punished pour decourager les autres. On the other hand,
those who had no objection to homosexuality per se, concluded, reluctantly, that
perhaps it should be discouraged because of the impact that the prejudices of others
was likely to have upon a person’s social status and employment prospects.
The symbiosis of these factors in the early 1950s is something whose impact on
legal decision-making cannot be quantified. It is possible that these factors may not
have influenced some courts at all, but their impact on other judges in other cases
may have been highly significant. Furthermore, the individuals within the legal
process may be unaware of the extent to which they are influenced by social
mores—its influence may be something that judges and juries do not consciously
recognise. Again, this points to the law being something that does not have
identifiable patterns of behaviour, and that legal decision-making does not have
precisely identifiable boundaries, thus rendering its outcomes unpredictable less
predictable than might be anticipated.

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 197

7 The individual influences on Alan Turing and the law

The viewpoints held by those who are liable to influence a defendant are also
indicative factors, as is the character and presentation of the defendant himself. In
Alan Turing’s case, his friends had advised him to plead not guilty, on the basis that
a court would be unlikely to convict (Turing 2015). However, his family’s advice
favoured pleading guilty on the basis that the sentence would be lower and that the
court would be more likely to accept a plea in mitigation.
The differences in age and social class between Turing and his co-defendant,
Arnold Murray are also likely to have been persuasive factors in the case. The
former was a 39-year-old university reader, while the latter was 19 years old (and
therefore below the age of majority) and worked as a photo-printer when the offence
took place. Turing attempted to protect Murray and therefore attempted to mislead
the police in order to conceal his suspicions regarding Murray’s involvement
(Hodges 1983). A defendant with different influences and a different set of
aggravating or mitigating factors may have been treated very differently by the
courts as the extent to which the defendant elicits a court’s understanding and
sympathy may also be stronger influences on culpability than is imagined by the
configurations of legislation. Again, we see how the law’s configurations, while they
may be static, are often markedly affected by external factors beyond the bare facts
of the case, and how the application of the same law may lead to very different
outcomes.

8 Is the law computable?

Alan Turing’s experiences of the legal system in the early 1950s came about
because of a complex multiplicity of factors, coming together at one period in time.
That period can be pinpointed even more narrowly to the early spring of 1952 in that
at no other period in the entire history of England would an indictment for the
offence of gross indecency have had to be hastily amended to indicate that the
prosecuting authority was no longer The King, but was rather The Queen. This is
particularly unfortunate because the term ‘Queen’ or ‘Quean’ was a term that was
used at the time as a derogatory term for a homosexual man. This misfortune would
only have befallen a person accused of gross indecency from the date of Elizabeth
II’s accession, until a time, shortly afterwards, when the standard forms would have
been reprinted. Elizabeth II acceded to the throne on February 6th 1952. On that
very day, Alan Turing was arrested for the criminal offence of gross indecency, and
his indictment does indeed have the words ‘The King’ crossed out, and the word
‘The Queen’ handwritten in its place. The social, legal and political factors that
made the early 1950s a period where the risk of capture and punishment for
homosexuality are particularly great, are compounded further therefore in the spring
of 1952.
What this demonstrates about the computability of the law is that a decision
regarding liability or otherwise cannot be predicted solely with reference to the

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
198 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

formulae of legislation. Both the data and the processing—the input to the machine
and the description of the machine itself—are constantly changing and largely
unknowable, incorporating the societal and personal backgrounds of every
individual involved in each case. Accordingly, the law is a machine that is touted
as being axiomatic, in that a person can only be punished for conduct that is contrary
to the law, but the law’s processes involve the operation of factors outside the
‘‘formal system’’ of the legislation itself. Therefore, during some periods in history,
that which is contrary to statute may have little impact on whether a person is caught
and punished, in that if there is no political, legal or social imperative to prosecute,
conduct that is criminal according to the legislation goes undetected and
unpunished. During other periods, efforts to bring an individual’s conduct within
the sphere of criminality are intensified. Accordingly, after the Sexual Offences Act
(1967) decriminalised homosexual acts committed in private, the conviction rate
increased as the police and the courts defined ‘in private’ very narrowly with any
acts committed where third parties were likely to be present being regarded as
contrary to the law. Even though the intention of the 1967 Act therefore was to
legitimise homosexuality, the narrow interpretation of the statute meant that
homosexual men were in even greater danger of being prosecuted for gross
indecency. For example, in the case of R v Knuller (Publishing, Printing and
Promotions) [1972] QB 179, Fenton-Atkinson LJ concluded (p. 187) that:
Even if those services included what the defendants refer to as flag and perv,
and the fact that Parliament has now said that acts of this kind between adults
in private shall not be a crime does not carry with it, in our view, the
consequence that such conduct may not be calculated to corrupt public morals.
We conclude therefore by asking whether, with reference to Turing’s own
experience whether the law is therefore computable? Is it possible to predict
whether the legal system will answer YES, and thus criminalise the individual or
will it answer NO? What is demonstrated by Alan Turing’s experience of the law is
that the law’s m-configurations and the facts of the case do not predict whether a
person will be pursued in respect of a criminal offence or not. Although we may
predict that law, politics and social mores may influence the outcome of certain
legal processes, what cannot be predicted is the extent and character of these
influences at any one time. Despite the appearance of certainty and consistency,
even if the configurations of the law were to remain constant, the actions of those
configurations would differ due to the multitude of factors which need to be
considered as part of the law’s ‘‘input’’ beyond the bare facts of the case, and it is
not therefore possible to conclude that like cases will behave in a like manner, just
as we cannot predict the output of a given Turing machine. The core reason for this
is that the law is not contained solely within its written parameters. It is influenced
by a myriad of shifting external factors. Thus, a written law may be relied upon very
extensively in some contexts in order to deter particular conduct or to demonstrate
that particular conduct is a growing problem, or, conversely, in other contexts, it
may fall into disuse. It may also be subject to shifting patterns in terms of the extent
to which it is regarded as an accurate barometer of public morality, or a catalyst for
change by being used to emphasise that the law is outdated and unjust. Furthermore,

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 199

it is impossible to predict whether, given similar conditions a court will arrive at the
same conclusion. This lack of consistency, as demonstrated by Alan Turing’s
experience of the law leads us to two important conclusions—one pertaining to the
nature of the law and the other relating to the limitations of artificial intelligence in
legal reasoning.
The hypothesis of law is that it should be certain—certainty is identified as one of
the principles of European Law (Case C-158/07 Förster v Hoofddirectie van de
Informatie Beheer Groep [2008] ECR WE-8507) while the three certainties are
essential elements in the creation of a valid trust (Knight v Knight 1840, 3 Beav
148). The prohibition under Article 7 of the European Convention on Human Rights
and Fundamental Freedoms (1950) against retrospective criminality would also
appear to be a central tenet of the rule of law. However, Alan Turing’s experience of
the legal process demonstrates that although the law under which he was prosecuted
predicted his act of criminality, the question of whether that law would be used was
decided retrospectively. In essence, although the possibility of being prosecuted for
acts of gross indecency is prospective, the circumstances whereby actually being
prosecuted becomes a likelihood are decided after the legislation has come into
force and after the transgressive act has been committed. Our first conclusion then is
that law is not computable because its outcomes cannot be calculated by finite
means, and the reason for that is that the inputs change in a manner that cannot be
predicted, and these configurations—these decision processes—may rely on data
which cannot be finitely encoded.
The second important aspect that Alan Turing’s experience of the law shows us
the limitations of artificial intelligence in relation to legal reasoning that arises
partly because there is a tendency to conflate ‘artificial intelligence’ with ‘the use of
computers.’ In the latter situation, although electronic processes may be
implemented to undertake a task that would be painstaking and time-consuming
for an individual human, the computer is not displaying intelligent behaviour. Much
work has been done on the use of computers to identify patterns (Walton 2010) in
terms of similar facts and predicting outcomes of cases through the use of artificial
intelligence (Unwin 2008). Work has also been undertaken on designing robot
lawyers that will undertake legal research and identify salient case precedents
(Carey 2013) and giving legal advice based on the information given (Al
Abdulkarim 2016). However, the machine is not ‘thinking’ in the sense that Alan
Turing conceives of in his other most famous work, ‘Computing Machinery and
Intelligence’ (Turing 1950) in other words emulating the thinking behaviour of
humans. Computerised legal advice operates either by responding to its program-
ming (El Jelali et al. 2015; Dalke 2013) or learning to identify patterns (Le et al.
2015) in terms of word usage and frequency, identifying factual similarities (Dalke
2013) and explaining probabilities (Franklin 2012).
Accordingly, a computer may be programmed to prompt a user to respond to a
series of questions, and can give advice on liability, or the availability of a claim
based on the responses given. It was soon discovered however that although this
works well with straightforward binary tests, where a yes/no answer may be given
(Sergot et al. 1986) it is less capable of dealing with more complex issues where
several pieces of legislation must be referred to (Bench-Capon et al. 1987). Despite

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
200 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

significant advances having been made in the scope for computers to apply
legislation through the use of ontologies (Van Kralingen et al. 1999), Al
Abdulkarim (2016) comments that much of the work on artificial intelligence and
the law has focused on ‘rule based systems, based on formalisations of legislation of
some kind’ and explains that computers have been less adept at recognising less
direct connections, such as inferential knowledge. However, more ‘‘advanced’’
forms of artificial intelligence with more powerful inferential techniques may be
able to identify trends in legal decision-making and identifying changing patterns in
terms of offences that come before the courts. Such artificial intelligence may be
able to track sentencing patterns ad to identify common factors in offences (Aleven
1997) that receive punishments at the upper boundaries of the courts’ sentencing
powers.
Alan Turing’s experience of the law demonstrates to us that the law is influenced
far more extensively by what is not known and by what is not predictable than
lawyer imagine. If we return therefore to the requirements under s.11 of the
Criminal Law Amendment act (1885), a computer could, on the basis of Alan
Turing having answered all the questions pertaining to the elements of the offence
in the affirmative, predict that Alan Turing would be guilty of gross indecency. The
computational process could be configured along the following pattern:
COMPUTER: Are you a male person?
ALAN: Yes. I am.
COMPUTER: Was the act conducted in public or in private?
ALAN: Yes it was.
COMPUTER: Was an act of gross indecency committed?
ALAN: Yes.
COMPUTER: Were you party to an act of gross indecency?
ALAN: Yes.
COMPUTER: Did you attempt to procure the commission of an act of gross
indecency?
ALAN: Yes.
COMPUTER: Was the other party a male person?
ALAN: Yes.
COMPUTER: Then you are guilty of an offence under s.11 of the Criminal Law
Amendment Act (1885).
However, as this article has demonstrated, this was not the problematic issue in
the case of R. v Turing and Murray. That Alan Turing was factually guilty of the
offence was never greatly in dispute. What was not predictable was the fact that this
offence would be pursued so extensively, and that Turing would be found guilty so
readily because a non-custodial sentence and the opportunity to provide treatment
were available to the courts. Thus, we conclude that the law machine cannot learn
by the law’s examples because what the law is does not emanate solely from the
law’s texts. Even when the law has a vast number of examples to draw upon, its
behaviour will not be consistent. We conclude then that the law machine cannot be
programmed because ultimately it is never the same machine. We cannot build a

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 201

machine to emulate it, because we cannot know the machine and the data upon
which it acts.

9 Conclusion

This article was inspired by a visit to Bletchley Park in 2011, and by the
juxtaposition within that museum of Alan Turing’s life and his work. In his life, his
sexuality, and the response of the legal system of giving female hormones to a male
problematised the question of ‘what is the difference between a man and a woman.
In his work, the question of whether a machine can think is also framed in terms of
asking whether one is able to differentiate between a man and a woman. In this
respect, Turing’s life is in his work and Turing’s work is in his life. What this article
demonstrates is that the same interconnectedness of life and work is encountered
when we juxtapose Alan Turing’s experience of the law with his investigations into
what is computable. For the lawyer, Alan Turing’s experiences of the law
demonstrates to us that what the law states is not the whole of what the law does.
For the computer scientist, analysing Alan Turing the mathematician alongside Alan
Turing the homosexual shows us that artificial intelligence cannot necessarily solve
the problems of the law. Law is not a computable number. The law’s Entschei-
dungsproblem cannot be solved. The Alan Turing Problem explains it.

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0
International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, dis-
tribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original
author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were
made.

References
Aamodt A, Plaza E (1994) Case-based reasoning: foundational issues, methodological variations, and
system approaches. AI Commun 7(1):39–59
Al Abdulkarim L (2016) A methodology for designing systems to reason with legal cases using abstract
dialectical frameworks. Artif Intell Law 24(1):1
Aleven V (1997) Teaching case-based argumentation through a model and examples. Ph.D. thesis,
University of Pittsburgh
Aleven V, Ashley KD (1997) Teaching case-based argumentation through a model and examples
empirical evaluation of an intelligent learning environment. Artif Intell Educ 39:87–94
Altman D (1972) Homosexual: oppression and liberation. Angus and Robertson, London
Arnot M, Usborne C (2002) Gender and crime in modern Europe. Routledge, Abingdon
Ashley KD, Brüninghaus S (2009) Automatically classifying case texts and predicting outcomes. Artif
Intell Law 17(2):125–165
Bench-Capon TJM, Robinson GO, Routen T, Sergot MJ (1987) Logic programming for large scale
applications in law: a formalisation of supplementary benefit legislation. In: Proceedings of the first
international conference on artificial intelligence and law, pp 190–198
Berman D, Hafner C (1987) Indeterminacy: a challenge to logic-based models of legal reasoning.
Yearbook of Law Comput Technol 3:1–35
Buggery Act 1533 (25 Hen. 8 c. 6)
Cantor G (1891) Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. Jahresbericht der Deutschen
Mathematiker-Vereinigung 1890–1891

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
202 C. F. Huws, J. C. Finnis

Carey M (2013) Holdings about holdings: modelling contradictions in judicial precedent. Artif Intell Law
21(3):341
Case C-158/07 Förster v Hoofddirectie van de Informatie Beheer Groep [2008] ECR WE-8507
Church A (1936) An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory. Am J Math 58:345
Copeland B (1996) The Church–Turing Thesis. In: Zalta A (ed) Stanford encyclopaedia of philosophy.
Stanford University, Stanford
Criminal Justice Act 1948 (1948 c.58)
Criminal Law Amendment Act 1885 (48 & 49 Vict c.69)
Dalke DL (2013) Can computers replace lawyers, mediators and judges? The Advocate 71(5):703
David H (1997) On Queer Street. Harper Collins, London
Davidson R (2009) Law, medicine and the treatment of homosexual offenders in Scotland 1950–1980. In:
Goold WE, Kelly C (eds) Lawyer’s medicine: the legislature, the courts and medical practice
1760–2000. Hart Publishing, Oxford, p 125
El Jelali S, Fersini E, Messina E (2015) Legal retrieval as support to eMediation: matching disputant’s
case and court decisions. Artif Intell Law 23:1
European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms 1950
Franklin J (2012) How much of common sense and legal reasoning is formalizable: a review of
conceptual obstacles. Law Probab Risk 11:225
Glass SJ, Deuel HJ, Wright CA (1940) Sex hormone studies in male homosexuality. Endocrinology
26(4):590
Green S (2014) Crime, community and morality. Routledge, Abingdon
Gödel K (1931) Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I.
Monatshefte Math Phys 38(1):173
HM Government (2015) A summary of recorded crime data from 1898 to 2001/02. https://www.gov.uk/
government/statistics/historical-crime-data. Accessed 23 Sept 2015
Hafner C, Berman D (2002) The role of context in case-based legal reasoning: teleological, temporal, and
procedural. Artif Intell Law 10(1):19
Hansard HC Deb 03 November 1949 vol. 469 cc577–9
Higgins P (1996) Heterosexual dictatorship. Fourth Estate, London, p 159
Hilbert D (1967) The foundations of mathematics. In: Heijenoort V (ed) From Frege to Gödel: a
sourcebook on mathematical logic 1879–1931. Harvard University Press, Cumberland, p 475
Hodges A (1983) Alan Turing: The Enigma. Vintage, London
Hohfeld W (1913) Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. Yale Law J 23:16
Hornsey R (2010) The Spiv and The Architect: Unruly life in Post-war London. Regents University of
Minnesota, Minneapolis
Huws CF (2014) Command Theory, Control and Computing: A Playwright’s Perspective on Alan Turing
and the Law. Liverpool Law Rev 35(1):7–23
Hyde HM (1970) The other love: an historical and contemporary survey of homosexuality in Britain.
Heinemann, London
Knight v Knight (1840) 3 Beav 148
Le TTN, Shirai K, Nguyen ML, Shimazu A (2015) Extracting indices from Japanese legal documents.
Artif Intell Law 23(4):315–344
Lewis B (2013) British Queer history: new approaches and perspectives. Manchester University Press,
Manchester
Liebwald D (2015) On transparent law; good legislation and accessibility to legal information: towards an
integrated information system. Artif Intell Law 23(3):301
Loui RP (2016) From Berman and Hafner’s teleological context to Baude and Sachs’ interpretive
defaults: an ontological challenge for the next decades of AI and Law. Artif Intell Law 24(4):371
Maxwell-Fife D (1954) Sexual Offences, Cabinet Office Record, 17 February. 1954, PRO: CAB 129/66
McCulloch WS (1955) Mysterium Iniquitatis of sinful man aspiring into the place of God. Sci Mon
80(1):36
McGhee D (2001) Homosexuality, law and resistance. Routledge, Abingdon
Mort F (1988) Cityscapes: consumption, masculinities, and the mapping of London. Urban Stud 35:5–6
Offences Against the Person Act 1861 (24 a& 25 Vict. c.100)
Petzold C (2008) The annotaed Turing: a guided tour through Alan Turing’s historic paper on
computability and the Turing machine. Wiley, Indianapolis
Prakken H, Sartor G (1996) Modelling reasoning with precedents in a formal dialogue game. Artif Intell
Law 6(2):127

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
On computable numbers with an application to the AlanTuringproblem 203

R v Hunt [1950] 2 All ER 291


R v Knuller (Publishing, Printing and Promotions) [1972] QB 179
R v Penguin Books [1961] Crim LR 176
Report of the Departmental Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution. London; HMSO, 1957
Scott RE (1993) Chaos theory and the justice paradox. William Mary Law Rev 35:329
Sergot MJ, Sadri F, Kowalski RA, Kriwaczek F, Hammond P, Cory HT (1986) The British nationality act
as a logic program. Commun ACM 29(5):370–386
Sexual Offences Act 1967 (1967 c.60)
Simmons K (1993) Universality and the liar: an essay on truth and the diagonal argument. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge
The Calgarth [1926] P. 93
Theft Act 1968 (1968 c.60)
Turing AM (1937) On computable numbers with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proc Lond
Math Soc 42(2):230
Turing AM (1950) Computing Machinery and Intelligence. Mind 49:433–460
Turing AM (1952) Letter to Fred Clayton, quoted in Hodges A (2012) Alan Turing: The Enigma.
Princeton University Press, Princeton
Turing D (2015) Prof: Alan Turing decoded. The History Press, Stroud
Unwin C (2008) An object model for use in oral and written advocacy. Artif Intell Law 16(4):384
Van Kralingen RW, Visser PR, Bench-Capon TJ, Van Den Herik HJ (1999) A principled approach to
developing legal knowledge systems. Int J Hum Comput Stud 51(6):1127–1154
Vincent J (2014) LGBT people and the UK cultural sector: the response of libraries, museums, archives
and heritage since 1950. Routldge, Abingdon
Vlek C, Prakken H, Renooik S, Verheij B (2016) A method for explaining Bayesian networks for legal
evidence with scenarios. Artif Intell Law 24(3):285–324
Walton D (2010) Similarity, precedent and argument from analogy. Artif Intell Law 18(3):217
Weeks J (1990) Coming out: homosexual politics in Britain from the 19th century to the present. Quartet
Books, London, p 12
Westwood G (1960) A minority. Longmans Green, London
World Health Organisation (1968) International Statistical Classification of Diseases and Related Health
Problems International Classification of Diseases 6. World Health Organisation, Geneva
Zach R (2016) Hilbert’s Program. In: Zalta E (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics
Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford

123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Terms and Conditions
Springer Nature journal content, brought to you courtesy of Springer Nature Customer Service Center
GmbH (“Springer Nature”).
Springer Nature supports a reasonable amount of sharing of research papers by authors, subscribers
and authorised users (“Users”), for small-scale personal, non-commercial use provided that all
copyright, trade and service marks and other proprietary notices are maintained. By accessing,
sharing, receiving or otherwise using the Springer Nature journal content you agree to these terms of
use (“Terms”). For these purposes, Springer Nature considers academic use (by researchers and
students) to be non-commercial.
These Terms are supplementary and will apply in addition to any applicable website terms and
conditions, a relevant site licence or a personal subscription. These Terms will prevail over any
conflict or ambiguity with regards to the relevant terms, a site licence or a personal subscription (to
the extent of the conflict or ambiguity only). For Creative Commons-licensed articles, the terms of
the Creative Commons license used will apply.
We collect and use personal data to provide access to the Springer Nature journal content. We may
also use these personal data internally within ResearchGate and Springer Nature and as agreed share
it, in an anonymised way, for purposes of tracking, analysis and reporting. We will not otherwise
disclose your personal data outside the ResearchGate or the Springer Nature group of companies
unless we have your permission as detailed in the Privacy Policy.
While Users may use the Springer Nature journal content for small scale, personal non-commercial
use, it is important to note that Users may not:

1. use such content for the purpose of providing other users with access on a regular or large scale
basis or as a means to circumvent access control;
2. use such content where to do so would be considered a criminal or statutory offence in any
jurisdiction, or gives rise to civil liability, or is otherwise unlawful;
3. falsely or misleadingly imply or suggest endorsement, approval , sponsorship, or association
unless explicitly agreed to by Springer Nature in writing;
4. use bots or other automated methods to access the content or redirect messages
5. override any security feature or exclusionary protocol; or
6. share the content in order to create substitute for Springer Nature products or services or a
systematic database of Springer Nature journal content.
In line with the restriction against commercial use, Springer Nature does not permit the creation of a
product or service that creates revenue, royalties, rent or income from our content or its inclusion as
part of a paid for service or for other commercial gain. Springer Nature journal content cannot be
used for inter-library loans and librarians may not upload Springer Nature journal content on a large
scale into their, or any other, institutional repository.
These terms of use are reviewed regularly and may be amended at any time. Springer Nature is not
obligated to publish any information or content on this website and may remove it or features or
functionality at our sole discretion, at any time with or without notice. Springer Nature may revoke
this licence to you at any time and remove access to any copies of the Springer Nature journal content
which have been saved.
To the fullest extent permitted by law, Springer Nature makes no warranties, representations or
guarantees to Users, either express or implied with respect to the Springer nature journal content and
all parties disclaim and waive any implied warranties or warranties imposed by law, including
merchantability or fitness for any particular purpose.
Please note that these rights do not automatically extend to content, data or other material published
by Springer Nature that may be licensed from third parties.
If you would like to use or distribute our Springer Nature journal content to a wider audience or on a
regular basis or in any other manner not expressly permitted by these Terms, please contact Springer
Nature at

onlineservice@springernature.com

You might also like