Health, Disease, and Illness As Conceptual Tools
Health, Disease, and Illness As Conceptual Tools
Health, Disease, and Illness As Conceptual Tools
2.1 Introduction
There has not been an absolute consensus on the definitions of health, disease, and
illness, even though these concepts are central not only in medicine but also in the
health social sciences (e.g., medical sociology, health psychology and medical de-
mography). These are parts of the conceptual tools in various medical-related fields.
A definition of each concept is imperative because they constitute parts of the analyt-
ical tools in medical sociology. The lack of consensus often prevents uniformity of
interpretations and generates more polemics. One wonders why there has not been
consensus, despite the long history of medicine. The concepts are multidimensional,
complex, and often elusive. For instance, Larson (1999) observed that disagreements
about the meaning of health are common because health is imbued with political,
medical, social, economic, and spiritual components. It is subject to various con-
ceptualisation and interpretations. While all the concepts have their foundations in
medicine, a biomedical perspective of health or disease may not be comprehensive
enough. However, a fusion of the various perspectives often presents a complex def-
inition like the WHO’s definition of health. This is why the debate on the definition
of health is still ongoing. That the debate continues is not a problem as refinement
of definition could lead to a better conceptualisation.
Physiological
The functionality of the body
biological system
Social
The ability to
connect and function
as a member of Health
society
Mental
The human psychological,
emotional, and intellectual state
2011; Awofeso 2012). For instance, Awofeso (2012) observed that the definition is
inflexible and unrealistic. He claimed that the inclusion of the word “complete” in the
definition makes it unlikely for anyone to be healthy for a reasonable period of time.
Godlee (2011) also noted that the definition is absolute and therefore unachievable
for most people in the world. The definition presents an absolute ideal situation by
combining the three aspects of human life. It is often difficult, if not impossible, to
gain complete contentment in all the aspects. It is observed that since health is a goal,
not only of the health care system but also individual and the society at large, it is
ideal for a body like WHO to present a realistic definition that can be operationalised
and achievable (Godlee 2011).
In addition, Saracci (1997) also submitted that the WHO’s definition of health
is problematic and it should be reconsidered. Saracci observed that the definition
equates health with happiness—that a disruption of happiness could be regarded as
a health problem. He further argued that the WHO’s definition reflects that health
is boundless. More so, Huber et al. (2011, p. 2) opined that the WHO’s defini-
tion is problematic because it impliedly declares people with chronic diseases and
disabilities definitively ill. The definition further minimises “the role of the human
capacity to cope autonomously with life’s ever changing physical, emotional, and
social challenges and to function with fulfilment and a feeling of wellbeing with
a chronic disease or disability” (Huber et al. 2011, p. 2). Despite several decades
of criticisms, the WHO has not reviewed the definition. The idea of a definition is
to present a holistic view that is meaningful not only for individuals but also as a
(definitive) tool in scientific investigation. The idea is not to advance an operational
perfection that is unchangeable. Perhaps, there is yet a review because there has not
been a more holistic and measurable alternative definition of health. The question is
simple: are other definitions of “health” more operational?
Several other scholars have proposed other definitions of health, which can be used
in light of changing global health circumstances. Some of these definitions will be
critically examined; however, the essence of examining other definitions is not to
defend the WHO’s definition or to render such alternative definitions as immaterial.
After some strictures of WHO’s definition of health by Saracci (1997, p. 1410),
he proposed a definition of health as “a condition of wellbeing, free of disease or
infirmity, and a basic and universal human right.” Impliedly, this definition also
defined those who are living positively with chronic disease as unhealthy. It presents
a health as a basic right, which is also problematic. In most parts of the world, health
is a commodity with an insurance premium, a price-tag, or it requires a pool from
the public tax. This also seems like a theoretical proposition that is not operational.
It does not really account for the multidimensionality of health. Therefore, it may
not be considered a holistic and viable alternative to the WHO definition.
24 2 Health, Disease, and Illness as Conceptual Tools
Table 2.1 Models for defining health. (Source: Larson 1999, p. 125)
Medical model The absence of disease or disability
World health organization State of complete physical, mental, and social well-being and not
(WHO) model merely the absence of disease or infirmity
Wellness model Health promotion and progress toward higher functioning, energy,
comfort, and integration of mind, body, and spirit
Environmental model Adaptation to physical and social surroundings—a balance free
from undue pain, discomfort, or disability
Bircher (2005, p. 1), on the other hand, defines health as “a dynamic state of well-
being characterised by a physical and mental potential, which satisfies the demands
of life commensurate with age, culture, and personal responsibility.” While this is
stylishly holistic, it is contentious due to the use of other concepts (e.g., age and
culture) without unified definitions. For instance, culture is complex, dynamic, and
relative. This may imply that the definition of health will also be relative and probably
depend on the circumstances or societies. Additionally, does the definition refer to
biological age or social construction of age? This is part of the complicatedness as
the concepts used are not specific.
In an attempt to proffer a more acceptable perspective in the face of the continu-
ous debate, Larson (1999) proposed that health should be conceived using multiple
models: medical, the WHO, wellness, and environmental models. A combination
of these models will be more holistic beyond the use of only the WHO model or
other definitions. Table 2.1 presents the models of defining health. One major prob-
lem with model-based definition is that there could be more models than expected.
The model-approach does not present a whole definition. Later, every profession
will likely present a model of health beyond common understanding, and this will
generate more issues. The major strength of this approach is that it emphases the
multifactorial context of the concept of health.
Following the argument that there could be more models, a social model will
dwell on Parsonian definition that defines health as “the state of optimum capacity
of an individual for the effective performance of the roles and tasks for which he has
been socialized” (Parsons 1972). This is more a sociological approach to health—a
conceptualisation of health as a social element. Health in this sociological sense is
more inclined towards human capacity to fulfil their obligations, participate in social
activities (including work), and fulfil role expectations in the society in the face
of structural limitations. This conception is connected with both physiological and
mental models of health in the sense that the source of a social incapacitation could
be from a biological or mental limitation. The social model does not debunk the
biomedical model. The model is complementary to the medical model and signifies
a perspective that is central in medical sociology.
In a recent development, Huber et al. (2011) defined health as the ability to
adapt and self-manage in the face of social, physical, and emotional challenges.
This definition was initially proposed in 2008 (see Jadad and O’Grady 2008). The
definition seems to be receiving some considerations, especially because of the use of
“adaptation.” While the WHO’s definition stresses on a complete state, this definition
proposes adaptive capacity. Lancet Editorial (2009, p. 781) commented, “Health is
2.3 A New Definition of Health? 25
Health has been conceived in a biomedical model as the absence of disease while
the holistic definition from the WHO signifies that health is not a mere absence of
disease. Whichever form the definition takes, the question now is “what constitutes a
disease?” One major issue is that disease is often conceived from a biomedical point
of view. It can also have behavioural manifestations, especially with regard to human
functionality. The definition of health is complex, so also is the definition of a disease.
If the lack of health can be defined as not a mere absence of a disease or infirmity, this
signifies that there are a number of germ- and non-germ-related (medical) conditions
that can signify the presence of a disease. This, however, also makes the definition
of a disease complex because of variations in its conceptions. Mainly, Boorse (1975,
1977) was engrossed in a practical and philosophical discussion of what health and
disease may entail. He defined disease as a type of internal state which impairs
health (i.e., reduces one or more functional ability below typical efficiency). One
major criticism of this definition is the use of “typical efficiency,” which implies the
presence of a reference group in the definition of disease (Kingma 2007; Stempsey
2000) as a kind of comparative analysis. This view is often referred to as a bio-
statistical theory (BST) of health and disease. Kingma (2007) argued that human
species are different in functional capacity: what is normal in one group can be
abnormal in another and vice versa. Therefore, Boorse’s definition of health or
disease is only valid depending on the reference group.
Despite this criticism, Boorse’s arguments have been a significant reference point
in the discussion of health and diseases. Boorse discussed seven major themes that
are prominent in the discussion of what health or a disease entails. It is important
here to examine the seven themes in line with the notion of disease and see how
important or otherwise those themes could be in identifying a disease.
1. Pain, suffering and discomfort: generally what is called disease accounts for
human suffering by inflicting pain and discomfort, sometimes unbearable, thereby
necessitating palliative care, like terminal sedation. Whitlow is a typical condition
that could impose considerable pain on the sufferer, although it requires a simple
medical procedure to resolve. A reason why the argument about pain may not be
sufficient is because there are a number of normal procedures that require medical
attention as a result of pain and discomfort, but are not diseases, such as teething,
menstruation, childbirth, and abortion.
2. Treatment by physicians: normally diseases require the attention of medical
doctors. A disease should be treatable. However, Boorse submitted that there
are some conditions that cannot be treated, and doctors also attend to a number
of conditions that are not diseases. With medicalisation of life, there are medical
expansions beyond treatment of disease, such as certification of fitness for a study
or travel. More so, circumcision, body modification or enhancement, and family
planning procedures cannot be regarded as diseases but require attention of a
physician.
2.4 Disease as a Conceptual Tool 27
Illness and disease have been major traditional concepts in sociology and medical
sciences. The important role of these concepts for human-related medical endeav-
ours was re-emphasised by Nordenfeldt (1993). These concepts are interwoven and
often require some analytical clarifications. Most often, people use the words inter-
changeable. As conceptual and practical tools, they are not the same. The essence of
this section is to make some conceptual clarifications of these concepts and not to
join the body of unending debate evident in the works of various scholars (including
Boorse 1975, 1977; Hesslow 1993; Nordenfeldt 1993; Stempsey 2000; Tengland
2007). More importantly, sociologists have laid more claims on the notion of illness
because it is more of a behavioural concept than a medical one. Undoubtedly, illness
has a number of undeniable social, moral, and legal contexts.
In a simple illustration, disease is a form of pathology or medical problem,
defect, or impairment, while illness is a manifestation of such an impairment, de-
fect/pathology, or disability. Illness is a presentation of a medical condition in a
way that limits the functional capability of an individual in the society. This is why
2.5 The Realities of Illness 29
There are various ways in which illnesses can be categorised. For the purpose of
this sociological explanation, categorisation based on acute, chronic, accident, and
mental illness is adopted. This categorisation also has sociological significance in
terms of the dimensions of the diseases. It is also important for medical sociologists
to be aware of the nature of diseases and some basic biomedical aetiologies and
modes of transmission.