A Participatory Model of The Atonement: - Life of Pi, Yann Martel
A Participatory Model of The Atonement: - Life of Pi, Yann Martel
A Participatory Model of The Atonement: - Life of Pi, Yann Martel
Tim Bayne
tim.bayne@gmail.com
St. Catherine’s College, University of Oxford
Greg Restall
restall@unimelb.edu.au
School of Philosophy, The University of Melbourne
Abstract
In this paper we develop a participatory model of the Christian doctrine of the atonement,
according to which the atonement involves participating in the death and resurrection of
Christ. In part one we argue that current models of the atonement—exemplary, penal,
substitutionary and merit models—are unsatisfactory. The central problem with these models is
that they assume a purely deontic conception of sin and, as a result, they fail to address sin as a
relational and ontological problem. In part two we argue that a participatory model of the
atonement is both exegetically and philosophically plausible, and should be taken seriously
within philosophical theology.i
What? Humanity sins but it’s God’s Son who pays the price? I tried to imagine Father saying to me, “Piscine, a
lion slipped into the llama pen today and killed two llamas. Yesterday another one killed a black buck. Last
week two of them ate the camel. The week before it was painted storks and grey herons. And who’s to say for
sure who snacked on our golden agouti? The situation has become intolerable. Something must be done. I have
decided that the only way the lions can atone for their sins is if I feed you to them.”
“Yes, Father, that would be the right and logical thing to do. Give me a moment to wash up.”
The atonement is at the heart of Christian theology. However, the atonement has not been at
the heart of 20th Century Christian philosophy of religion: at least, you would not get the
impression that it was from the volume of literature on the topic. Nonetheless, in recent years
there has been a noticeable change in the intellectual climate, with a number of philosophers
articulating models of the atonement. Although much of this work contains valuable insights, it
A model of the atonement is a model of God’s way of dealing with sin. In light of this, it is
useful to taxonomize models of the atonement in terms of their conception of sin. Roughly
speaking, one might conceptualise sin in three ways: ontologically; deontically; and relationally. An
ontological conception of sin conceives of it as a feature or element of human nature; it is
something from which we suffer. One might also call it a “pathological” conception of sin, for it
conceives of sin as a sickness. A deontic conception of sin conceives of sin in terms of a failure to
fulfil our moral obligations. Sin, on this view, is immoral behaviour, and it results in a moral
debt; it involves a debit in our moral ledger. A relational conception of sin conceives of it in terms
of broken or alienated relationships; sin, on this view, consists in the fact that our relationship
with God and each other is not what it ought to be. These three models of sin are not
necessarily mutually exclusive—perhaps a pluralist account of the atonement could view sin
through the lens of all three models—but they are substantively different, and treatments of the
Deontic Models
By far the dominant approach to the atonement in philosophical theology is deontic. Penal,
satisfaction, merit and sacrificial models of the atonement are all deontic models in that they
conceive of the atonement as dealing with a problem of moral debt. These models present
different accounts of how God deals with this debt, but they are united in their conception of sin
as first and foremost a deontic problem – it is a problem of moral debt.
According to Anselm’s satisfaction model in Cur Deus Homo, the debt is paid when Christ gives
God the honour that the human race owes him (see Aspenson 1990 for a contemporary
discussion). The debt is dealt with by payment: the death of Christ qualifies as payment for the
sin of humanity. According to the penal model (Morris 1966; Packer 1974; Porter 2002), the
debt is dealt with by punishment: Christ is punished in place of our non-payment of the debt.
On Swinburne’s (1989) sacrificial model, Christ’s death constitutes reparation and penance for
non-payment of the debt. And on the merit model the debt of sin is forgiven rather than repaid:
Christ’s life and death is a meritorious act that persuades God to forgive the debt (Quinn 1994;
Cross 2001; Putrill 1991).
A number of specific objections can be levelled against particular deontic models of the
atonement but rather than pursue these objections we want to explore generic objections to
deontic accounts of the atonement.iii
Somewhat curiously, proponents of the deontic conception of sin have said little about the
nature of the moral obligations that we are assumed to have. There are three issues to be
There is general agreement that the primary obligations are owed to God. Some or most sin
might involve flouting one’s obligation to oneself, or to other human beings, but on this picture,
all sin is first and foremost an offence against God. But what are these obligations? According to
Anselm, the obligation in question is our oubligation to honour God. There seems something
morally problematic about this claim. To conceive of this as the centre of our obligations is
morally dangerous. If the obligation to honour God is the ground of our obligations, then God's
relation to us is morally no different to a petty bureaucrat, whose relations with his inferiors are
controlled by whether or not those inferiors show respect. This is not to deny that respect may
be appropriate in a right relationship, but to analyse the rightness of the relationship in terms of
respect is to conceive of God’s desires for his creatures in terms of their compliance and deference.
This does grave injustice to the Gospel imperatives for the believer to love God and love
neigbour.
A second worry with Swinburne’s conception of sin is that it sits uneasily with the biblical claim
that all are subject to sin. Do we all live second-rate lives? It is not at all clear that we do.
Obviously a life can be more or less virtuous, but surely some lives are very virtuous — yet all
have sinned. (It could well be granted that we should call all lives of sinners “second-rate”, but
this is to evacuate the term of explanatory power. We then understand being second-rate in
terms of sin rather than vice versa, which was the aim.) Finally, we note that if we have an
obligation to God to live first-rate lives, then God has an obligation to us to give us the
opportunity to live first-rate lives. Given the prevalence of evil and suffering, one might think
that God has failed in this respect. Someone brought up in a violent and abusive household has
little opportunity to live a first-rate life. At the very least, we do not think that this is a helpful
explanatory notion, and again, it cannot be the point from which we explain the atonement.
Another ground for obligation might be the obligation we have to love God and love neighbour.iv
There is much to be said in favour of this notion, of course, and any properly Christian account
of the imperatives of the Christian life will focus on the these commandments. However, it
seems to us that thinking of love for God and love for neigbour as the grounds of an obligation is
to undercut the explanatory force of the deontological vocabulary. To conceive of sin in these
terms instead of than in compliance to some measurable code, is to recast the discussion in
relational terms, which we shall consider below.
Of course, none of these points is conclusive; there is surely much that could be said in reply to
them. Nonetheless, they do suggest to us that the deontic conception of sin is not
unproblematic.
So, a ground for dissatisfaction with deontic models of the atonement concerns their exclusive
focus on the deontic conception of sin.v Deontic models give very little attention to sin as either
an ontological or relational problem. The standard view seems to proceed as follows. Sin
involves a failure on our part to fulfil our moral obligations. This, in turn, leads to a breach in the
relationship between God and humanity, a breach which God repairs by means of the
atonement. This repair job—so the story goes—involves solving the deontological problem: the
restoration (and continued health) of the relationship is conditional on and grounded in the
good standing of humanity vis-à-vis our moral obligations to God. Since we are unable to secure
that good standing by our own merits alone, God must take the appropriate actions to secure it
for us (or with our help). As we have seen, models of the atonement differ on exactly how this
good standing is achieved (and maintained)—some models give a role to restitution, others to
punishment, others to forgiveness – but there is a broad consensus that reconciliation in the
relationship between humanity and God is conditional on a solution to the deontological
problem, the breach of obligations and duties.
There are a number of reasons to question this picture of things. For one thing, there is more
than a little tension between deontological and relational language. Even where is it justified, the
language of rights and duties is ill-suited to the most intimate of human relationships.vi The
surest sign that a marriage or friendship is in trouble is when the participants start invoking
their rights, or calling attention to their partner’s obligations. Friends do indeed have obligations
to each other, but it is not in the nature of friendship for friends to call attention to such
obligations. Outsiders seeking to understand the relationship would not be advised to conceive
of the relationship in terms of obligations, and it is unlikely that deontic language will play a
central role in the restoration of the relationship when it breaks down. We grant that as a
relationship is repaired, this may mean (and it may require) the meeting of obligations that were
Consider also another intimate relationship, that between children and parents. Although there
may be some room for a deontological approach to the parent-child relationship, this is surely
not how this relationship ought to be understood in the first instance. Children may have an
obligation to care for their parents in old age simply because they are their parents, but their
primary motivation and ground for such activity ought surely to be that of love. Similarly,
parents may have obligations to care for their children simply because they are their children,
but their primary motivation here should be based in the love they have for them. At the very
least, if the obligation has to play an important motivational or explanatory role, there is
something deeply wrong with the relationship. Invoking deontological language in a last-ditch
effort to fix what is broken is unlikely to mend an intimate relationship, and may well sour it
further.
So too, it seems to us, to conceive of restoring a broken relationship between a person and God
in terms of compliance with obligations is to do grave injustice to scripture and to Christian
tradition. According to the prophets, God desires mercy, not compliance with ritual commands.
Compliance with obligations is a consequence of atonement an not its ground (Isaiah 1:11ff,
Hosea 6:6, Matthew 9:13, Romans 3:20, Galatians 2:16).
Although this point has been extensively discussed in recent theological literature, it has been
only dimly appreciated in the literature in the philosophy of religion. Richard Swinburne rejects
penal models of the Atonement on the grounds that “talk of law courts and punishment makes
the whole process too ‘mechanical’ for a means of reconciliation that ought to be intimate and
personal” (1989: 152). This is surely true, but Swinburne himself describes sin as a debt that we
have incurred as a result of failing to fulfil our obligations to God (1989: 149). Porter’s (2002)
version of the penal model suffers from precisely the same shortcoming. Porter claims that
“fundamental to sin is a prideful usurpation of God’s rightful place in one’s life and thereby a
The deontological model of sin is also in tension with an ontological understanding of sin. If
sin is something under which we (together with the rest of creation) labour, then it is not clear
that we are morally responsible for it. An inability to do something is normally thought of as
excusatory. As the slogan has it, ‘ought implies can’. The sick need a doctor not a judge or jailor.
Even if deontic models of the atonement are able to deal with sin as a deontological problem,
they fail to deal with it as a problem of human nature.vii None of this is to say that talk of
obligations and duties can play no role for someone who takes sin to be a primarily ontological
problem. It is merely to say that such talk does not get to the heart of the problem. The signs
that the sick need a doctor are the symptoms of the illness. In the case of sin as diagnosed in the
New Testament, our failures of duties and obligations are at most a sign and symptom of the
illness and not the disease itself. Curing the disease by merely correcting the symptoms in no
more likely to be successful in treating the problem in this case than it is in everyday medical
practice.
A satisfactory model of the atonement should explain how Christ’s incarnation, death and
resurrection play an essential role in the atonement. Arguably, an account of the atonement need
not show that the incarnation was the only way that the atonement could be brought about if
only because we tread on difficult ground, and judgements of necessity and what is possible for
God to achieve in atonement are, at best, extremely difficult to justify. Nonetheless, an account
of the atonement should at the very least draw a meaningful connection between the atonement
and the incarnation. It is a powerful objection to any Christian theory of the atonement that it
Few conceptions of the atonement are able to meet these criteria. Consider, for example, Quinn’s
modified version of the substitution model:
Christ’s life and death persuade God to be lenient rather than severe in his treatment of
human sinners. Just because the supererogatory goodness in Christ’s life and his
voluntary submission to suffering and death are a sacrifice that is enormously pleasing
to God, their effect is to forestall the severe but just demand for reparation and not to
make the reparation that would be demanded in their absence. They function not to
remove a debt of punishment that human sinners owe by paying it, but to persuade
God to remit or cancel the debt. (1994: 298)
Quinn fails to explain here how Christ’s life and death persuades God to be lenient. Why was
the sacrifice that Christ paid to God enormously pleasing to him? If it were sacrifice alone that
God desired, why must God incarnate make that sacrifice? Why couldn’t someone else make the
sacrifice? Quinn fails to address any of these questions.
Brümmer’s accounts of the atonement raises similar questions. Brümmer summarizes his model
as follows: “through sincere penitence and divine forgiveness I can be restored to loving
fellowship. Such fellowship bestows ultimate meaning on my very existence and enables me to
‘live with myself ’” (1992: 451). Why does divine forgiveness require the incarnation, the cross,
and the resurrection? Brümmer’s answer is this:
… the person who forgives us is the person who has to pay the price for
reconciliation. Since in restoring our fellowship with God it is God who
forgives, it is also God who has to pay the price and has to absorb into his own
suffering the consequences of the wrong that we have done to him. On Calvary
God reveals to us the cost of his forgiveness. (1992: 452).
Perhaps the best that can be made of Brümmer’s line is this. The death of Christ is not in any
way a mechanism or a means of forgiveness, but a manifestation of God’s attitude toward us. We
need to know that God has forgiven us for the relationship to be restored, and this is how God
shows us. But now one wonders why God would choose to reveal the fact that we are forgiven in
this peculiar and costly way, unless that action was more than simply a revelation of God’s love.
The most sustained attempt to answer these questions that we know of is Purtill’s. Purtill
suggests that
in suffering and dying, Christ was giving God a good reason to punish us less and reward
us more than we deserve on our own merits. His suffering and death for our sake give
us a claim on God’s mercy and generosity. God became a man; as a man he offered his
suffering and death for our sake. God now has good reason to show us justice and mercy.
(Purtill 1991: 44; italics in original).
What is the “good reason” that Christ’s death provides? According to Purtill, God could have
forgiven us without Christ’s suffering, but to do so would have removed our motivation for
gratitude and repentance, for “we do not value what seems easy” (1991: 44). According to
Purtill’s account, Christ’s death is only externally related to the atonement: dealing with sin is
costly, but only because it is necessary that it appear to be costly. It is easy for God to obtain
salvation, but God doesn’t want us to think that it is easy. It is important for us that our
Purtill’s suggestion is ingenious, but there is something unsavoury about it. Consider the
following analogy. An eight-year-old wants a bicycle. Her parents can easily afford it, but they
worry that if their daughter realises this then she won’t value it. So they pretend that they can
barely afford to purchase the bike for her. No doubt there is something honourable about the
motives of such parents, but there is something dishonourable about their means. Similarly, one
ought to wonder about a God who makes a process that is not intrinsically costly appear to be
so.
There is a further problem with Purtill’s account. ] The costliness of an action can be a motive
for gratitude, but the costliness has to be seen to be internally related to the offence in order for
this to happen. Should the eight-year-old discover that her parents could easily afford the bike,
she would be angry, and justifiably so. Her parents take a risk in pretending that their daughter’s
present cost them more than it did, and their actions might well alienate her from them.
Similarly, on Purtill’s account, God takes a risk when he makes our atonement appear costly.
The motivational force of the atonement is dependent on our failure to realize that the
atonement doesn’t intrinsically cost God anything.
So, these contemporary analyses do not succeed in showing how the incarnation, crucifiction
and resurrection play an essential role in the atonement. We have reason to look elsewhere.
We end this section with some brief comments on deontic models of the atonement in the light
of the doctrine of the Trinity. The general worry here is that such models posit problematic
intra-Trinitarian relations. Consider, for instance, the penal model. The idea that God might
punish God for a debt owed to God is a strange one. Is God punishing Godself? That seems
The merit model of the atonement, according to which Christ’s life and death persuades God to
forgive the debt of sin, also posits the kind of intra-Trinitarian relations that is foreign to
Christian doctrine. In his letter to the Romans St. Paul claims that the Father sent the Son for
our salvation (Rom. 8: 3), and indeed the entire thrust of Paul’s thought sees the atonement as
the unified work of the Father, the Son and the Spirit. It is difficult to reconcile this with the
thought that Christ’s death persuades God the Father to cancel the debt of sin.
Finally, consider the Anselmian line, according to which Christ pays God the honour that we
owe him. There are two ways to understand this position. On one view, Christ honours God the
Father and not God as such. If this is Anselm’s view it is a strange one, for surely God as such
ought to be honoured, and not solely God the Father. So perhaps Christ honours God. This
view too is strange, for Christ as a member of the Trinity is God. Is Christ honouring himself?
Is that what atonement is all about? That too seems hard to square with what Christian
tradition takes the atonement to have achieved.
Two models of the atonement conceive of sin as an ontological problem: ransom models and
exemplary models. Although we applaud the fact that these models see sin as an ontological
problem, we find them unsatisfactory as well.
According to the ransom model Christ’s death was a ransom paid to the devil to free us from
bondage to him. Although the ransom model continues to have adherents (Taliaferro 1988) the
criticisms of the model are well known andwe will say little about it here.viii More popular are
exemplary accounts of the atonement. Such models go back to Abelard, and have been recently
defended by McNaughton (1992) and Quinn (1993). According to a purely exemplary model,
There is much that is attractive about the exemplary model of the atonement. Unlike many
models of the atonement, it offends against neither moral nor metaphysical scruples. There are
no dubious moral transactions at work when we take Christ’s death as an example to follow: we
all understand how it is that someone’s life can be inspirational. But for all that the exemplary
model has what we regard as fatal weaknesses.
One problem concerns what exactly it is that we are meant to emulate. For the emulation to
have any purpose, we need to be able to characterize Christ’s death as having an objective,
intrinsic point. Campbell captures the problem here well:
A meaningless or trivial death cannot reveal love: it reveals nothing – except perhaps
foolishness. If I drive my car at high speed into a brick wall, loudly proclaiming my love
for all humanity, my surviving family would probably wonder how I had left my senses,
not how extraordinarily loving my gesture was (Campbell 1994: 239).
The problem, in a nutshell, is that the exemplary model needs to be able to characterize Christ’s
death as accomplishing something in and of itself, apart from its inspirational value.
Proponents of the exemplary model are not blind to this problem. McNaughton suggests that
“Christ’s death can be seen as showing the believer, in the most vivid way imaginable, the costs of
human sin” (McNaughton 1992: 144). But how does Christ’s death show the costs of human sin?
McNaughton doesn’t say. We need an account of how Christ’s death is a response t—a cost of –
human sin, and this is precisely what exemplary accounts fail to provide. Unless one has some
understanding of how Christ’s death functions as a response to human sin it’s hard to see how it
could be taken to show the costs of human sin, far less show them “in the most vivid way
imaginable”. Perhaps McNaughton is merely suggesting that the atoning value of Christ’s death
derives from the fact that Christ’s death, as the death of an innocent and just man, was a very
A second problem with the exemplary model concerns its ability to address sin as an ontological
problem. The New Testament does present Christ as a model of self-sacrificial love, but it
doesn’t suggest that our primary problem is a lack of such models, nor does it suggest that we
are ignorant of the costs of sin. Instead, it suggests that our sinful nature puts us at odds with
each other and with God. The exemplary model lacks the resources to deal with a problem of
this nature.
In light of the above considerations we would seem to have ample justification for exploring new
conceptions of the atonement. In what follows we will do just that, not by introducing a new
model, but by rehabilitating an old model that has been undeservedly neglected: the
participatory model. There are hints of the participatory model in the recent philosophical
discussion of the atonement, but the model has not received the detailed attention that it
deserves.ix
The participatory model of the atonement goes back not to Calvin, Luther, Abelard[,] Aquinas
or Anselm, but to Paul. Consider the following excerpt from a summary of Paul’s thought by
the New Testament scholar Morna Hooker:
The sin of Adam was reversed and the possibility of restoration opened up
when Christ lived and died in obedience and was raised from life to death.
Those who are ‘baptized’ into him are able to share his death to sin (Rom. 6:
4-11) and his status of righteousness before God (2 Cor. 5: 21). Since Adam’s
sin brought corruption to the world, restoration involved the whole universe
But one might ask: isn’t there some sense in which sin is a deontic problem? How does the
participatory model deal with sin as a problem of moral culpability? We are not sure how best to
answer this question, but there are a couple of lines of thought one might pursue. One might
develop a hybrid model of the atonement, where participation in Christ’s death and resurrection
deals with sin as a relational and ontological problem, and some form of the deontic model deals
with sin as a deontic problem. While there is certainly room for such hybridisation, we are more
inclined to adopt the view that the atonement deals with sin as a deontic problem as a by-
product of dealing with the sinner: if the sinner is the “old person,” and the old person died with
Christ on the cross, then there is no one who ought to be regarded as guilty for their sin;
indeed, there is no longer anyone who ought to feel guilty for their sin.xi The moral debt we owe
to God (if such there be) is not punished or forgiven, nor is satisfaction or reparation made for
it. Instead, it is dealt with by changing the identity of the sinner: strictly speaking, the person
who is in the wrong before God no longer exists. We think that this is an advantage of the
model. God’s forgiveness cannot be coerced or merited, even by Godself.
One reason for the neglect of the participatory model is that Paul’s thought has all-too-often
been understood in deontic terms: specifically satisfaction and penal terms. Within the Western
tradition Paul has often been presented as concerned with the question of how guilty man can
be justified—that is, declared morally pure —before God (Torrance 2000). As we pointed out
above, recent Pauline scholarship has undermined this conception of Paul’s thought, and
replaced it with a view on which participatory notions lie at the heart of Paul’s understanding of
the atonement (see Campbell 1994, 2001; Hooker 1994; Sanders 1977; Ziesler 1990).
But what are we to make of those passages in which Paul does seem to endorse a deontological
conception of sin, such as Rom. 1:16–4:25, and Gal. 2:15–4:7? There are a number of options
here. One option is to adopt a two-crater view, on which Paul endorsed (perhaps at different
times) two models of salvation (see Sanders 1977). Another option, which we prefer, is an
argumentative reading of these passages, in which Paul’s use of deontic language is largely a
dialectical device, forced on him by the rhetorical framework of the theological battles he is
waging (see Campbell 2001). Although we find this position attractive, we needn’t argue for it
here. For our purposes we need claim only that participatory notions play a vital and centrally
explanatory role in Paul’s conception of the atonement.
This is a serious objection, and it deserves a detailed response. We can begin by noting that any
religion that is committed to a Trinitarian and Incarnational view of the divine has reason to be
cautious about a thoroughgoing application of Abelard’s constraint. It would be puzzling, to say
the least, to endorse (say) a realist conception of the incarnation or the Trinity only to dismiss
the participatory model of the atonement on the grounds that it is difficult to conceive of how
we might participate in the Cross. Indeed, it is tempting to suspect that the conceptual
difficulties involved in unpacking the participatory model are similar to those involved in the
Trinity and incarnation, and that this is a benefit of the current approach and not a cost. It is more
than tempting to think that participatory notions should play a role in our understanding of
both the incarnation and the Trinity. We don’t have the space to develop this line of thought
here; suffice to say that problematic conceptions of identity feature prominently in Christian
philosophical theology, and it should be no surprise to find them at the heart of the Christian
doctrine of the atonement.
But although not without merit, this point evades the central question for us: is the
participatory model really intelligible? There are really two questions here: (1) what can be said
by way of explicating what it is to be “in Christ,” and (2) what can be said by way of explicating
the relationship between the old person and the new person. (These two questions are, of
Consider the difference between what we might call numerical (or thin) personal identity and
moral (or thick) personal identity. The standard accounts of personal identity are best
understood as accounts of personal identity in the numerical (or thin) sense of the term.xii The
question these accounts attempt to answer is this: what, fundamentally, are we? What are our
identity conditions? In addition to the question of numerical identity, one might also think that
there is such a thing as moral identity. One’s moral identity is one’s identity as a moral agent, as
an entity that is responsible for its actions. The need to distinguish between numerical and
moral identity is, we think, amply motivated. Think about actions performed while asleep, or
under the influence of a drug, or in a fugue state, and so on. Are such actions things one has
done? Should one feel guilty for them? In some sense these are things that one has done – and
some feeling of [causal?] responsibility for them might be appropriate. (Think, for instance, of a
motorist who runs over and injures a young child who runs out in front of her. The motorist
might not be morally responsible for the child’s injuries, but she will – and arguably should –
feel some sort of responsibility for her actions.) But at the same time we might want to distance
ourselves from such actions in a certain way, and such distancing seems defensible. Such actions
are not a part of one’s real self: they are not expressive of one’s identity as a moral agent.
Moral identity is a matter of one’s commitments, values and relationships. My identity qua
moral agent is bound up with those projects and values with which I identify. I could survive
the transition from one set of relations and commitments to another as one and the same
person, but not as one and the same moral agent. The notion of moral identity gives us some
handle on what it is to be in Christ. To be in Christ is for one’s identity as a moral agent—as a
moral self—to be centred on Christ and Christ’s participation in the life of God.
What about the second problem: how are the old and new persons related? The first thing to
note is that Paul regards the transition from the old to new as a work in progress. The process
3. Conclusion
We have argued that the participatory model should be taken seriously within the
contemporary philosophical discussion of the atonement. It has strong Biblical credentials, and
it avoids many of the objections that plague other models. But embracing the participatory
model doesn’t demand that one reject all other accounts of the atonement; there is certainly
room for hybrid accounts of the atonement. Indeed, the participatory model can illuminate a
number of the other models of the atonement.
The atonement does indeed involve sacrifice on the part of God, but it is not a sacrifice that
God makes (to Godself ) as restitution for our debt (Swinburne), or in order to convince God
to forgive us of our debt to God (Quinn). Instead, the participatory account follows Paul in
drawing on Old Testament conceptions of sacrifice and expiation, on which one’s transgressions
are transferred to the animal, so that they die with the animal (see e.g. Childs 1992). Although
the participatory approach does not, as such, see participation as a mechanism for the transfer of
sin, it does build on the idea of participation and identification that is inherent in the notion of
the sacrificial animal.
The participatory model can also make sense of exemplary language, although it will regard
such language as highly impoverished if it is left to itself. The Christian is, of course, invited to
References
Aspenson, Steven S. (1990) “In Defence of Anselm,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 7/1: 33-45.
Campbell, D. (2001) “Natural Theology in Paul? Reading Romans I.19-20,” International Journal
of Systematic Theology, 1/3: 231-52.
Childs, B. S. (1992) Biblical Theology of the Old and New Testaments, London: SCM.
Fiddes, P. (1989) Past Event and Present Salvation: The Christian Idea of Atonement. London:
Darton, Longman and Todd.
Gorringe, T. (1996) God’s Just Vengeance: Crime, Violence and the Rhetoric of Salvation. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Hooker, M. (1994) Not Ashamed of the Gospel: New Testament Interpretations of the Death of Christ,
Carlisle: Paternoster.
Lucas, J.R. (1994) “Reflections on the Atonement,” In Alan G. Padgett (ed), Reason and the
Christian Religion: Essays in honour of Richard Swinburne, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Morris, L. (1966) The Cross in the New Testament. Exeter: Paternoster Press.
Packer, J. I. (1974) What did the Cross Achieve? The Logic of Penal Substitution. Leicester: TSF
Monograph.
Porter, S. (2002) “Rethinking the Logic of Penal Substitution,” In William Lane Craig (ed),
Philosophy of Religion: A Reader and Guide. Rutgers, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 596-608.
Purtill, R. (1991) “Justice, Mercy, Supererogation, and Atonement,” In Thomas P. Flint (ed),
Christian Philosophy, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 37-50.
Quinn, Philip L. (1986) “Christian Atonement and Kantian Justification,” Faith and Philosophy,
3: 440-62.
Taliaferro, C. (1988) “The Narnian Theory of the Atonement,” Scottish Journal of Theology,
XLI, 75-92.
Torrance, A. (2000) “Justification,” In Adrian Hastings, Alistair Mason, and Hugh Piper
(eds.), The Oxford Companion to Christian Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press.