Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Entropy 20 00381

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 17

Article

Observables and Unobservables in Quantum


Mechanics: How the No-Hidden-Variables
Theorems Support the Bohmian Particle Ontology
Dustin Lazarovici * ID
, Andrea Oldofredi * and Michael Esfeld *
Section de Philosophie, Université de Lausanne, 1015 Lausanne, Switzerland
* Correspondence: dustin.lazarovici@unil.ch (D.L.); andrea.oldofredi@unil.ch (A.O.);
michael-andreas.esfeld@unil.ch (M.E.)

Received: 23 April 2018; Accepted: 17 May 2018; Published: 18 May 2018

Abstract: The paper argues that far from challenging—or even refuting—Bohm’s quantum theory,
the no-hidden-variables theorems in fact support the Bohmian ontology for quantum mechanics.
The reason is that (i) all measurements come down to position measurements; and (ii) Bohm’s
theory provides a clear and coherent explanation of the measurement outcome statistics based on
an ontology of particle positions, a law for their evolution and a probability measure linked with that
law. What the no-hidden-variables theorems teach us is that (i) one cannot infer the properties that
the physical systems possess from observables; and that (ii) measurements, being an interaction like
other interactions, change the state of the measured system.

Keywords: no-hidden-variables theorems; observables; measurement problem; Bohmian mechanics;


primitive ontology

1. Introduction
The famous no-hidden-variables theorems have played a crucial, though often questionable
role in the history of quantum mechanics. For decades, they have been employed to defend the
quantum orthodoxy and to argue, nay prove, that any attempt to go beyond the statistical formalism of
standard quantum mechanics in providing a “complete” description of the microcosm is bound to fail.
Even after David Bohm [1] got “the impossible done” (as Bell [2] (p. 160) later put it) and showed how
the statistical predictions of quantum mechanics can be derived from an ontology of point particles
and a deterministic law of motion, many scientists and philosophers refused to pay attention to this
theory on the basis that the no-hidden-variables theorems had established that it couldn’t be correct
(one striking example of such a misunderstanding is Wigner [3] (pp. 53–55)).
Of course, Bohm’s theory is not a counterexample to these theorems qua mathematical theorems.
It is rather the most striking demonstration of the fact that these mathematical results do not support
the ideological conclusions in defense of which they have been generally cited. That notwithstanding,
it would be premature to dismiss the “no-go theorems” as physically and philosophically irrelevant.
They capture something not only about the nature of measurements and the statistical predictions of
quantum mechanics that strikes us as remarkable and contrary to classical intuitions, but also about
the nature of physical objects. The aim of this paper is to work out what exactly these theorems show
and how they support in fact Bohm’s quantum theory, instead of being an argument against it.
In the next section, we briefly recall the quantum orthodoxy and Bohm’s quantum theory.
Section 3 outlines three of the most important theorems useful for our discussion. Section 4 rebuts the
conclusions that are commonly drawn from them. Section 5 provides an account of the Bohmian theory
of measurements. Section 6 shows how it supports an ontology of point particles that are characterized
by their positions only. Section 7 draws a general conclusion.

Entropy 2018, 20, 381; doi:10.3390/e20050381 www.mdpi.com/journal/entropy


Entropy 2018, 20, 381 2 of 17

2. Quantum Orthodoxy and Bohmian Mechanics


In the words of David Mermin [4] (p. 803), the scope of the no-hidden-variables theorems is to
defend “a fundamental quantum doctrine”, namely that

(Q) A measurement does not, in general, reveal a preexisting value of the measured property.

However, accepting this doctrine leads to at least two urgent questions:

1. How do the quantum observables acquire definite values upon measurement?


It is now generally acknowledged that measurements are not a new type of interaction—let alone
a primitive metaphysical concept—that requires a special treatment, but come under the common
types of physical interactions (electromagnetism, gravitation, etc.). Hence, our physical theories
should be able, at least in principle, to describe them. This, in turn, entails that the notion of
measurement must not be part of the axioms of a physical theory. Thus, if quantum theory
implies that the observable values are not merely revealed but produced by the measurement
process—that is, by the interaction between the measurement device and the measured system,
the theory should tell us how they are produced.
2. What characterizes a physical system prior to—or better: independent of—measurement?
After all, there must be some sort of ontological underpinning to the measurement process
and the empirical data that it yields. That is, there must be something in the world on which
the measurement is actually performed—something with which the observer or measurement
device interacts, and there must be something definite about the physical state of the observer or
measurement device that does not, in turn, require a measurement of the measurement (and so
on, ad infinitum).

According to Mermin [4] (p. 803), the orthodox response to question 1 is that “Precisely how the
particular result of an individual measurement is brought into being—Heisenberg’s ‘transition from
the possible to the actual’—is inherently unknowable”. The response to 2 seems to be some sort of
radical idealism, expressed in his now famous assertion (and belated response to Einstein) according
to which the moon is demonstrably not there when nobody looks (Mermin [5]). Bohm’s theory entirely
rejects this way of talking. Its presentation as a “hidden variables theory” suggests that it denies
the doctrine Q. However, most contemporary Bohmians actually endorse this doctrine, and quite
emphatically so. Let us briefly recall why this is the case.
For present purposes, we use the formulation of Bohm’s theory that is today known as Bohmian
mechanics (see Dürr et al. [6]; for a discussion of the different contemporary formulations of Bohm’s
theory, see Belousek [7]; Bohm and Hiley [8] is the latest elaborate treatment by Bohm himself).
Bohmian mechanics can be defined in terms of the following four principles:

1. Particle configuration: There always is a configuration of N permanent point particles in the


universe that are characterized only by their positions X1 , . . . , X N in three-dimensional, physical
space at any time t.
2. Guiding equation: A wave function Ψ is attributed to the particle configuration, being the central
dynamical parameter for its evolution. On the fundamental level, Ψ is the universal wave function
attributed to all the particles in the universe together. The wave function has the task to determine
a velocity field along which the particles move, given their positions. It accomplishes this task by
figuring in the law of motion of the particles, which is known as the guiding equation:

dXk h̄ ∇ Ψ
= Im k ( X1 , . . . , X N ). (1)
dt mk Ψ

This equation yields the evolution of the k-th particle at a time t as depending on, via the wave
function, the position of all the other particles at that time.
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 3 of 17

3. Schrödinger equation: The wave function always evolves according to the Schrödinger equation:

∂Ψ N
h̄2
ih̄ =−∑ ∆ Ψ + VΨ. (2)
∂t k =1
2mk k

4. Typicality measure: On the basis of the universal wave function Ψ, a unique stationary
(more precisely: equivariant) typicality measure can be defined in terms of the |Ψ |2 –density
(see Goldstein and Struyve [9] for a proof and precise statement of the uniqueness result).
Given that typicality measure, it can then be shown that for nearly all initial conditions, the
distribution of particle configurations in an ensemble of sub-systems of the universe that admit
of a wave function ψ of their own (known as effective wave function) is a |ψ|2 –distribution.
A universe in which this distribution of the particles in sub-configurations obtains is considered
to be in quantum equilibrium.

Assuming that the actual universe is a typical Bohmian universe in that it is in quantum
equilibrium, one can hence deduce Born’s rule for the calculation of measurement outcome statistics
on sub-systems of the universe in Bohmian mechanics (instead of simply stipulating that rule).
In a nutshell, the axiom of |Ψ |2 providing a typicality measure with Ψ being the universal wave function
justifies applying the |ψ|2 –rule for the calculation of the probabilities of measurement outcomes on
particular sub-systems within the universe, with ψ being the effective wave function of the particular
systems in question (see Dürr et al. [6] (Chapter 2); cf. Section 5 for the notion of effective wave
functions). Thus, the quantum probabilities have in Bohmian mechanics exactly the same status as the
probabilities in classical statistical mechanics: they are derived from a deterministic law of motion via
an appropriate probability measure that is linked with the law. Moreover, if a sub-system admits for
an autonomous description in terms of an effective wave ψ, its complete physical and dynamical state
at any time t is given by the pair ( Xt , ψt ), where Xt = ( X1 (t), . . . , X M (t)) describes the actual spatial
configuration of the system.
Consequently, measurements of observables such as energy, angular momentum, spin, etc. do not
reveal predetermined properties of the particles, because Bohmian mechanics does not admit them
as intrinsic properties of the particles to begin with. Similarly, a simple analysis of the theory shows
that a measurement of the momentum observable does not, except under special circumstances,
measure the instantaneous velocity of a particle. It is a crucial feature of the theory that the only
property of the particles is their position in space. The particles have a velocity, of course, but velocity
is nothing else than the change of position in time. The Bohmian velocity is not an observable
(see Dürr et al. [6] (Chapter 3.7.2) for a simple proof, but also Wiseman [10] for the possibility of weak
measurements; see [6] (Chapter 7) for a good discussion of both results). And velocity is not—in
contrast to the Newtonian case—a dynamical degree of freedom that can be specified independently of
the position, because the guiding law (1) is a first order differential equation, requiring only positions
as initial data.
The first and foremost role of the wave function is a dynamical one, namely to yield the motion
of the particles as output, given their positions as input. This explains the name “pilot-wave theory”
historically given to Bohm’s theory, as if the particles were literally guided or piloted by a wave in
physical space. This way of speaking, however, cannot be taken literally, since the wave function is
defined on configuration space; it is not a wave propagating in physical space (for the debate about
the status of the wave function in Bohmian mechanics, see [11]). Even in the special case when the
wave function of a subsystem happens to be an eigenstate ψα of a certain observable  with eigenvalue
α—for instance after an ideal measurement—and it would be safe to say that “the particle possesses
a definite value of A”, this way of speaking is unwarranted. It should be replaced by the statement
that a (repeated) experiment, whose statistics is encoded in the operator Â, would yield the outcome
α with certainty; or simply by the statement that the effective wave function, guiding the motion of
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 4 of 17

the system, is ψα . In summary, the validity of doctrine Q is not denied, but substantiated by Bohmian
mechanics on the basis of this theory recognizing only a position as a property of the physical system.

3. No-Hidden-Variables Theorems
The basic question that the no-hidden-variables theorems set out to address is whether the
probabilistic nature of the quantum formalism allows for an ignorance interpretation in the sense that
the measured values of quantum observables are in fact predetermined by additional parameters,
whose actual values, in individual runs of an experiment, are unknown to us, but whose statistical
distributions over a series of measurements reproduce the observed outcome statistics. In more formal
terms, the question is whether for any relevant family of quantum observables Â, B̂, Ĉ, . . . there exists
a corresponding family of random variables Z A , ZB , ZC , . . . on a common probability space Ω such
that the values of these random variables correspond to the possible measurement outcomes—that is,
the eigenvalues of the observable operators. Any ω ∈ Ω would then be a value of the hypothetical
hidden variable(s), determining the measurement values Z A (ω ), ZB (ω ), ZC (ω ), . . ., and the quantum
predictions, for some quantum state ψ, would be reproduced by a probability distribution µψ over this
R
hidden variable, such as hψ| Â|ψi = Ω Z A (ω )dµψ (ω ), etc.
A no-hidden-variables theorem is thus, in general, a result of the following form (cf. Dürr et al. [6]
(Chapter 3)):

There is no “good” map  7→ Z A from the set of self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space H
to random variables on a common probability space Ω such that the possible values of Z A
correspond to the eigenvalues of  (that is, the possible measurement values).

The term “good map” is not quite precise, but deliberately so, for it is essentially on this
point—the requirements on the assignment  7→ Z A —that the various no-hidden-variables
theorems differ.

3.1. Von Neumann


The first no-hidden-variables theorem was proven by von Neumann in his seminal 1932 book
Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik ([12], English translation [13]). In this theorem, a “good”
map from observables to random variables was supposed to be linear, that is, in particular:

 + B̂ 7→ Z A+ B = Z A + ZB . (3)

It is easy to see that such a map cannot exist, since, for non-commuting operators, the eigenvalues
of their sum are in general not sums of their eigenvalues. Von Neumann’s linearity assumption was
arguably motivated by the additivity of quantum mechanical expectations values (hψ| Â + B̂|ψi =
hψ| Â|ψi + hψ| B̂|ψi holds for all observables Â, B̂ and any state ψ), but is nowadays considered as
rather naive (Mermin [4] (pp. 805–806) calls it “silly”). As Mermin [4] (p. 806) points out, requiring
Equation (3) “is to ensure that a relation holds in the mean by imposing it case by case—a sufficient, but
hardly a necessary condition”. In addition, the physical significance of this assumption—in particular
for non-commuting observables that cannot even simultaneously measured—is rather obscure. If, let
us say, X̂ is the position and P̂ the momentum observable, what is a “measurement of X̂ + P̂” even
supposed to mean? For decades, von Neumann’s impossibility proof was a key element in the defense
of the quantum orthodoxy, but it started to fall apart rather quickly, once people began to study it
more systematically.

3.2. Kochen–Specker
The theorem of Kochen and Specker [14] was a considerable improvement because it makes
a requirement for the “goodness” of the assignment  7→ Z A that seems a priori much more plausible:
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 5 of 17

(NC) Whenever the quantum mechanical joint distribution of a set of self-adjoint operators
( A1 , . . . , Am ) exists, that is, when they form a commuting family, the joint distribution of
the corresponding set of random variables, that is, of ( Z A1 , . . . , Z Am ), must agree with the
quantum mechanical joint distribution.

This assumption actually implies that all algebraic identities that hold between the observable
operators must also hold between the random variables (e.g., if Â × B̂ = B̂ × Â = Ĉ, it means that
the joint distribution is zero on the value set {(c 6= ab) | a, b, c eigenvalues of Â, B̂, Ĉ } and hence
Z A × ZB = ZC almost surely), but the condition is now only imposed on families of commuting
observables that can be jointly measured.
Families of commuting observables always have a common probability distribution (as random
variables on a classical probability space). So what could possibly go wrong? One can consider
an observable  once as part of a commuting family ( Â, B̂, Ĉ, . . .) and once as part of
a commuting family ( Â, L̂, M̂, . . .) such that B̂, Ĉ, . . . and L̂, M̂, . . . are incompatible—that is,
non-commuting—with each other. Assumption (NC) would be trivial if the observable  could
be associated with a random variable Z A , as part of the family ( Z A , ZB , ZC , . . . ), and another
random variable Z̃ A as part of the family ( Z̃ A , ZL , Z M , . . . ). The considered hidden-variables-schemes
presuppose, however, a rigid assignment  7→ Z A , independent of the measurement context. In other
words, Z A must be the same, whether  is measured together with B̂, Ĉ, . . . or together with L̂, M̂, . . . .
The crucial assumption underlying the no-go theorem of Kochen and Specker has thus been named
non-contextuality. The upshot is that non-contextual hidden variables are incompatible with the
predictions of quantum mechanics.
A particularly nice and simple proof is due to Mermin [4] (p. 810). It consists in the following
arrangement of 3 × 3 observables on a four-dimensional Hilbert space:

σx1 σx2 σx1 σx2 ,

σy2 σy1 σy1 σy2 ,

σx1 σy2 σx2 σy1 σz1 σz2 .


Using the standard commutation relations of the Pauli-matrices (“spin observables”) and the fact
that the possible eigenvalues are ±1, it is easy to verify that:

(a) The observables in each of the three rows and each of the three columns are
mutually commuting.
(b) The product of the three observables in each of the three rows is 1.
(c) The product of the three observables in first two columns is 1, while the product of the right
column is −1.

Thus, no consistent assignment of predetermined values to the nine observables is possible,


since identity (b) would require the product of all nine values to be +1, while (c) would require it to be
−1. This proves the Kochen–Specker theorem.

3.3. Bell
One of the more tragic chapters in the history of quantum mechanics is that, for many defenders of
the supposed orthodoxy, Bell’s theorem (reprinted in Bell [2] (Chapter 2)) has replaced von Neumann’s
as the mathematical result that finally spells the dead for any “completion” of the quantum formalism.
Certainly, the physical significance of Bell’s theorem can hardly be overstated, but to understand it as
just another no-hidden-variables argument is to miss the point entirely. Bell himself has addressed the
misunderstanding on various occasions, for instance:
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 6 of 17

My own first paper on this subject (Physics 1, 195 (1965)) starts with a summary of the EPR
argument from locality to deterministic hidden variables. However the commentators have
almost universally reported that it begins with deterministic hidden variables. (Bell [2]
(p. 157))
The point of Bell’s theorem is not hidden variables but nonlocality (see Maudlin [15] for an excellent
discussion). Bell’s analysis starts from the EPR argument that assumes locality and concludes that the
quantum formalism must be incomplete. EPR did indeed attack the quantum doctrine that observables
do not have predetermined values prior to measurement. In brief, they did so by noticing that,
when considering two entangled systems A and B, certain observable values of A can be determined
by measurements on the distant system B (and vice versa). However, this would presuppose some sort
of nonlocal influence unless these values were actually predetermined, prior to the measurement on the
distant system, by hidden variables (and thus only revealed rather than determined by our interaction
with the distant system).
Three decades later, Bell proved that even by introducing additional variables, the statistical
predictions of quantum mechanics cannot be reproduced without nonlocal influences. The conclusion
is thus that quantum mechanics is nonlocal, no matter what. In addition, since a substantial amount
of experimental evidence confirms the predictions of quantum mechanics, the conclusion is that any
correct theory of nature is nonlocal, no matter what. Nonlocality, in other words, is not the price
that we pay for introducing hidden variables. Hidden variables were Einstein’s hope for avoiding
the nonlocality of standard quantum mechanics, and Bell proved that this hope cannot be realized
because nonlocality is a fact of nature. Hence, using nonlocality as an argument against Bohmian
mechanics, or so-called ”hidden variables theories” in general, gets the issue completely wrong.
Quantum mechanics is nonlocal, and any extension of—or alternative to—quantum mechanics better
be nonlocal as well; otherwise, it is demonstrably wrong.

4. The Message of the Quantum


Thus, what is the upshot of the no-hidden-variables theorems? In this section, we consider some
common responses and briefly indicate why they are wrong-headed.

4.1. Completeness of Quantum Mechanics


The no-hidden-variables theorems are usually cited in support of the claim that standard quantum
mechanics is “complete”, that is, in particular, that the wave function or quantum state —with its role
in determining the probabilities of measurement outcomes—represents the complete physical state
of a quantum system. However, when used in this context, the traditional hidden variables program
seems to commit the following mistake that Einstein warned the young Heisenberg about:
I suspect that you will run into problems at exactly that part of your theory that we just talked
about . . . You pretend that you could leave everything as it is on the side of observations,
that is, that you could just talk in the former language about what physicists observe.
(Quoted after Heisenberg [16] (p. 89); translation by the authors.)
Indeed, the idea that physical observations must be reported in “classical language” (while the
same language is unable to provide an objective description of the microcosm) became one of the core
tenants of the so-called Copenhagen interpretation. This included the (at least tacit) assumption that
the relevant observables of quantum physics are just the familiar properties known from Newtonian
mechanics, or at least that the physical and ontological status of the properties, once measured, is the
same as had been generally assumed in classical physics, namely that the observables refer to intrinsic
properties of the physical systems. The no-hidden-variables theorems then show that the intrinsic
properties of physical systems, insofar as they are captured by observables, cannot have predetermined
values (unless one buys into undesirable consequences such as “contextuality” that seem to defeat the
purpose of assuming predetermined properties).
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 7 of 17

However, this orthodox way of reading the no-hidden-variables theorems directly runs into
the two questions raised in Section 2: How do the quantum observables acquire definite values
upon measurement? What characterizes a physical system prior to—or better: independent
of—measurement? The “industry of no-go theorems” (Laudisa [17]) drives us towards the negative
conclusion of no predetermined values, but it does not provide an answer to these questions. Instead
of this reading of no predetermined values of intrinsic properties of physical systems, there also is
another, arguably more radical reading of the no-hidden-variables theorems possible: they tell us
that observables do not correspond to properties of physical systems at all, so that the question of
predetermined values of such properties does not even arise. This is the Bohmian reading, which then
does provide an answer to these questions.

4.2. Metaphysical Indeterminacy


Following the lead of mainstream physics, the philosophical literature has recently developed
a renewed interest in the concept of metaphysical indeterminacy, which is intended in this context
to capture the idea that the values of quantum observables, prior to measurement, are not merely
unknown but, in a metaphysically robust sense, unspecified. According to Calosi and Wilson [18],
properties of quantum systems are metaphysically indeterminate in the sense that they have
a determinable property without a unique corresponding determinate. Thus, an electron, for instance,
possesses a determinable property “spin”, but its value is indeterminate until we actually measure it.
In contrast, and arguing against the concept of metaphysical indeterminacy, Glick [19] (p. 207)
proposes what he calls a “sparse view” of standard quantum mechanics:

Sparse view: when the quantum state of A is not in an eigenstate of Ô, it lacks both the
determinate and determinable properties associated with Ô.

Obviously, none of these views does anything to address the measurement problem, that is,
to clarify how a measurement turns an indeterminate—or non-existent—property of a physical system
into a determinate one. In addition, while this is not the issue of this particular philosophical discussion,
it certainly is dubious to base metaphysics on imprecise or even inconsistent physics.
Bohmian mechanics, by contrast, shows that there is no work to do for a concept of metaphysical
indeterminacy: the state of a physical system is completely and precisely determined, at any moment
in time, by the actual particle positions and the wave function, fixing how the positions change in time.
Furthermore, this theory supports a metaphysical view that is even sparser than the one advocated
by Glick: neither the determinate nor the determinable property associated with an observable Ô is
part of the ontology, independent of whether or not the quantum state of a system is an eigenstate or
not. The only property that particles have—and need—is a position in physical space (see Esfeld and
Deckert [20] for an elaboration on a sparse ontology in that sense).

4.3. Quantum Logic


One of the more audacious claims in support of which the no-hidden-variables theorems are
employed is that quantum mechanics compels us to give up classical logic in favor of a new quantum
logic. It is easy to see where this idea comes from. If we consider the simple example of spin
(for a spin-1/2-particle, to be discussed in detail in Section 5), it is tempting to assign to the proposition

q ∨ ¬q: The particle has z-spin up or z-spin down

the truth-value true. However, according to the doctrine Q, neither

q: The particle has z-spin up

nor

¬q: The particle has z-spin down


Entropy 2018, 20, 381 8 of 17

can be considered true prior to a measurement or unless the particle happens to be in a z-spin eigenstate.
Since Quine’s seminal paper “Two dogmas of empiricism” [21], it is widely accepted in philosophy
that not even a revision of the rules of logic is out of bounds when adjusting a theoretical system to
new empirical evidence, though they are the last knob to turn. In that vein, the first and most
important objection to quantum logic (as a proposal for the “true” logic of the physical world)
is not that it is a priori absurd, but that it is hardly justified by theoretical or explanatory merits.
Giving up on classical logic does nothing to address the two crucial questions formulated in Section 2.
The various proposed systems of “quantum logic” are merely modeled on the standard theory and
thus inherit all its problems—including the measurement problem. In particular, changing a logical
formalism does not elucidate the ontology of quantum mechanics, nor does it provide for a physical
account of when and why propositions involving quantum observables acquire definitive truth values.
Conversely, the example of Bohmian mechanics shows that once we have a clear ontology, and take
the measurement process seriously as part of the theory, no departure from classical logic is called for.

5. Measurements in Bohmian Mechanics: Spin


In this section, we explain how Bohmian mechanics treats measurement experiments, how this
treatment supports doctrine Q and what the consequences for the status of observables are.

5.1. The Bohmian Treatment of the Measurement Process


The solution to the measurement problem offered by Bohmian mechanics comes from a simple
idea: to describe quantum mechanically also the experimental devices, since macroscopic objects are
composed of microscopic objects. Thus, to describe experimental situations in Bohmian mechanics,
we split the total configuration (of, in the last resort, the entire universe) into ( X, Y ) ∈ R3M × R3( N − M)
where the former variable refers to the particle configuration of the investigated M-particle sub-system
and the latter to the configuration of the environment, which includes the particles of the measurement
device registering the outcomes in “pointer positions”. Fundamentally, in the Bohmian theory, there is
only one wave function, the universal wave function Ψ = Ψ ( x, y), guiding all the particles together
(the lower case variables refer to the possible configurations—Ψ is a function on the entire configuration
space—in contrast to the actual configurations denoted by upper case letters). However, by inserting
the actual configuration of the environment at time t, we get a conditional wave function, which is
a function of the degrees of freedom of the sub-system only:

ψt ( x ) := Ψt ( x, Yt ). (4)

This conditional wave function is always well-defined but not very useful in practice, since it has
a non-trivial dependence on the exact configuration of the environment. However, in some situations,
when the universal wave function takes the form

Ψ ( x, y) = ψ( x )Φ(y) + Ψ ⊥ ( x, y), (5)

where Φ(y) and Ψ ⊥ ( x, y) have macroscopically disjoint support in the y-variables and Yt ∈ supp Φ,
i.e., Ψ ⊥ ( x, Yt ) = 0 ∀ x, we can for all practical purposes forget about the “empty” wave Ψ ⊥ and
provide an autonomous description of the subsystem in terms of the effective wave function ψ, which is
the Bohmian analog to the usual wave function used in textbook quantum mechanics. Now, let
us consider an ideal measurement associated with an “observable” with eigenvalues α1 , . . . , αn and
n
corresponding eigenstates ϕ1 , . . . , ϕn . In general, ψ will be a superposition ψ = ∑ ci ϕi , ci ∈ C.
i =1
Under the Schrödinger evolution—after the subsystem has coupled to the measurement device in the
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 9 of 17

course of the measurement process—the state of system + environment (ignoring again the empty part
of the wave function Ψ ⊥ ) will thus have the form
n
Ψ( x, y) = ∑ ci ϕi (x)Φi (y), (6)
i =1

where the environment states Φi are concentrated, in particular, on different pointer configurations,
indicating the measurement outcomes αi , and have therefore pairwise disjoint supports in configuration
space. Note that it is only for simplicity that we do not distinguish between the degrees of freedom of
the measurement device and the rest of the universe, subsuming both in the “environment” (y-system).
However, the actual configuration Y of the universe (pointer) will lie inside only one of the branches,
let us say Y ∈ supp Φk . Hence, the actual pointer configuration will indicate the measurement
outcome αk and the new effective (=conditional) wave function of the subsystem becomes
ψY ( x ) = ck ϕk ( x )Φk (Y ) =
ˆ ϕk after normalization. Hence, while the universal wave function always
evolves according to the linear Schrödinger equation, the effective wave function automatically
collapses into the eigenstate corresponding to the registered measurement result (for a detailed
exposition see Dürr and Teufel [22] (Chapter 9)).
This account notably has the following five features:
1. There never are superpositions of anything in physical space. All there is in physical space
are particle configurations with always definite positions. Thus, Schrödinger’s cat always is in
a configuration of either a live cat or a dead cat. Superpositions concern only the wave function
in physical space in its role to determine the trajectories on which the particles move.
2. Consequently, quantum logic is irrelevant when it comes to an account of measurement:
the particle configuration belongs unambiguously to one of the possible supports of the wave
function, which in turn correspond to macroscopically different components of the experimental
device, determining in this way the final outcome of the observation at hand.
3. Nevertheless, there is entanglement in physical space: the motion of any particle depends on,
strictly speaking, the positions of all the other particles in the universe via the wave function.
Thus, for instance, in the double slit experiment, the motion of any particle after having passed one
slit depends on the position of all the particles making up the experimental set-up, in particular
on whether or not the other slit is open. This is the way in which Bohmian mechanics implements
the quantum nonlocality proven by Bell’s theorem. The consequence is that the trajectories of the
particles often are highly non-classical.
4. A measurement is an interaction that will in general change the wave function of
the measured system. “Incompatible measurements”—corresponding to non-commuting
observables—are simply experiments in which the first measurement interaction changes the
wave function in a way that influences the statistics of the second, etc.
5. The fact that we cannot go beyond Born’s rule in making predictions is explained not by
any indeterminacy of the properties of the particles, or any indeterminism of the dynamics,
but by the fact that we cannot have more precise knowledge of the initial particle configuration.
As mentioned in Section 2, in Bohmian mechanics, Born’s rule is derived from the laws of motion
plus a probability (more precisely: typicality) measure linked with these laws.
Once “measurements” and “observations” are no longer treated as primitive but as physical
processes, to be analyzed on the basis of a precise microscopic theory, it turns out that the quantum
orthodoxy was right about the fact that measurements do not reveal preexisting values of observables,
but wrong about the idea that these observables correspond to properties of physical systems.
The important contrast between classical and quantum mechanics that the no-hidden-variables
theorems reveal is thus not that quantum phenomena are irreducibly random, but rather that quantum
phenomena are at odds with a metaphysics of intrinsic properties that classical mechanics did not
necessitate but indulge.
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 10 of 17

5.2. What Is Measured in a Spin Measurement?


Let us now discuss a Stern–Gerlach spin measurement, as the simplest but maybe most
instructive example of a measurement process in Bohmian mechanics. In this famous experiment,
a spin-1/2-particle (originally a silver atom) is sent through an inhomogeneous magnetic field
(Stern–Gerlach magnet) and then registered on a detector screen, where one observes a deviation
perpendicular to the flight direction and parallel or anti-parallel to the gradient of the magnetic field.
To describe the experiment theoretically, we consider the propagation of a concentrated
wave packet     
1 0
Φ0 = ϕ0 (z) α +β (7)
0 1
through an inhomogeneous magnetic field with the gradient in the z-direction. We ignore the
components of the wave-function in the x, y-directions and the spatial spreading of the wave function,
assuming that the flight time is reasonably short. A straightforward computation using the Pauli
equation (which is the non-relativistic limit of the Dirac equation, describing the time evolution of a
spinor-valued wave function in an external electromagnetic field) then shows that the equations for
the two spin-components decouple and that each acquires a phase

µbτ (n)
Φ(n) (τ ) = exp[i(−1)n+1 z] Φ0 ,

where τ is the time spent in the magnetic field, corresponding to a group velocity of

µbτ
vz = (−1)n+1 .
m
The inhomogeneous magnetic field thus leads to a spatial separation of the wave packets,
corresponding to the spin-components: The wave packet Φ(1) (t) = αϕ1 (t, z)(10) propagates in the
positive z-direction (in the direction of the gradient of the magnetic field) and the wave packet
Φ(2) (t) = βϕ2 (t, z)(01) in the negative z-direction. Assuming that the two wave packets remain
reasonably well localized, they will have approximately disjoint supports after a little while, that is,
Φ(1) is concentrated above the symmetry axis and Φ(2) below. It is important to emphasize that this is
purely a result of the Schrödinger (respectively Pauli) time evolution, which is part of every quantum
theory, independent of interpretative issues.
However, in Bohmian mechanics (and only there), it now makes sense to ask whether the particle
moves upwards—guided by the wave packet Φ(1) —or downwards, guided by the wave packet Φ(2) .
In the first case, it would hit a detector screen above the symmetry axis and one says that “the particle
has z-spin up”; in the second case, it would hit a detector screen below the symmetry axis and one
says that “the particle has z-spin down”. However, this is a rather unfortunate way of speaking.
Spin is not a property that the particle possesses over and above its position. To “have” spin up or
spin down means nothing more and nothing less than to be guided by the part of the wave function
that corresponds to the upper or lower spinor-component (in the z-spin basis)—that is, to move, in the
pertinent measurement context, in the respective way. In other words: spin is a degree of freedom of
the wave function (related to its transformation under rotations) that manifests itself, under certain
circumstances, in a particular kind of particle motion. As such, it belongs to the dynamical structure of
the theory, not to the ontology of objects in physical space (see also Bell [2] (Chapter 4) and Norsen [23]).
According to Born’s rule for the particle positions, we can compute the probability of finding the
particle with “spin up”, that is, in the support of Φ(1) , or “spin down”, that is, in the support of Φ(2) as:
Z
P(“z-spin up”) = P( X ∈ supp Φ(1) ) = |Φ(1) (t, z)|2 dz = |α|2 ,
supp Φ(1)
Z (8)
P(“z-spin down”) = P( X ∈ supp Φ(2) ) = |Φ(2) (t, z)|2 dz = | β|2 .
supp Φ(2)
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 11 of 17

Obviously, these probabilities can already be computed from the initial state, using the projections
on the respective spin-components:

P(“z-spin up”) = hΦ0 | ↑ih↑ |Φ0 i = |α|2 ,


(9)
P(“z-spin down”) = hΦ0 | ↓ih↓ |Φ0 i = | β|2 .

Finally, assigning to “spin up” and “spin down” the numerical values ± 2h̄ , the expectation value
is computed as
h̄   h̄
hΦ0 | |↑ih↑| − |↓ih↓| |Φ0 i = hΦ0 |σz |Φ0 i. (10)
2 2
In standard quantum mechanics, the operator 2h̄ σz has developed a certain life of its own as
the “spin observable”. The Bohmian analysis reveals it to be nothing more and nothing less than
a convenient book-keeper of the measurement statistics (for a general discussion of observables and
operators in Bohmian mechanics, see Dürr et al. [6]) (Chapter 3). We should note that the example of
spin is particular in Bohmian mechanics in that the statistical analysis does not require the coupling to
a measurement device. It makes sense to ask whether the particle moves upwards or downwards after
passing the Stern–Gerlach magnet, without considering a screen or detector in which its position is
finally recorded. In many cases, though, the “observable values” have meaning only insofar as their
are registered in some sort of “pointer” configuration.
It is interesting to observe that all precise formulations of quantum mechanics, which solve the
measurement problem, agree on this basic point that the measured values are produced rather than
revealed by the interaction between system and measurement device. According to spontaneous collapse
theories (such as the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber (GRW) theory), it is the Stern–Gerlach magnet that causes
the wave packets to separate and the subsequent coupling to a detector (screen) that (very very likely)
causes a collapse and forces the system to go into one of the possible outcomes. According to the more
sophisticated versions of many-worlds, it is the splitting of the wave packets in the Stern–Gerlach
magnet and the subsequent interaction with a detector that leads to decoherence and a branching into
“worlds”, in which the detector has registered “spin up” and “spin down”, respectively.
Only in Bohmian mechanics, however, is a unique measurement outcome determined by
the initial position of the particle and the deterministic law of motion (Collapse theories are
fundamentally stochastic, while, in many-worlds theories, measurements do not have unique
outcomes). That notwithstanding, it would be misleading to say that the particle possesses
a predetermined spin, irrespective of the measurement context. In particular, what we end up
calling the “spin value” is a number that encodes the result of the measurement interaction—how the
particle moves after passing the magnetic field—by contrast to an additional physical quantity that
determines it.

5.3. Is Bohmian Mechanics “Contextual”?


In fact, this confusion between “predetermined outcomes” and “predetermined properties” is all
there is to the discussion of contextuality in Bohmian mechanics. What this theory rejects is the “naive
realism about operators” or observables (Daumer et al. [24])—these unholy and categorically confused
amalgams of self-adjoint operators, physical properties, and observed data points. As mentioned
before, observables play no fundamental role in the theory; they merely arise, in a statistical analysis,
as book-keepers of outcome statistics. Consequently, they are not properties of anything. It is simply
wrong, and giving rise to further confusion, to call them “contextual properties” of physical systems.
In fact, different experimental setups associated with the same “observable” may have nothing in
common besides the fact that they are associated with the same statistical book-keeping operator.
To illustrate this point, let us return to Mermin’s proof of the Kochen–Specker theorem
(see Section 3.2) and focus, for instance, on the observable σx1 σx2 in the upper right corner of his scheme.
This observable can be trivially measured together with σx1 and σx2 : Take two spin-1/2-particles and
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 12 of 17

measure their x-spin separately in the way described above. Assign the value +1 if the particle moves
in positive x-direction and −1 if the particle moves in negative x-direction and compute the product
of the outcome values to obtain “the value of σx1 σx2 ”. However how to measure σx1 σx2 together with
σy1 σy2 and σz1 σz2 ? We have no idea, actually. In any case, one cannot simply measure the x-spin of
particle 1 and 2 separately, as before, since this would preclude the simultaneous measurement of σy1 σy2
and σz1 σz2 . Hence, whatever an experimentalist would have to do to perform a joint measurement of
(σx1 σx2 , σy1 σy2 , σz1 σz2 )—and whatever the physical significance of this measurement might be—it certainly
requires a completely different experiment than the measurement of (σx1 , σx2 , σx1 σx2 ).
In Bohmian mechanics, the initial state (wave-function + positions) of the particles (possibly
together with the initial state of the experimental setup) would determine the outcome of
“the σx1 σx2 -measurement” in both experiments, but there is simply no reason why these outcomes must
in every case agree. A disagreement would be troubling only if one assumed that the particles actually
have a preexisting σx1 σx2 -property that both experiments are supposed to reveal by different methods.
However this is just not the case in Bohmian mechanics. Furthermore, taking the physical situation
seriously, there is no reason why it should be the case in any reasonable theory. As Goldstein [25]
notes: “If we avoid naive realism about operators, contextuality amounts to little more than the rather
unremarkable observation that results of experiments should depend on how they are performed . . . ”.

5.4. Why Measurements?


Nonetheless, since, according to Bohmian mechanics, the outcome of any measurement is
determined by the initial state of the system (or at least of system + apparatus), the measurement
outcome does reveal a certain amount of information about the state of the system prior to
measurement. In fact, in some cases, the Bohmian theory allows us to infer significantly more
information about the measured system than standard quantum mechanics does. If we consider,
for instance, a z-spin measurement on a particle in the spin state √1 (| ↑z i + | ↓z i) and assume that the
2
setup is reasonably symmetric about the incident axis, we can infer from the “no-crossing property”
of Bohmian trajectories that if a particle hits the screen above/below the symmetry axis (corresponding
to z-spin up or z-spin down, respectively), its initial position must have been above/below the
symmetry axis as well.
In general, though, a quantum experiment provides more information about the state of the
system after the measurement process. In particular, if we perform an ideal (projective) measurement
and find a non-degenerate eigenvalue α of some observable Â, we know that the effective quantum
state of the system after the measurement is the corresponding eigenstate ψα . According to Bohmian
mechanics, this quantum state is an objective physical degree of freedom of the system (in accordance
with the Pusey–Barrett–Rudolph (PBR) theorem [26]), providing statistical information about the
particle configuration and determining its state of motion. It is thus highly informative about the
future behavior of the system. Note, however, that it would be wrongheaded to interpret the effective
quantum state as an additional intrinsic property of the particles, a) because one can, in general, assign a
wave function only to the subsystem as a whole but not to each particle individually (non-separability)
and b) because the effective wave function depends—implicitly—on the universal wave function and
the configuration of all the other particles in the universe (cf. Equations (4) and (5)).
Orthodox quantum mechanics agrees that a measurement provides, in general, more information
about the post-measurement state of the system, but would, strictly speaking, disagree on what the
information is actually about. The disagreement can be summarized as follows: According to Bohmian
mechanics, the “observable values” are best understood as encoding information about the quantum
state (i.e. the dynamical state) of the system, while according to standard quantum mechanics (or at
least most versions thereof), the quantum state is understood as encoding information about the
observable values. What makes the Bohmian view more coherent is the fact that the observable values
per se—in contrast to the quantum state—have no causal role within the theory (except maybe for
conserved quantities, but even those get their physical significance mostly in the “classical limit”).
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 13 of 17

To appreciate this point, it might be helpful to engage in a little thought exercise: Suppose we write
down some abstract self-adjoint operator  on a Hilbert space and tell you that a certain physical
system (an electron, let us say) has the value α of this “observable”. What information have we actually
given you about the world? How would you (or any other physical system) have to interact with the
electron to “notice” that it has the Â-value α rather than α0 ? Try to answer these questions by taking
the physical theory seriously, whatever you consider quantum theory to be.

6. Are Observables Observable?


The suggestive but misleading terminology of “measuring an observable” has not only lead to
a naive realism, but also to a naive empiricism about observables in quantum mechanics. It is usually
taken for granted that all empirical data underlying quantum physics consist in measured values
of observables, represented by—or corresponding to—self-adjoint operators. Against this backdrop,
our previous analysis seems to lead to a certain dilemma. Since the measured values of quantum
observables are emergent in a measurement process, they must emerge from an underlying ontology
that is not itself characterized in terms of definite values of quantum observables. This seems to leave
us with two possible options:
1. The physical properties are not observable.
2. The physical properties are a small subset of the observables (small enough to avoid the
no-hidden-variables results).
Both options invite criticism. In the first case, the underlying ontology would have no direct
empirical basis. The second option is open to the charge of arbitrariness, as it seems to reify some
observable properties but not others that have the same empirical status. In fact, both lines of attack
are occasionally used against Bohmian mechanics, the first in form of the claim that “the Bohmian
trajectories cannot be observed”, the second in form of the question “why take the position as your
‘hidden variable’ and not something else?”. While some interesting remarks could be made in response
to these objections, we want to take a step back and question the basic assumption that the “observables”
are somehow a priori given as fundamental objects of empirical observation.
Consider the following image (Figure 1) from an original Stern–Gerlach experiment, reported as
the first experimental observation of a “quantized direction (Richtungsquantelung)” of the angular
momentum/magnetic moment of atoms in an external magnetic field (Gerlach and Stern [27]).
Should we say that what was actually observed in this experiment—what the empirical data consists
in—is the particles’ spin?

Figure 1. Pattern created by a ray of silver atoms in the original Stern–Gerlach experiment: left: without,
right: with magnetic field.

Evidently, our more immediate observation is that of dark marks on a screen, the “non-classical
two-valuedness” being manifested in the distinct separation of the arcs on both sides of the symmetry
axis, when the magnetic field is turned on. In addition, evidently, the statistics of “spin up” and “spin
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 14 of 17

down” (deviation to the right/left) alone are too coarse-grained to capture all observable details of
the pattern.
However, this now puts the orthodox view in a predicament. Either quantum mechanics could
describe the experiment, in more detail, as series of position measurements (the points of impact
of the atoms building up the pattern on the screen); then, the spin observable is redundant or,
at least, derivative upon the observable “position”—or standard quantum mechanics somehow
compels us to describe this experiment as a measurement of “spin”. Then, the theory is empirically
incomplete, since it cannot—even statistically and in principle—account for all observable details of
the experimental outcome.
In general, all that we observe are the positions of discrete objects and the change of these positions.
Of course, there is more to these discrete objects than their mere positions, that is, spatial relationships
and change of these relationships. They notably have different colors, which makes it possible to
discern them in perception. However, color perception is not an observable that figures in any physical
theory, and the quantum observables do not help us to come up with an account of color perception.
In electromagnetism, “colors” are identified with certain wavelengths in the electromagnetic field.
However, the electromagnetic field should be first and foremost understood in terms of its role for the
motion of particles (and be it particles in our visual receptors). In other words, we do not observe fields,
but only certain patterns of motion that we explain and calculate in terms of fields (cf. Lazarovici [28]).
For classical electrodynamics, even a field free formulation is available, namely the one of Wheeler
and Feynman [29], which may have a number of drawbacks, but certainly does not fail for the reason
that it denies alleged field observations. By the same token, even in the case of the gravitational waves
detected by LIGO (Laser Interferometer Gravitational-Wave Observatory) in 2016, all the evidence is
evidence of change in the relative positions of particles, which is then mathematically described in
terms of a wave rippling through the gravitational field.
Bell [2] (p. 166) considered it to be the first and foremost lesson of Bohmian mechanics that

in physics the only observations we must consider are position observations, if only the
positions of instrument pointers. It is a great merit of the de Broglie–Bohm picture to force
us to consider this fact. If you make axioms, rather than definitions and theorems, about the
“measurement” of anything else, then you commit redundancy and risk inconsistency.

This crucial point applies to the whole of physics. Also in classical mechanics, we do not observe
mass when we observe gravitational attraction, and we do not literally see angular momentum when
we notice the regular motion of the moon around the earth. What we observe is just that: certain
regularities in the motion of matter, which are captured by the dynamical structure of the theory.
Hence, even in classical physics, quantities like energy, momentum, angular momentum, etc.
get their meaning and relevance from what they tell us about the way matter moves. The same applies
also to the classical parameters of mass and charge. Ernst Mach [30] (p. 241) highlighted this issue
when he emphasized in his comment on Newton’s Principia that “The true definition of mass can be
deduced only from the dynamical relations of bodies”. In Bohmian mechanics, then, the way matter
moves is encoded in the wave function, making all additional properties unnecessary or redundant
(mass and charge, as well, are best understood as situated on the level of the wave function, instead
of being intrinsic properties of the particles, see most recently Pylkkänen [31] and Esfeld et al. [32]).
This is the basic reason why Bohmian mechanics endorses doctrine Q. In that respect, the lesson of
the no-hidden-variables theorems is that in quantum mechanics, one cannot treat the observables as
properties of the physical systems, whereas in classical mechanics, one does not run into a problem with
the physics if one regards quantities like energy, momentum, angular momentum, etc. as properties of
the physical systems (although there is no cogent reason to do so in classical physics either).
Any quantum theory that admits what is known as a primitive ontology of matter in physical
space privileges position—be it the position of permanent particles as in the Bohm theory, be it the
value of the density of matter at the points of physical space as in the GRWm theory, or be it single
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 15 of 17

events (flashes) occurring at some points of space as in the GRWf theory (see Allori et al. [33]). In all
these theories, the quantum observables are construed on the basis of the positions of objects, namely
in terms of how these positions behave in certain experimental contexts. Also in the many worlds
theory, which does not recognize a primitive ontology of matter in physical space, but proposes an
ontology in terms of the universal wave function, position is privileged: it is the position basis in
which the wave function decoheres, splitting into different branches, which constitute “many worlds”
on this view.

7. Conclusions
What we perceive with the naked eye are the positions of macroscopic objects. However, we
know from scientific experience that the macroscopic objects are composed of discrete microscopic
objects. If the macroscopic objects have precise positions when we observe them, so do the microscopic
objects. There is no coherent theory of a magic power of the mind to change macroscopic objects in
such a way that they acquire positions only when a being with a mind perceives them. Thus, the
macroscopic objects better have positions independently of someone observing them. If not the moon,
so surely the desk in my office is there also when I do not observe it. However then it follows that
also the microscopic objects that compose these macroscopic objects do have positions independently
of them being observed. Again, there is no coherent theory according to which there is something
special about the microscopic objects that compose my desk and the like. Thus, the conclusion is that
the microscopic objects tout court have a position independently of them being observed.
Bohmian mechanics shows how to build a quantum theory on this simple and obvious reasoning.
Superpositions then concern only the parameter that encodes the dynamics of the particles, namely the
wave function, but not the particles themselves. This insight is the key to answering the two questions
raised at the beginning of this paper and to avoid all the puzzles of standard quantum mechanics,
such as notably the measurement problem. However, as it is trivial that physical objects have positions,
so it is trivial that in order to access these positions, we have to interact with these objects and thereby
change their positions. Generally speaking, for one particle configuration, say a macroscopic object,
to contain information about the positions of other particles, there must be a correlation between
them, which is, furthermore, reliable in the sense of being reproducible. This applies in particular
to correlations between particle configurations in human brains and particles outside the brains,
assuming that all the perceptual knowledge that persons acquire passes through their brains.
Hence, for reasons stemming from the very way in which we acquire knowledge about the natural
world, a limited accessibility of physical objects is to be expected. In that sense, classical mechanics is
an idealization, and quantum mechanics brings out that limitation on our knowledge. In Bohmian
mechanics, this is done in the theorem of “absolute uncertainty” (Dürr et al. [6] (Chapter 2)), stating
that we cannot have more information about the actual particle configuration of a sub-system than
what is provided by the |ψ|2 -distribution in terms of its effective wave function. That notwithstanding,
there is, of course, no question of an a priori deduction of this theorem—or the Heisenberg uncertainty
relations—from general conditions of our knowledge. It is just that some principled limit on our
knowledge of particular matters of fact—such as initial conditions of physical systems—is to
be expected.
If the evolution of the physical systems is highly sensitive to slight variations in their initial
conditions, as is the case with quantum systems, it then follows that in general we can only make
statistical predictions about the behavior of ensembles of physical systems prepared under the same
conditions, but not predictions about the evolution of an individual system, although the laws of
motion that govern the evolution of these systems can be fully deterministic (cf. Oldofredi et al. [34]).
Again, classical mechanics is deceptively generous in this respect, and quantum mechanics brings out
a fact that turns out to be trivial upon reflection (and actually comes out already in classical statistical
mechanics): deterministic laws require a probability measure to yield predictions, which then are
statistical. However, all these are facts about epistemology, the theory of knowledge—as the word
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 16 of 17

“uncertainty relations” clearly brings out, and not about ontology, that is, about what there is in
the world.
Nonetheless, the no-hidden-variables theorems have a great merit: they tell us that a sparse
ontology of positions is not just good metaphysics, but strongly suggested by our best theory of physics.
In classical mechanics, one can attribute dynamical parameters and all sorts of “observables”, which are
functions of the particle positions and momenta, as intrinsic properties to the particles. This does
not lead to conflict with the phenomena because the active role of the measurement process—both in
producing the data and in changing the state of the measured system—can be usually neglected in the
classical regime. In quantum mechanics, as we have seen, the situation is markedly different. The moral
then is of course not that there is nothing if one cannot go from observables to ontology, but that one
has to start with conceiving a—provisional, hypothetical—ontology for whose evolution the dynamical
parameters then are formulated. The guideline for this is the experimental evidence together with the
coherence and explanatory fruitfulness of the proposed ontology. Bohmian mechanics shows how the
simplest suggestion in that respect—the evidence of discrete objects and their composition by discrete
micro-objects suggesting to try out a particle ontology—can go through also in the quantum case and
yield all the explanations that one can reasonably demand.
In a nutshell, the lesson of the no-hidden-variables theorems is that it is position only when it
comes to the ontology of the physical world, and Bohmian mechanics teaches us how to do physics on
that basis (see Esfeld and Deckert [20] for a general treatment of that insight from classical mechanics
to quantum field theory). Note that this is not about classical vs. quantum. The ontology neither is
classical nor quantum. The dynamics may be classical (as in local field theories) or quantum. What a
quantum dynamics has to be subsequent to Bell’s theorem is clearly brought out by the nonlocality
implemented in the Bohm theory. There is no a priori explanation of why the dynamics of the world is
nonlocal. However, this nonlocality fundamentally deviates from the ideas that drive classical field
theory, showing a profound interconnectedness (holism) of the things in the universe.

Author Contributions: Conceptualization, D.L. and M.E.; Writing—Original Draft Preparation, D.L.;
Writing—Review & Editing, A.O. and M.E.; Visualization, A.O.; Supervision, M.E.
Funding: Andrea Oldofredi acknowledges funding from the Swiss National Science Foundation (SNSF), grant
number 105212_175971.
Acknowledgments: We are grateful to Detlef Dürr and three anonymous referees for helpful suggestions to
improve the manuscript.
Conflicts of Interest: The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References
1. Bohm, D. A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables, I and II. Phys. Rev.
1952, 85, 166–193. [CrossRef]
2. Bell, J.S. Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, 2nd ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge,
UK, 2004.
3. Wigner, E. Review of Quantum Mechanical Measurement Problem. In Quantum Optics, Experimental Gravity
and Measurement Theory; Meystre, P., Scully, O., Eds.; Plenum Press: New York, NY, USA, 1983.
4. Mermin, N.D. Hidden variables and the two theorems of John Bell. Rev. Mod. Phys. 1993, 65, 803–815.
[CrossRef]
5. Mermin, N.D. Is the moon there when nobody looks? Reality and the quantum theory. Phys. Today 1985,
38, 38–47. [CrossRef]
6. Dürr, D.; Goldstein, S.; Zanghì, N. Quantum Physics without Quantum Philosophy; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg,
Germany, 2013.
7. Belousek, D.W. Formalism, ontology and methodology in Bohmian mechanics. Found. Sci. 2003, 8, 109–172.
[CrossRef]
8. Bohm, D.; Hiley, B.J. The Undivided Universe. An Ontological Interpretation of Quantum Theory; Routledge:
London, UK, 1993.
Entropy 2018, 20, 381 17 of 17

9. Goldstein, S.; Struyve, W. On the uniqueness of quantum equilibrium in Bohmian mechanics. J. Stat. Phys.
2007, 128, 1197–1209. [CrossRef]
10. Wiseman, H.M. Grounding Bohmian Mechanics in Weak Values and Bayesianism. New J. Phys. 2007, 9, 165.
[CrossRef]
11. Esfeld, M.; Lazarovici, D.; Hubert, M.; Dürr, D. The ontology of Bohmian mechanics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2014,
65, 773–796. [CrossRef]
12. Von Neumann, J. Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1932.
13. Von Neumann, J. Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ,
USA, 1955.
14. Kochen, S.; Specker, E. The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. J. Math. Mech. 1967, 17, 59–87.
[CrossRef]
15. Maudlin, T. What Bell Did. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 2014, 47, 424010. [CrossRef]
16. Heisenberg, W. Der Teil und das Ganze: Gespräche im Umkreis der Atomphysik, 9th ed.; Piper Verlag: Munich,
Germany, 2012. (In German)
17. Laudisa, F. Against the ‘no-go’ philosophy of quantum mechanics. Eur. J. Philos. Sci. 2014, 4, 1–17. [CrossRef]
18. Calosi, C.; Wilson, J. Quantum Metaphysical Indeterminacy. 2017. Available online: https://philpapers.org/
rec/CALQMI (accessed on 5 May 2018).
19. Glick, D. Against quantum indeterminacy. Thought J. Philos. 2017, 6, 204–213. [CrossRef]
20. Esfeld, M.; Deckert, D.A. A Minimalist Ontology of the Natural World; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2017.
21. Van Orman Quine, W. Two dogmas of empiricism. Philos. Rev. 1951, 60, 20–43. [CrossRef]
22. Dürr, D.; Teufel, S. Bohmian Mechanics: The Physics and Mathematics of Quantum Theory; Springer:
Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009.
23. Norsen, T. The pilot-wave perspective on spin. Am. J. Phys. 2014, 82, 337–348. [CrossRef]
24. Daumer, M.; Dürr, D.; Goldstein, S.; Zanghì, N. Naive realism about operators. Erkenntnis 1996, 45, 379–397.
25. Goldstein, S. Bohmian Mechanics; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Stanford, CA, USA, 2017.
26. Pusey, M.F.; Barrett, J.; Rudolph, T. On the Reality of the Quantum State. Nat. Phys. 2012, 8, 476–479.
[CrossRef]
27. Gerlach, W.; Stern, O. Der experimentelle Nachweis der Richtungsquantelung im Magnetfeld. Z. Phys. 1922,
9, 349–352. (In German)
28. Lazarovici, D. Against Fields. Eur. J. Philos. Sci. 2018, 8, 145–170. [CrossRef]
29. Wheeler, J.A.; Feynman, R.P. Interaction with the absorber as the mechanism of radiation. Rev. Mod. Phys.
1945, 17, 157–181. [CrossRef]
30. Mach, E. The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development, 4th ed.; Open Court:
Chicago, IL, USA, 1919.
31. Pylkkänen, P.; Hiley, B.J.; Pättiniemi, I. Bohm’s approach and individuality. In Individuals across the Sciences;
Guay, A., Pradeu, T., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015; Chapter 12, pp. 226–246.
32. Esfeld, M.; Lazarovici, D.; Lam, V.; Hubert, M. The physics and metaphysics of primitive stuff. Br. J. Philos. Sci.
2017, 68, 133–161. [CrossRef]
33. Allori, V.; Goldstein, S.; Tumulka, R.; Zanghì, N. On the common structure of Bohmian mechanics and the
Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber theory. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2008, 59, 353–389. [CrossRef]
34. Oldofredi, A.; Lazarovici, D.; Deckert, D.A.; Esfeld, M. From the universe to subsystems: Why quantum
mechanics appears more stochastic than classical mechanics. Fluct. Noise Lett. 2016, 15, 164002. [CrossRef]

c 2018 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access
article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution
(CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).

You might also like