Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu

2021, "The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare" (updated and corrected version, 2022)

2021, W. Heckel; F.S. Naiden; E.E. Garvin; J. Vanderspoel, eds., A Companion to Greek Warfare, Wiley-Blackwell

PART II Military Operations CHAPTER 6 The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare Fernando Echeverría During the Archaic period (roughly 750–500), the emerging communities in Greece embarked on intermittent episodes of conflict with each other that entailed the mobilization of armies and fleets. At the same time, some of them were founding new settlements abroad, others exploring routes for trade and piracy, and others still reaching the mighty powers in the East to trade, raid, and sometimes fight. All those situations were potential scenarios for military conflict, determined to a great extent by the culture of the polis but definitely not circumscribed to it. Unfortunately, the fragmentary state of our sources leaves us uncertain about how those wars were fought and through which means and practices. The study of warfare in the Archaic period relies on a handful of poetic narratives (epic) and fragments (lyric), an immense but problematic stock of iconographic material (paintings and sculptures), and a considerable yet still expanding collection of artifacts (mainly arms and armor). However, we lack the kind of historical and detailed narratives that we find during the Classical period (such as Herodotus, Thucydides, and Xenophon), and here is where the trouble begins.1 This scattered, fragmentary, unsystematic, and sometimes even contradictory evidence led late nineteenth-century scholars to believe that there was a broad gap between the warfare and society depicted in the Homeric epics and those described by the Classical sources; radical changes had to be hypothesized if the gap was to be filled. Over more than a century, scholars introduced new aspects into the debate, such as politics, society, economy, or technology, combining the scattered pieces into a single picture: the result was the so-called “hoplite revolution,” a holistic theory that accounted not only for the evolution of Greek warfare but also for the historical development of the Greek polis in the Archaic period. This 1 Nature and types of sources for Greek warfare: Hornblower 2007; Millett 2013. A Companion to Greek Warfare, First Edition. Edited by Waldemar Heckel, F.S. Naiden, E. Edward Garvin, and John Vanderspoel. © 2021 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2021 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc. 76 Fernando Echeverría theory was based in turn on a particular vision of the nature of Greek warfare as a comprehensive and internally consistent structure of military practices and ideas that is commonly known as “hoplite warfare.” The need to bridge an alleged divide between Homer and Herodotus led then to a reconstruction of the political and social history of the Archaic period built entirely around the hoplite as a military, political, and socioeconomic figure, the so-called “hoplite narrative.” The following pages will sketch the origins and evolution of the scholarly discussion on hoplite warfare, trace the complexities of the theory of the “hoplite revolution,” and draw its various implications for the reconstruction and understanding of the Archaic period in Greece. But, more importantly, they will also address the many difficulties that the “hoplite narrative” presents as an academic explanation for Greek warfare and culture in the Archaic period. Finally, despite the broad acceptance and dissemination of both the “hoplite revolution” and “hoplite warfare” models, I will present them here as two (problematic, questionable, and overstretched) modern constructs.2 “Hoplites Rule”: Decoding the “Hoplite Narrative” Both “hoplite warfare” and the “hoplite revolution” are related aspects of what Victor Hanson recently branded as the “hoplite narrative,”3 a comprehensive account of the rise of the polis and the nature of the political and social organization in Archaic and Classical Greece from the point of view of military change. Previously, the “narrative” was most tellingly referred to as “orthodoxy,”4 but the consciousness of a relationship between the nature and origins of the Greek political community and the patterns and practices of Greek combat emerged much earlier, in the mid-nineteenth century, as we shall see. Hanson then basically articulated in twenty-first century language what was in fact an old belief: that the political, social, and economic history of the Archaic period could be explained through the figure of the “hoplite.” In this “narrative,” the hoplite is not just an ancient type of heavily armed infantryman, but a multifaceted and all-encompassing figure that synthesizes the social, political, and ideological changes of the Archaic period. The modern notion of “hoplite”5 combines both military and socioeconomic connotations, referring to a particular type of Greek soldier equipped with a specific panoply of weapons and fighting in a certain kind of formation (the phalanx) on the one hand, and to an individual belonging to a particular socioeconomic class with landed property and citizen rights on the other. Finally, it also conveys ideological connotations, referring not only to the agrarian ideas of economy, sacrifice, and hard work but also to notions of equality, homogeneity, moderation, and participation. The “hoplite” is then the key to the “narrative,” for his peculiarities, constraints, and interests are supposed to determine the complex set of changes and circumstances that explain the Archaic period. He is also the cornerstone that connects (as the name attests) “hoplite warfare” with the “hoplite revolution”: the emergence of the hoplite determined a 2 The “hoplite revolution” as a “modern construct”: Raaflaub 1993, 80. 3 Hanson 2013. 4 Morris 1987, 196; Rawlings 2000, 234; Cartledge 2001, 155; Matthew 2009, 395; Krentz 2010; 45; Kagan and Viggiano 2013b. See recently Konijnendijk 2016, 1–2; 2018, 22; Lloyd 2017, 234–235. 5 For theoretical approaches see Lazenby and Whitehead 1996; Echeverría 2012. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 77 new kind of warfare that empowered this new class of farmers and enabled them to force political changes in their communities; they established isonomic and democratic regimes in which the elites were balanced by a powerful, self-conscious, and autonomous middle class, which legitimized in turn their control of political power through the practice of this exclusive and highly normative (or ritualized) style of warfare, the most adequate, efficient, and economic way of war for the polis; finally, the ideology of the “hoplite” became the ideology of the polis as a whole, and political and social institutions were shaped according to their egalitarian principle. The narrative thus contains multiple elements such as military change, social and political revolution, agrarian ideology, ritualized combat, democracy and egalitarianism, and class struggle, glued together in a single and coherent story. Hanson dominates the “hoplite narrative” in recent scholarship, but the narrative is in fact much older, the result of a long process of reflection that started by the middle of the nineteenth century. First came “hoplite warfare,” the idea that the Classical period possessed its own style of combat governed by a complex set of rules and conditions; then the “hoplite revolution,” arguing that a new socioeconomic class transformed the political scene of Greece; and finally the “hoplite ideology,” the notion of an ideological system motivated and determined by the “hoplite class.” During that process, many other aspects (Homeric warfare and society, colonization, tyrannies, mercenary service, archaic legislation, ritualized warfare, property levels, citizenship) were incorporated into the debate, making the original narrative increasingly complex and wide ranging. Given the state of the ancient evidence, however, the narrative allowed a considerable degree of speculation, starting with the date of the military revolution itself: “hoplite warfare” is fundamentally reconstructed using Classical sources and thus fits the framework of the Classical period, but the “hoplite revolution” argues that it emerged at the beginning of the Archaic era, basically extrapolating it to the eighth century with the support of a few circumstantial pieces of evidence.6 The “hoplite narrative” is then a “hoplite-centric” account of the Archaic period, using a multifaceted and overstretched notion. Moreover, since Archaic Greece is perceived as the formative period of such purely Hellenic institutions as the polis, representative government, legislation, philosophical inquiry, or athletic competitions, the “hoplite” is thus situated at the beginning of all those phenomena, at the very core of Greekness.7 According to the “narrative,” then, hoplites do indeed rule, and the key to understanding their predominance lies in the factor that gave them the edge against the elites: their new panoply, including their broad, two-handled round shield. The Cornerstone: The Hoplite Equipment Archaic Greek military equipment has received considerable attention, particularly since the publication of Snodgrass’ seminal work.8 A series of modern studies traces the origins and evolution of the main types of weapons9 and infers that a particular group of them 6 Basically a few lyric fragments by Archilochus and Tyrtaeus and a few vase paintings from the mid-seventh century thought to represent closed formations (the Chigi Vase). See Echeverría 2008, 74–85. For recent interpretations of the Chigi Vase, see van Wees 2000, 2004, 170–172; Hurwit 2002; Viggiano and van Wees 2013, 67–68. 7 Hanson 1989, 1995, 2000, 2013. 8 Snodgrass 1964; see also 1965a, 1965b, 1967, 1971, 1980. 9 Bottini 1988; Bol 1989; Jarva 1995, 2013; Baitinger 2001. 78 Fernando Echeverría constituted the typical “pack” of the Greek heavily armed infantryman, so they are known collectively as “hoplite equipment” or the “hoplite panoply.”10 This set consisted of six items: a metallic helmet of closed design and topped by a crest; body armor of different types (fundamentally of bronze, but later also leather) with the predominance at the beginning of a heavy, double-plated bronze cuirass (the “bell cuirass”); a pair of bronze greaves crafted to adapt to the muscles of the lower leg; a two-meter-long spear with bronze ends, a spear point, and a butt spike (the sauroter), that was the main offensive weapon; a short sword (40–60 cm) with straight or curved blade that is usually interpreted as a secondary weapon; and a wide (90–100 cm of diameter), bowl-shaped round shield (the aspis or Argive shield), with wooden core and a protruding rim, occasionally covered with a bronze sheet and provided with two handles, a central armband (porpax) and a lateral handgrip (antilabe). According to modern scholarship, the different elements of the panoply appeared in Greece from the middle of the eighth century onward and spread during the following decades in a piecemeal process: they appear in considerable quantities as offerings in sanctuaries and figure prominently in the iconography of the period.11 The extent of the impact of foreign influences in Greek military technology of this period is still debated,12 but by the beginning the sixth century, the panoply seems to be widespread and will be the standard equipment of Greek heavy infantry forces during the Classical period. The physical characteristics of the different items of the panoply have generated little controversy, except for the weight of the Argive shield and the accumulated weight of the panoply: traditionally, both shield and panoply were regarded as heavy and cumbersome,13 but recent estimates reduce their weight by half,14 with important consequences for the general interpretation of the capabilities of the Greek hoplite. Discussion has, however, focused on the panoply in action. The “hoplite narrative” argues that the particular blend of peculiarities and disadvantages of the panoply explains the nature of hoplite warfare and hence the “hoplite revolution.”15 It all starts with the Argive shield: its double grip and its width provide better handling and greater protection, respectively; these qualities are improved by its concave shape, which allows the inner side of the rim to rest on the shoulder, contributes to deflect blows, and makes it structurally more solid. These very same qualities, however, together with its considerable weight, make its wearer slower and heavier, while the double grip determines that the shield protects only one side of the fighter and thus exposes him to attacks from the unprotected side or the rear. The bronze cuirass offers additional protection at the cost of additional weight, and the helmet 10 Treatments and descriptions of the “hoplite panoply”: Snodgrass 1964, 1967; Anderson 1970, 13–42; Cartledge 1977, 12–15; Anderson 1991; Hanson 1991b; Hunt 2007, 112–117; Krentz 2007a, 67–72; Jarva 2013, 397–412; Lee 2013, 147–149; Viggiano and van Wees 2013. 11 Iconography of the hoplite panoply: Lorimer 1947; Greenhalgh 1973; Salmon 1977; van Wees 2000; Viggiano and van Wees 2013. 12 Particularly Assyrian and Persian influences. See Lee 2013; Raaflaub 2013a. 13 An estimated combined weight of 30–32 kg: Lorimer 1947; Cartledge 1977, 20, 1996; Hanson 1989, 55–88, 1991b; Dawson 1996, 48; Mitchell 1996, 89; Schwartz 2002; Jarva 2013, 398. The idea goes back to Rüstow and Köchly 1852, 44 and Delbrück 1887, 56. See Krentz 2010, 45–50 for discussion. 14 Krentz 2007a, 70–71, 2010, 50, 2013a, 135–137. Rawlings also questions the burden of the hoplite panoply (2000, 246–249). 15 Lorimer 1947; Adcock 1957, 3–4; Greenhalgh 1973, 70–74; Cartledge 1977, 12–13, 1996; Salmon 1977; Hanson 1989, 1991a, 1991b; Bryant 1990; Mitchell 1996, 89–91; Schwartz 2002, 2009, 2013; Viggiano 2013. For a recent analysis of the discussion, see Krentz 2013a, 137–140, who situates the origin of the idea in Helbig 1909, 1911. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 79 paradoxically increases the vulnerability of its wearer considerably by reducing his visual and auditory perception. As a result, the hoplite is a heavily equipped and highly protected fighter, but also a slow, clumsy, and easily disoriented target. Bearing those difficulties in mind, the “hoplite narrative” argues that the different weapons are engineered to complement each other and compensate for their individual disadvantages, but, more importantly, that the panoply needs a closed formation, the phalanx, to be truly efficient. According to the “narrative,” hoplites can only fight in the ranks of the phalanx and they are useless in isolation;16 the homogeneous adoption of the panoply also facilitates fighting in a closed formation. The key is technological determinism: the peculiarities of the weapons determine the need for a specific tactical deployment, and that deployment only. Determinism lies also behind the original adoption and later spread of the new panoply in Greece, as we shall see. So from this deterministic point of view, the “narrative” takes for granted that the panoply implies a hoplite (thus the label “hoplite equipment”) and that hoplites imply the phalanx (thus the label “hoplite warfare”); the equipment then becomes an indicator of the presence of certain military realities.17 Conversely, a phalanx is taken to imply the presence of hoplites and they in turn are taken to imply the presence of the panoply. Technological determinism thus comes full circle. All the different stages of the deterministic sequence have been questioned recently: it has been argued, for example, that the panoply was rarely complete (something attested by the iconography)18 and that the different items could be used in endless combinations, even including controversial typologies such as the Boeotian shield; as a result, military equipment was not homogeneous but could depend to some extent on particular tastes and local traditions. If there was no such thing as a standard panoply, hoplites cannot be the key to the phalanx as technological determinism and the “hoplite narrative” claim. The Nature of “Hoplite Warfare” For modern scholars, “hoplite warfare” is basically the style of combat determined by the peculiarities and conditions of the “hoplite” (the multifaceted character described above), but also the military structure derived from it.19 In place during the Classical period, it can be summarized as a combat system consisting of a clash of phalanxes with a set of prescriptive rules and protocols. It was the result of the prevalence of the hoplite in the Greek poleis 16 Lorimer 1947; Andrewes 1956, 32; Detienne 1968, 139 n. 108; Bryant 1990, 498; Mitchell 1996, 89; Cartledge 1977, 13, 1996, 712; Hanson 2000, 206; Schwartz 2002, 40. 17 This quality is used, for example, for chronological purposes: identifying the “hoplite panoply” in painted scenes allows us to date the appearance of the hoplite and, consequently, of the phalanx. This is the premise of most iconographical studies: Helbig 1911; Nilsson 1929; Lorimer 1947; Snodgrass 1965b, 1993; Greenhalgh 1973; Salmon 1977; Anderson 1991. See van Wees 2000 for a comprehensive discussion. 18 For discussion with further bibliography, see Jarva 1995; van Wees 2000, 2004, 47–52; Lee 2013; Echeverría 2015. 19 General descriptions of “hoplite warfare”: Adcock 1957, 2–11; Anderson 1970, 1–9; Ridley 1979; Hanson 1983, 1989, 1991a, 1991b; Bryant 1990; Wheeler 1991, 2007; Bowden 1995; Dawson 1996, 47–52; Mitchell 1996; Santosuosso 1997; Morgan 2001; Trundle 2001; Lendon 2005, 39–57; Krentz 2007a, 72–77; de Souza 2008; Hunt 2009, 229–230; Lee 2013, 153–157. Theoretical discussions on the nature of “hoplite warfare”: Snodgrass 1965a, 1993; Detienne 1968; Cartledge 1977, 1996; Hanson 1983, 1989, 1991a, 2000; Krentz 1985, 2007a, 2007b, 2013a, 2013b; Connor 1988; Cawkwell 1989; Lazenby 1991; Wheeler 1991, 2007; Foxhall 1995; Hanson 1995, 2000; Mitchell 1996; Storch 1998; van Wees 2000, 2004, 2013; Schwartz 2002; Rawlings 2007, 2013; Echeverría 2011; Lloyd 2017; Konijnendijk 2018. 80 Fernando Echeverría (“hoplite warfare” thus corresponds to the “time of the hoplite”),20 a figure who was simultaneously a farmer (owner of a plot of land), a citizen (a free man with political rights and participation in decision-making), and a soldier (a heavily armed infantryman fighting in the phalanx), and thus was in an ideal position to impose his political and military agenda upon the entire community. The notion of “hoplite warfare” developed in two complementary spheres: a tactical one, dealing with the circumstances of the hoplite in the phalanx and on the battlefield, and an ideological one, referring to the ideas and values that inspired this kind of warfare and influenced Greek communities in turn. “Hoplite warfare” (this consciousness of the particular way of war of Classical Greek communities) was the first step in the construction of the “hoplite narrative,” and discussion started with the analysis of tactics.21 By the 1850s, Grote22 established that the kind of warfare practiced during the historical period in Greece was radically different from the “heroic” warfare of the epics; historical warfare was characterized by the closed order of the phalanx, in which individual prowess became secondary to the discipline of the group, and the soldier of the phalanx was a nonaristocratic member of the farmer class, who imposed an egalitarian ethos upon the tactical formation. In the following decades, a group of German scholars23 built on Grote’s ideas and established one of the main principles of “hoplite warfare”: that Greek war could be reduced to (and equated with) battle. According to them, Greek wars were decided in short and straightforward battles by the clash of two closed formations of heavy infantry arranged in neat ranks and with homogenous equipment; there were no tactics, no maneuvers, and no inventiveness, but considerable single-mindedness and prejudices; battles were planned in advance, and troops other than heavy infantry were regarded as auxiliary and played no relevant role in the action. It has been argued24 that the Prussians elaborated such a restricted model of combat in order to reduce Greek warfare to a minimum set of rules and protocols and thus produce greater contrast with fourth-century tactical developments. In any case, by the first quarter of the twentieth century, the foundations of “hoplite warfare” had been laid. In the following decades, Anglo-American scholars adopted the model without reservations25 and helped to fix and spread the principles of the “hoplite orthodoxy”: the simple battles of phalanxes, the exclusive presence of hoplites, the deterministic correlation between hoplite and phalanx, the homogeneity of equipment, and the quasi-ritualized protocols and practices. Moreover, they also formulated for the first time the great “paradox” of Greek warfare (the prevalence of the heavy and rigid phalanx in the rugged landscape of Greece), situated the aim of combat in agricultural devastation (as a bait to lure the enemy army to accept battle), and discussed the nature of hand-to-hand combat in closed formation (the debate on the othismos or “push” and the analogy of the rugby scrum).26 These ideas became extremely influential and shaped the image of Greek warfare up to this date. 20 See fundamentally Hanson 1989, 1995, 1996 for the rise and fall of the hoplite in Greek history and the corresponding rise and fall of hoplite warfare, what he labels the “age of the hoplite.” See recently Snodgrass 2013, 92–93 on the end of the hoplite. 21 I follow the treatments by Kagan and Viggiano 2013b; Konijnendijk 2018, 7–20. 22 Grote 1846, 106–107. 23 Whom Konijnendijk 2018, 7–12 aptly calls the “Prussians”: Rüstow and Köchly 1852; Droysen 1889; Bauer 1893; Beloch 1897; Lammert 1899; Delbrück 1900; Kromayer and Veith 1903, 1928. 24 Konijnendijk 2018, 11–12. 25 Grundy 1911; Gomme 1945; Adcock 1957; Anderson 1970; Pritchett 1971–1991. 26 Grundy 1911; Fraser 1942; Pritchett 1971–1991 IV; Krentz 1985, 1994, 2013a; Cawkwell 1989; Luginbill 1994; Goldsworthy 1997; Schwartz 2002; van Wees 2004, 188–191; Rawlings 2007, 93–97; Matthew 2009. For a recent analysis of the discussion, see Krentz 2013a, 143–148. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 81 The elaboration and definition of the ideological framework of hoplite combat during the 1960s and 1970s was the next step in the evolution of the concept of “hoplite warfare.” The original thinkers of the “hoplite narrative” had already established that the new style of combat implied a new mentality in opposition to the traditional “heroic ethos” of the aristocracy, but no particular attention had been paid to the question beyond the basic formulation of a set of anti-aristocratic principles.27 Proper reflection now prompted a lively discussion that sanctioned the existence of a “hoplite ideology” that explained and justified the hoplite system, and consisted of two basic components: equality and ritualism. With a major impulse by a group of French scholars,28 the tradition of the homogeneity and solidarity of the phalanx was now interpreted as a principle of strict equality, determined by the nature of the military equipment and combat in closed formation, and then transferred to the social and political spheres. The conditions of the panoply and the phalanx (homogenous equipment, fixed positions in the formation, restricted movements, and rigidity) determined that hoplite combat rested on the solidarity and equality of the fighters, and thus aristocratic individualism was abandoned in favor of collective values (keeping formation, cohesion, rejection of individualistic behavior, sacrifice); the hoplite was now expected to collaborate in the mass of fighters for the common good; the “hoplite class” was characterized by socioeconomic homogeneity and prompted egalitarian institutions (assemblies, juries) in the community. The egalitarian principle of the polis was then the result of the transference of military values to the political and social spheres. Once predominant in the polis, egalitarian values reinforced in turn the role and protocols of the phalanx and hoplite combat, emphasizing and actively encouraging solidarity, anonymity, and simplicity (amateur soldiers who relied on simple tactics and strategies), and serving as a legitimizing factor for the prevalence of the “hoplite class” in the political, social, and military institutions of the polis. The second component of the “hoplite ideology” is ritualism. The German scholars of the nineteenth century had already described “hoplite warfare” as a simple, unimaginative kind of warfare,29 but its rigidity seemed to be the result of the simplicity of the tactic itself and the limitations of the phalanx. From the 1960s onward, however, the tactical simplicity of “hoplite warfare” was reinterpreted as a deliberate choice taken by the hoplites to materialize their ideas, principles, and interests,30 a conscious solution to the paradox formulated by Grundy and Gomme: in order to make the phalanx a feasible system to settle political disputes, its tactical limitations had to be compensated by a strict code of unwritten norms and protocols that emanated from the material conditions and ideological principles of the “hoplite class”; being a natural by-product of the hoplite mentality, the code was tacitly adopted by all Greek communities with a substantial hoplite group. The “simple battle” described by the Prussians became thus a “ritualized battle.” Ritualism drew from the long tradition of studies on Greek athletic competitions to conceive battle as a highly regulated contest in which all the relevant elements were present: a setting (the battlefield), a board of judges (the gods), two participants (the rival armies), and a prize (military victory). The rules for the competition, finally, were most systematically distilled by Ober,31 a list of 12 norms that were allegedly of general application in Greece and included formal declaration of war, sparing of “civilians,” and ransom of prisoners, among 27 Grote 1846, 106–107; Rüstow and Köchly 1852; Meyer 1893; Grundy 1911; Weber 1922; Nilsson 1929. 28 Detienne 1968; Mossé 1968; Vidal-Naquet 1968; Garlan 1972; Ducrey 1985. 29 Rüstow and Köchly 1852, 144–145; Droysen 1889, 93–94; Lammert 1899, 21. 30 Detienne 1968; Pritchett 1971–1991 II; Cartledge 1977; Connor 1988; Hanson 1989, 1991a, 2000; Bryant 1990; Ober 1991, 1994; Dawson 1996, 49–52; Mitchell 1996. 31 Ober 1994. 82 Fernando Echeverría others. Ritualism seemed to fit perfectly the principles of “hoplite warfare”: the hoplite agenda of economy of effort, the hoplite social background of amateur farmers, the hoplite reliance on the allegedly heavy and cumbersome panoply, and the hoplite reduction of war to individual and quickly resolved battles. By the 1990s, then, it had become the prevailing view on the mechanics of Greek warfare. With the principles of the “hoplite ideology” already in place, the final step toward the consolidation of the model of “hoplite warfare” came with the work of Hanson,32 perhaps the most influential advocate of the “hoplite narrative” in the recent decades. Hanson reinstated the traditional elements of the narrative (Greek warfare as phalanx battle, the paradox of “hoplite warfare,” the simplicity and ritualism of phalanx warfare, the deterministic identification between hoplite and phalanx, the peculiarities of the hoplite panoply, the hoplite class as an anti-aristocratic and egalitarian social group), but also made four distinct and far-reaching contributions to it: first, he described an economic revolution at the beginning of the eighth century in Greece that allowed the exploitation of new farmlands and thus explained the rise of the “hoplite class,” a group of non-elite landowners presented as middle-class independent farmers or yeomen; second, he connected the “hoplite ideology” (egalitarianism and ritualism) with the agrarian nature of the “hoplite class” and coined the term agrarianism, the agrarian ideology of the hoplite that helped to understand his world view and his agenda, connecting in turn Greek warfare and the polis with agriculture; third, he adapted John Keegan’s ground-level approach to battle33 to ancient Greece and thus explored the “hoplite experience” of combat from a battlefield point of view, describing the actions, emotions, and concerns of the hoplites standing in the ranks of the phalanx; and fourth, he presented the “hoplite system” as the origin and foundation of a distinctively Western “world system,” in which modern warfare and democracy are the direct and uncorrupted counterparts of hoplite warfare and democracy. Armed with these tools, and with an unwavering faith in the democratic virtues of the middling hoplite, Hanson updated the old pillars of the theory, turning it into a comprehensive and holistic “narrative.” The expanding construct of “hoplite warfare” met equally growing criticism from the 1960s onward by a group of scholars known as “revisionists.”34 Revisionism, however, not only addressed the problems posed by the principles of hoplite combat but embarked on a deeper reconsideration of Greek society, politics, and war that has led to the gradual articulation of alternative views of the Archaic period and the nature and origins of the polis. We will develop the evolution of such criticism in some detail in the following section, but for now it is crucial to understand that its cumulative effect has been to question the very concepts of “hoplite” and “phalanx” held by the “hoplite narrative.” In fact, the “narrative” had never taken serious steps toward a rigorous definition of their two single most important terms. In the late nineteenth century, the “Prussians” used both “hoplite” and “phalanx” as primarily military and tactical concepts, but their approaches and definitions were considerably determined by their own professional background, so they privileged the creation of a theoretical paradigm even at the expense of an absolute lack of evidence at times.35 From then on, the terms were shaped more by 32 Hanson 1983, 1989, 1991a, 1991b, 1995, 1996, 2000, 2013. 33 Keegan 1976. 34 Snodgrass 1965a, 1993, 2013; Krentz 1985, 2000, 2002; Foxhall 1995, 2013; Rawlings 2000, 2007, 2013; van Wees 2000, 2001, 2004, 2013. For the label see Wheeler 2011, 79–104. 35 Konijnendijk 2018, 7–10. A paramount example, highlighted by Konijnendijk, is Rüstow and Köchly’s axiom (1852, 118–120) that the standard depth of the phalanx was eight ranks, a statement completely unsupported by the ancient sources but anyway taken as a given by generations of scholars. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 83 conventional use than by a proper conceptual reflection, most of the time in absolute disregard of their ancient meanings and connotations. This is most evident in the case of “hoplite”: its core meaning is extremely narrow (a kind of heavy-armed infantryman mentioned in the literary sources of the Classical period), but in modern literature, it became rather common as an adjective applied to many different fields. At the beginning it was referred to strictly military matters, so scholars spoke of “hoplite panoply,” “hoplite equipment,” “hoplite shield,” “hoplite forces/army,” “hoplite phalanx,” “hoplite formation/line,” “hoplite tactics,” and “hoplite warfare/battle.”36 From the late 1960s onward, however, the concept colonized a broad range of social, ideological, political, and economic spheres, and thus new uses appeared: “hoplite system,” “hoplite state,” “hoplite polis,” “hoplite republic,” “hoplite democracy,” “hoplite class,” “hoplite status,” “hoplite assembly,” “hoplite landowner,” “hoplite farm,” “hoplite ritual,” “hoplite ideology,” “hoplite ethos,” “hoplite discipline,” “hoplite agon/agonalism,” and so on.37 The hoplite thus left behind the soldier to become the multifaceted figure we have been discussing, responding to the interests and concerns of modern scholarship. This “definition by use” has been crucial in the shaping of our modern concepts of both “hoplite” and “phalanx,” but at some point it has brought some confusion and a disturbing detachment from the ancient realities themselves, so it seems crucial to pursue a serious reflection on this matter.38 The Theory of the “Hoplite Revolution” The definition by the early theorists of the “hoplite narrative” of a distinct military figure with its own military tactic soon led to the application of the new model to the political and social evolution in Archaic Greece and to the complex question of the nature and rise of the polis. The so-called “hoplite revolution” or “hoplite reform”39 attempts an explanation of the social and political processes that led to the birth of the polis using the figure of the hoplite as its central focus, its guiding principle, and its driving force. In its basic structure, the “hoplite revolution” is based on Aristotle’s reflections on the birth and evolution of the political regimes in Greece,40 and particularly on two fundamental Aristotelian ideas: the identification between political power and possession of weapons, and the foundation of Greek communities on military values and structures. The modern theory has expanded on aspects and details that Aristotle could have never anticipated, but its internal mechanics are no doubt Aristotelian. 36 Nilsson 1928, 1929; Lorimer 1947; Snodgrass 1964, 1965a, 1965b. 37 Snodgrass 1965a, 1965b; Detienne 1968; Cartledge 1977, 2013; Salmon 1977; Bryant 1990; Lazenby 1991; Hanson 1995; Kagan and Viggiano 2013a. Nilsson spoke of a “hoplite-state” already in 1929 (p. 9), so the potential for the spread of the term was already present. 38 Fifty years ago, Snodgrass stated that “we should be hesitant in our application of the term [hoplites] to the earlier stages of Greek armament” (Snodgrass 1964, 204). It seems quite evident that the conceptual caution he was urging has largely passed unattended. For a recent attempt at a conceptual reflection on both “hoplite” and “phalanx,” see Echeverría 2012. 39 Although Anglo-Saxon scholarship prefers the term “hoplite reform,” I think the theory is more correctly labelled as “hoplite revolution,” doing better justice to the revolutionary nature of the social, political and military changes described in it. 40 For the connection between Aristotle and the “hoplite revolution,” see basically Echeverría 2008, 93–103; van Wees 2013. 84 Fernando Echeverría The theory draws a continuous line of cultural development with several phases of deep transformation arranged in causal succession (a “revolution” made of a sequence of minor “revolutions”). In its most developed form, it argues41 that an economic change in the beginning of the Archaic period allowed new groups to afford new military equipment (the hoplite panoply), which led in turn to a military change with the introduction of the phalanx; the new tactic eroded the military exclusivity of the aristocracy and prompted a social change that entailed the consolidation of a new social class of middle (or at least non-elite) landowners who served as hoplites in the phalanx; finally, given their new military and economic predominance in the community, the hoplite class forced political changes that established the egalitarian institutions of the developed polis. As a result, a set of diverse (and in principle unrelated) questions and debates, such as the rise of the polis, the emergence of the hoplite, and the introduction of the phalanx, were put together in a causal relationship, with the result that a single theory was able to explain them all in concert. The theory is built on five fundamental principles that articulate its internal logic.42 First, the cultural gap between the “Homeric world” and the “historical world” of the polis: the societal and political structures presented in the epics are regarded as radically different from those of the Classical polis, and a period of changes and adjustments is consequently argued. Second, the community of warriors:43 Greek communities were structured according to military values and to the military prevalence of a class of warriors who fought as a way to access and preserve political participation; that made the political community isomorphic with the army. Third, technological determinism: new weapons with superior qualities were immediately adopted and replaced the old types, rendering them obsolete; new weapons entailed new types of fighters, both involving in turn new tactics that were automatically implemented; technological determinism is thus driven by the principle of superiority (of design, of performance, of effectiveness) and often leads to the idea of “arms race” between communities. Fourth, the sociopolitical revolution: “class struggle” (or at least vertical conflict) erupted between a privileged aristocratic class and lower and oppressed socioeconomic segments who resort to violence and the use of weapons to force political changes; this context of political and social unrest is connected to the rise of tyrannies, as a symbiotic alliance between the revolting classes and ambitious despots. And fifth, the polis as intrinsically egalitarian and democratic: the values of solidarity and equality of the hoplite class impregnate the social and political institutions (counsels, assemblies) of the new communities that emerged from the social and political struggle with the elite; democracy, egalitarian communities governed by isonomic and democratic principles, is the goal of the “hoplite revolution.” Those different arguments were laid down in a long and piecemeal process that took more than a century to complete. The basic components of the theory were already present by the end of the nineteenth century, but it only reached its maturity by the 1960s, when it was first 41 I will draw from my own treatment in 2008 (29–71) and from Kagan and Viggiano’s (2013b), less detailed but more recent. This presentation will be necessarily schematic. Other synthesis of the theory in Bryant 1990, 494–500; Wheeler 1991, Bowden 1995, 47–49; Cartledge 1996, 685–686; Raaflaub 1997, 49–50; Krentz 2007a, 61–65; Hunt 2009, 231–234; Viggiano 2013. 42 Echeverría 2008, 66–71. 43 This is based on the Aristotelian principle that the possessors of the weapons were the participants in the political system: Arist. Pol. 1265b 28–29, 1268a 21–23, 1279b 2–4, 1297b 1–2, 1329a 11–12. For a recent discussion on the polis as a “community of warriors,” see Berent 2000, 273–285. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 85 labelled as the “hoplite reform.”44 The intellectual background of the theory can be found in the historiography of the mid-nineteenth century,45 which noticed the cultural gap between Homeric warfare and society (aristocratic, individualistic) on the one hand and the Classical polis and phalanx (egalitarian, solidary) on the other. A social and political transformation in the Archaic period was inferred to account for that military and political divide, and particularly the replacement of the aristocratic cavalry by a homogenous formation of middle-class infantrymen.46 Greek communities abandoned the traditional and heroic kingships in favor of oligarchies, but those were in turn challenged by despots and individual rulers. It was also by the end of the nineteenth century when the German scholars established the principles of “hoplite warfare” as a solidary and homogenous style of combat that undermined the military supremacy of the elite, as we have already seen. This background, that has been labelled a “proto-orthodoxy,”47 set the context for the foundation of the theory at the beginning of the twentieth century, when its basic components were put in place. Scholars then argued that the nature of the Greek polis was essentially military and thus reinstated the Aristotelian principle of the “community of warriors”: military values and practices determined social change, political participation, and institutional organization.48 They accepted the divide between the “heroic” and the “historical” ways of war and the replacement of the cavalry by the phalanx, and tied the latter to the democratic polis. This change had been carried out gradually, with the rise of a middle class of farmers (the traditional demos) that demolished the aristocratic system in the middle of intense political struggles. As a result, new timocratic systems emerged, as well as the democratic institutions of the developed polis. Slightly later, Lorimer laid another principle of the theory,49 technological determinism, arguing that the tactical change was the result of “a single structural alteration,” the doublegrip system of the Argive shield.50 She established that the reason to account for the unprecedented spread of the shield was its (presumed) superiority, and the reason to justify the adoption of the phalanx was the peculiar characteristics of the panoply; its subsequent spread throughout Greece was attributed to its superiority as a tactic and to the dynamics of “peer polity interactions” and “arms race.”51 A minor adaptation in a weapon was then responsible for a chain reaction that led to the end of “heroic” and cavalry fighting and the prevalence of infantry fighting in closed formation. That is the very definition of technological determinism. Finally, the political consequences of the reform were explored by Andrewes,52 who embraced the Aristotelian definition of Greek tyranny and Grote’s and Weber’s idea of the end of traditional oligarchies by a collaboration of new middle classes (the demos of the 44 “Hoplite reform”: Snodgrass 1965a, 1965b; Detienne 1968; Greenhalgh 1973. Previous scholars had naturally conceived the idea of a military and political reform or revolution: Lorimer 1947, 92; Andrewes 1956, 38. 45 Grote 1846; Fustel de Coulanges 1864. 46 The idea was drawn (but also considerably adapted) from Aristotle’s famous fragment in Pol. 1297b 16–25. 47 Kagan and Viggiano 2013b, 3. 48 Meyer 1893; Helbig 1911; Weber 1922; Glotz 1928; Nilsson 1928, 1929; Ehrenberg 1932, 1937. 49 Lorimer 1947. 50 Lorimer 1947, 76. 51 An analysis of technological determinism and the “hoplite revolution”: Echeverría 2008, 193–248, 2010. “Arms race” applied to Greece and hoplite warfare: Lorimer 1947, 108; Andrewes 1956, 38; Cartledge 1977, 18; Salmon 1977, 96; Holladay 1982, 99–100. “Peer polity interactions”: Snodgrass 1986, 51–52. 52 Andrewes 1956. 86 Fernando Echeverría ancient sources) and ambitious demagogues. He then argued for a context of internal struggle in the Greek communities, the stasis, characterized by the rise of the middling demos and its alliance with those demagogues who conspired to overthrow the oligarchic regimes and established tyrannies throughout Greece. Andrewes reinstated the components of the “hoplite revolution” and gave it its final shape: a military change led to a social transformation, which in turn prompted a political reform.53 This “orthodoxy” was soon to be questioned. Snodgrass picked up Meyer’s and Nilsson’s idea of the gradual “reform,” and in a series of works on Greek military equipment in the 1960s and beyond,54 he undermined the principle of the sudden revolution presenting the new panoply as a “motley assemblage” of dispersed weapons, and its introduction and spread in Greece as a “piecemeal” process.55 Snodgrass suggested that the adoption of the equipment and the introduction of the phalanx were not successive steps but were separated by a sizeable lapse of time. He also questioned the idea of the social revolution and presented the middle-class farmers as “reluctant hoplites,”56 undermining in turn the need for a political revolution. Snodgrass accepted the rest of the theory (military change and political change, the superiority of the hoplite and the phalanx, military service as a requisite for political participation, collaboration between demos and tyrants), but with considerable nuances, so he inaugurated a “gradualist” line that was followed by some in the ensuing decades.57 Another group of scholars, however, immediately reinstated the principles of the sudden revolution and even elaborated on the social and ideological implications of the adoption of the phalanx;58 for them, technological change led to tactical change and to the “paradox” of Greek warfare, “heroic” combat was antithetical to phalanx warfare, and the middle classes of hoplites established a “republic of Equals” in which “political and military systems were perfectly homologous.”59 As a result, “orthodoxy” was preserved and the theory split in two contrasting positions that disagreed in the pace of the military and political transformation. Scholarly discussion had been kept so far within the framework of the “hoplite revolution” and no criticism had questioned the structure as a whole, but that was bound to change by the end of the 1970s: Two separate and completely unrelated monographs challenged some of the most fundamental assumptions of the theory. First, Latacz’s analysis of the Homeric poems60 concluded that “heroic” combat was only a (short) phase of the Homeric battle and that the core of the fighting was in fact carried out by the anonymous mass, arranged in a sort of closed formation that he recognized as a forerunner of the Classical phalanx.61 The impact of this discovery cannot be underestimated: Latacz had questioned the gap between Homeric and historical combat that Grote had established more than a century before and had thus eliminated the context for a military reform. Taken to its last consequences, the idea was a 53 Drews 1972 modified this view arguing that the “hoplites” on which the would-be tyrants relied were not lower-class members of the community but mercenaries, so he skipped the social transformation in his own reconstruction. 54 Snodgrass 1964, 1965a, 1965b, 1967, 1971, 1980. 55 Snodgrass 1964, 83–84, 89–90, 136–139, 193–204, 1965a, 110. 56 Snodgrass 1965a, 115, 1980, 101–102, 106–107. 57 Finley 1970; Salmon 1977; Murray 1980. 58 Detienne 1968; Greenhalgh 1973; Cartledge 1977, 1996. 59 Quotes from Detienne 1968, 140 (my translation). 60 Latacz 1977. 61 Latacz 1977, 45–67, 224–245. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 87 deadly blow for the theory,62 but later scholars managed to embrace the proto-phalanx without questioning the “hoplite reform.”63 The second contribution came from the field of archaeology. Polignac’s study on rural sanctuaries during the Archaic period64 presented them as physical nodes in the ideological definition of the community and its identity, and as territorial markers in the construction of the surrounding landscape: they signaled the geographical limits of the polis and thus had to be protected, demanding a new kind of warfare in which the community as a whole could be involved (“hoplite warfare”). Polignac suggested thus a cause other than determinism for the introduction of the phalanx and laid the emphasis of social and political change not on internal struggles but on the dynamics of territorial conflict between neighboring communities. This line was immediately expanded by Morris,65 who questioned the “hoplite revolution” as a valid theory66 but anyway subscribed to “orthodox” notions such as vertical conflict (between the agathoi and the kakoi), the egalitarian principle of the polis, or the “middling tradition.”67 This reconsideration of the Archaic period both from the philological and the archaeological spheres shattered the pillars of the “hoplite revolution” but did not manage to tear it down. Alternatively, it prompted a period of exploration that produced a string of revised or “updated” versions of the theory, all of them presenting individual attempts to integrate the new discoveries in the framework of the “hoplite revolution”:68 Most of them reinstated the scheme of technological determinism, social struggle, and political revolution that had been the core of the theory since the beginning, although from more moderate positions that included a more complex causality and a deeper reflection on the social, economic, and political processes. An expected corollary to this exploratory phase was an “orthodox” reaction that updated and reinstated the pillars, components, and internal dynamics of the theory. Hanson’s work during the 1980s and 1990s69 was a direct reaction to the challenges to the “hoplite model” and the main reason for the revitalization of the theory, which was starting to crack. Hanson provided a new context (the agrarian revolution of the eighth to sixth centuries), a new ideology (agrarianism, the agrarian “hoplite ethos”), a new goal (the democratic polis), and even a new military process (tactical determinism: the panoply was designed to fit a pre-existing phalanx) for the “hoplite revolution,” and thus tied its old components (the rise of an egalitarian middle class, the vertical struggle with the old “heroic” elites, the creation of the democratic institutions of the rising polis) in a holistic and more comprehensive “narrative.” The impact of Hanson’s scheme on the interpretation of Greek military and political history has been massive, and some scholars have followed his lead,70 but his methodology (American-centric perspective, tendency to 62 As argued by Raaflaub (2005, 2008, 2013a, 2013b), who accepts the existence of a “proto-phalanx” and thus rejects the theory of the “hoplite revolution.” 63 Pritchett 1971–1991 IV, 1–44; Hanson 1995, 2000. 64 Polignac 1984. 65 Morris 1987. 66 Morris 1987, 196–202. 67 Morris 1987, 19–42, 175–183, 1996. 68 Bryant 1990; Bowden 1995; Mitchell 1996; Osborne 1996; Storch 1998. Even Snodgrass (1993) reconsidered his old position in the light of the recent developments. 69 Hanson 1983, 1989, 1991c, 1995, 1996, 2000. 70 Schwartz 2002, 2009, 2013; Viggiano 2013. 88 Fernando Echeverría anachronism and presentism, lenient treatment of the literary sources, complete disregard for archaeological data) has been severely questioned.71 Hanson’s reaction was partly motivated by the impact of a group of “revisionists” who in the past three decades have subjected the theory to thorough and systematic criticism.72 Krentz entered the complex debate on the othismos and concluded that hoplite battle consisted of a multiplicity of individual combats; this strengthened the gradualist position at first, but later invited connections with van Wees’ new approach to Homeric combat: van Wees completely reinterpreted the dynamics of Homeric warfare as an open and fluid battlefield in which the individual leaders moved freely followed by their “hosts” and engaged intermittently in the fighting to retreat immediately to the safety of the rearguard.73 This was the greatest upheaval in the interpretation of Homeric warfare since Latacz’s contribution, and its consequences and implications are still to be fully explored. One of them was immediately clear: van Wees argued that this open battlefield could be also detected in the fragments of Tyrtaeus and Callinus, thus opening the path to an open phalanx during the Archaic period, but Krentz’s hypothesis potentially projected it well into the Classical era. Krentz also questioned the alleged ritualism of Greek warfare and showed that Ober’s “rules” were the result of an optimistic reading of the literary sources at best (some of them referred to religious duties, others rarely verified in practice, and most of them not older than the fifth century).74 This was a crucial contribution, for the “hoplite narrative” had constructed an idealized view of Greek warfare as a “civilized” and “diplomatic” conflict at the expense of ignoring the brutality described in the literary sources, and Krentz helped to reinstate it as a human (contradictory, unpredictable, uncontrollable) activity. In a related field, Krentz reassessed the weight of the panoply and found it much lighter than previously thought; this had crucial consequences for closed combat, for it undermined the deterministic connection between the panoply and the phalanx. Van Wees had reinterpreted Homeric warfare, questioning the gap between the “Homeric” and the “historical” worlds, but he then attacked the entire notion of a hoplite middle class.75 He argued that both the analysis of the literary tradition and the quantitative assessment of the economic conditions of the Archaic period unveil a polarized society with a sharp divide between rich and poor and no room for middle classes, and concludes that most elements usually regarded as “middling” (political equality, the poetry of Hesiod and his ideology of work, the Athenian zeugites, military service in the local militia) should be in fact reinterpreted as characteristics of the elite. This debilitates in practice the traditional context for (vertical) “class struggle” and lays new emphasis on (horizontal) competition and conflict within the elite. Other scholars entered the fray. Foxhall argued for unexploited and rather empty landscapes during the Archaic period, thus questioning Hanson’s pattern of “family farms” and small plots that supported the rise of a “yeomen class,” and discussed the informal organization of the institutions and internal dynamics of the polis.76 Rawlings presented 71 Fundamentally by Foxhall 1995, 2013; van Wees 2000, 2001, 2013. See also González and López-Barja 2012. 72 Krentz 1985, 1994, 2000, 2002, 2007a, 2007b, 2010, 2013a, 2013b; van Wees 1986, 1988, 1992, 1994a, 1994b, 1995, 1996, 1997, 2000, 2001, 2002, 2004, 2006, 2013. Rawlings 2000, 2007, 2013; Foxhall 1995, 2013; Raaflaub 1993, 1997, 2013a. 73 van Wees 1986, 1988, 1992, 1994a, 1994b, 1996, 1997. 74 Krentz 2000, 2002, 2007a, 76–79. 75 van Wees 2001, 2002, 2006, 2013. 76 Foxhall 1995, 1997, 2013. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 89 the wide range of military tasks and contexts that the Classical hoplite was expected to cope with, undermining the traditional connection between the hoplite and the phalanx.77 Raaflaub, finally, explored the nature of ancient Greek democracy and the rise of the polis and connected them to the activities of the elite and the gradual definition of a “public” sphere; this essentially political process interacted with the military transformations of the period, more gradual and leading to the slow definition of closed combat and the Classical phalanx.78 The combined effect of their work was devastating: they questioned the deterministic connection between the hoplite panoply, the hoplite, and the phalanx; they rejected the “paradox” of Greek warfare and envisaged a more fluid and flexible phalanx that took a couple of centuries to develop and only appeared in its Classical form by the end of the Archaic period; Krentz also differentiated between an “inclusive” and an “exclusive” phalanx, depending on the presence (or not, respectively) of troops other than hoplites in the formation;79 there were no middle classes, nor political revolutions to overthrow the oligarchic regimes, which continued to rule in most parts of Greece. They consequently rejected the “hoplite revolution” altogether and elaborated alternative ways to reconstruct the social, political, and military processes in Archaic Greece. Van Wees even attempted an alternative narrative of the cultural development of the Archaic period, presenting a range of social, political, and economic processes that converged to generate different responses at different times in different Greek communities, instead of a sequence of steps in causal relationship and with a single origin (as the “hoplite narrative” does).80 Its impact is still to be measured. This “revisionism”81 constitutes the last phase of the evolution of the theory and takes us finally to the present. Conclusion In their Introduction to Men of Bronze, the most recent and influential synthesis on the subject,82 Kagan and Viggiano declare that their original intention for the 2008 Conference at Yale University that inspired the book was “to bring together the leading scholars from both the orthodox and the revisionist schools of thought to examine the current state of the field.” Eventually, they lament that, “instead of working toward a consensus, each side sharpened its position in response to the latest research.”83 Looking at the history of the “hoplite narrative,” that outcome could have been easily anticipated: since the appearance of the first criticism to the theory by the 1960s, the debate has evolved in a sequence of reactions and counter-reactions by two main lines of thought (the “orthodox,” more strict and conservative, and the “gradualist/revisionist,” more flexible and innovative), but has rarely led to an understanding. When doubts about the “hoplite revolution” started to grow 77 Rawlings 2000. 78 Raaflaub 1993, 1996, 1997. 79 Krentz 2010, 2013a, 2013b. 80 van Wees 2013. In this reconstruction, the “hoplite” is no longer the cause and the core, but a mere component among many others. 81 See also Echeverría 2008, 2010, 2011, 2012, 2015; Konijnendijk 2016, 2018; Lloyd 2017. 82 Kagan and Viggiano 2013a. 83 Kagan and Viggiano 2013a, xvii. 90 Fernando Echeverría by the 1970s and 1980s,84 for example, the “orthodox” reaction described above brought about Hanson’s “Western way of war” and “hoplite narrative.” The situation is (and has been) rather polarized. And it is no surprise, since each position entails much deeper implications beyond the particular characteristics of a certain weapon: it compromises the particular perspective on historical change and causality, on political and social structures and mobility, and on the nature of the polis. On one side, “orthodoxy” thinks of the polis as an advanced form of ancient state, subjected to the rule of law and governed by formal institutions; on the other, “revisionism” envisages a more informal and flexible situation, with the polis as “little more than a stand-off between the members of the elite who ran them,”85 or at least as a less formalized political community. Despite the work of “revisionism,” the “hoplite narrative” has taken over the field, particularly outside the Academia, where its capacity to produce much simpler and all-encompassing explanations to complex processes is much appreciated. Within the scholarly world, the “hoplite revolution” has lost much of its former appeal, but “hoplite warfare” is still the most widespread model to reconstruct the dynamics of Greek warfare. According to the “orthodoxy,” this is because “revisionists” have not been able to produce “a coherent theory that even begins to replace the orthodox model,”86 so they argue that the burden of proof rests with those who want to question the “hoplite narrative.”87 This is seriously flawed on two methodological grounds. First, the “hoplite narrative” is not carved out in stone in some ancient inscription, but deduced and constructed by modern theorists at the expense of historical extrapolation and against existing evidence at times, so the burden of proof rests always with those who want to put it up. Second, a narrative as complex and expanding as the “hoplite narrative” serves basically the purpose of easing our need for answers and ensuring our peace of mind, but it does not necessarily bring more clarity to ancient Greek warfare and politics. This allencompassing structure is a gigantic but unstable construct that attempts to explain the whole Archaic period from one single component, the “hoplite,” like an inverted pyramid resting on its apex. Greek history does not need an alternative and competing narrative of that kind, in my opinion, but different narratives that approach the ancient sources with new eyes and allow a degree of inconsistency and singularity among the hundreds of different Greek poleis of the Archaic period, as the one produced, for example, by van Wees.88 Too much pressure has been put on the shoulders of the “hoplite” over the last decades: he has been identified as an independent farmer, a social revolutionary, a highly specialized infantryman, a convinced democrat, a tyrant-supporter, a responsible citizen, an amateur 84 When the theory is first rejected: “The silence of the record is so impressive that one should doubt the presuppositions of the ‘hoplite’ theory” (Sealey 1976, 57); “The ‘hoplite revolution’ must be listed among the great non-events of history” (Frost 1984, 293); “There is no evidence whatsoever to support the theory that there was a hoplite reform” (Morris 1987, 198); “We should begin by expelling from the closets of our textbooks two skeletons that have lingered there far too long. One is the theory that tyranny and hoplite phalanx were directly connected [. . .]. The other skeleton is the theory of the ‘hoplite revolution’” (Raaflaub 1997, 53). See also Nafissi 2009, 129. 85 Foxhall 1997, 119. 86 Viggiano 2013, 126. 87 Schwartz 2013, 119. 88 Krentz also attempted an alternative reconstruction of the evolution of “hoplite warfare” (2002, 35–37), while Lloyd (2017, 239–246) specifically addresses the diversity of the Greek world in his own account. Another alternative reconstruction in Morgan (2001). The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 91 fighter, a political reformer, a champion of equality, a dedicated soldier, a moderate thinker, a reactionary exclusivist, a solidary and selfless battle comrade, a conscious voter. But whatever he was, he represented just a fraction of the population of the ancient Greek communities, and not even the biggest one. Perhaps it is time to put him to rest for a while and pay due attention to the role of other groups in the defense and political articulation of the community. Perhaps it is time for narratives without the “hoplite.” Bibliography Adcock, Frank E. 1957. The Greek and Macedonian Art of War. Berkeley and Los Angeles; reprinted 1962. Anderson, John K. 1970. Military Theory and Practice in the Age of Xenophon. Berkeley and Los Angeles. Anderson, John K. 1991. “Hoplite Weapons and Offensive Arms.” In Victor D. Hanson (ed.), Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience, London, 15–37. Andrewes, Antony. 1956. The Greek Tyrants. New York. Baitinger, Holger. 2oo1. Die Angriffswaffen aus Olympia. Olympische Forschungen XXIX. Berlin. Bauer, Adolf. 1893. Die griechischen Kriegsaltertümer, 2nd ed. Munich. Beloch, Julius. 1897. Griechische Geschichte, vol. II. Strasbourg. Berent, Moshe. 2000. “Anthropology and the Classics: War, Violence and the Stateless Polis.” CQ 50.1: 257–289. Bol, Peter C. 1989. Argivische Schilde. Olympische Forschungen XVII. Berlin. Bottini, Angelo. 1988. Antike Helme. Mainz. Bowden, Hugh. 1995. “Hoplites and Homer: Warfare, Hero Cult, and the Ideology of the Polis.” In John Rich and Graham Shipley (eds.), War and Society in the Greek World, London, 45–63. Bryant, Joseph M. 1990. “Military Technology and Socio-Cultural Change in the Ancient Greek City.” Sociological Review 38.3: 484–516. Cartledge, Paul. 1977. “Hoplites and Heroes: Sparta’s Contribution to the Technique of Ancient Warfare.” JHS 97: 11–27. Cartledge, Paul. 1996. “La nascita degli opliti e l’organizzazione militare.” In Salvatore Settis (ed.), I Greci: Storia, Cultura, Arte, Societá, vol. II.I. Formazione, Torino, 681–714. Cartledge, Paul. 2001. “The Birth of the Hoplite: Sparta’s Contribution to Early Greek Military Organization.” In id. (ed.), Spartan Reflections, London, 153–166. Cartledge, Paul. 2013. “Hoplitai/Politai: Refighting Ancient Battles.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 74–84. Cawkwell, George L. 1989. “Orthodoxy and Hoplites.” CQ 39.2: 375–389. Connor, W. Robert. 1988. “Early Greek Land Warfare as Symbolic Expression.” P&P 119: 3–29. Dawson, Doyne. 1996. The Origins of Western Warfare. Militarism and Morality in the Ancient World. Boulder. de Souza, Philip. 2008. “Greek Warfare and Fortification.” In John P. Oleson (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Engineering and Technology in the Classical World, Oxford, 673–690. Delbrück, Hans. 1887. Die Perserkriege und die Burgunderkriege. Berlin. 92 Fernando Echeverría Delbrück, Hans. 1900. Geschichte der Kriegskunst im Rahmen der Politischen Geschichte, vol. I. Berlin (originally published 1900–1908; with new editions to 1920; often reprinted). Detienne, Marcel. 1968. “La phalange. Problèmes et controversies.” In Jean-Pierre Vernant (ed.), Problèmes de la Guerre en Grèce Ancienne, Paris, 119–142. Drews, Robert. 1972. “The First Tyrants in Greece.” Historia 21.2: 129–144. Droysen, Hans. 1889. Heerwesen und Kriegführung der Griechen. Freiburg. Ducrey, Pierre. 1985. Guerre et guerriers dans la Grèce antique. Fribourg. Echeverría, Fernando. 2008. Ciudadanos, Campesinos y Soldados. El Nacimiento de la Polis Griega y la Teoría de la ‘Revolución Hoplita’. Madrid. Echeverría, Fernando. 2010. “Weapons, Technological Determinism and Ancient Warfare.” In Garrett G. Fagan and Matthew Trundle (eds.), New Perspectives on Ancient Warfare, Leiden and Boston, 21–56. Echeverría, Fernando. 2011. “Taktiké Téchne: The Neglected Element in Classical Hoplite Battles.” AncSoc 41: 45–82. Echeverría, Fernando. 2012. “Hoplite and Phalanx in Archaic and Classical Greece: A Reassessment.” CP 107.4: 291–318. Echeverría, Fernando. 2015. “Heroic Fiction, Combat Scenes, and the Scholarly Reconstruction of Archaic Greek Warfare.” BICS 58.1: 33–60. Ehrenberg, Victor. 1932. Der griechische und der hellenistische Staat. Leipzig. Ehrenberg, Victor. 1937. “When Did the Polis Rise?” JHS 57: 147–159. Finley, Moses I. 1970. Early Greece. The Bronze and Archaic Ages. London. Foxhall, Lin. 1995. “Farming and Fighting in Ancient Greece.” In John Rich and Graham Shipley (eds.), War and Society in the Greek World, London, 134–145. Foxhall, Lin. 1997. “A View from the Top. Evaluating the Solonian Property Classes.” In Lynette G. Mitchell and Peter J. Rhodes (eds.), The Development of the Polis in Archaic Greece, London, 113–136. Foxhall, Lin. 2013. “Can We See the ‘Hoplite Revolution’ on the Ground? Archaeological Landscapes, Material Culture, and Social Status in Early Greece.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 194–221. Fraser, A.D. 1942. “The Myth of the Phalanx Scrimmage.” Classical Weekly 36.2: 15–16. Frost, Frank J. 1984. “The Athenian Military Before Cleisthenes.” Historia 33: 283–294. Fustel de Coulanges, Numa D. 1864. La Cité Antique. Paris. Garlan, Yvon. 1972. La Guerre dans l’Antiquité. Paris. (= War in the Ancient World: A Social History, trans. Janet Lloyd, 1975. London). Glotz, Gustave. 1928. La Cité Grecque. Paris. Goldsworthy, Adrian K. 1997. “The Othismos, Myths and Heresies: The Nature of Hoplite Battle.” War in History 4: 1–26. Gomme, Arnold W. 1945. An Historical Commentary on Thucydides, vol. I: Introduction and Commentary on Book I. Oxford. González, Francisco J. and Pedro López-Barja. 2012. “Neocon Greece: V.D. Hanson’s War on History.” IJCT 19.3: 129–151. Greenhalgh, Peter A.L. 1973. Early Greek Warfare. Horsemen and Chariots in the Homeric and Archaic Ages. Cambridge. Grote, George. 1846–1856. A History of Greece, 12 vols. London. Often reprinted (also cited as 1900 = vol. 8). Grundy, George B. 1911. Thucydides and the History of His Age. London. Hanson, Victor D. 1983/19982. Warfare and Agriculture in Classical Greece. Berkeley. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 93 Hanson, Victor D. 1989/19982/20002/20092. The Western Way of War: Infantry Battle in Classical Greece. New York, Berkeley and Los Angeles (2nd ed. variously reprinted). Hanson, Victor D. 1991a. “The Ideology of Hoplite Battle, Ancient and Modern.” In Victor D. Hanson (ed.), Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience, London, 3–11. Hanson, Victor D. 1991b. “Hoplite Technology in Phalanx Battle.” In Victor D. Hanson (ed.), Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience, London, 63–84. Hanson, Victor D. (ed.). 1991c. Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience. London and New York. Hanson, Victor D. 1995/19992. The Other Greeks. The Family Farm and the Agrarian Roots of Western Civilization. Berkeley. Hanson, Victor D. 1996. “Hoplites into Democrats: The Changing Ideology of Athenian Infantry.” In Josiah Ober and Charles Hedrick (eds.), Demokratia: A Conversation on Democracies, Ancient and Modern, Princeton, 289–312. Hanson, Victor D. 2000. “Hoplite Battle as Ancient Greek Warfare: When, Where, and Why?” In Hans van Wees (ed.), War and Violence in Ancient Greece, London, 201–232. Hanson, Victor D. 2013. “The Hoplite Narrative.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 256–275. Helbig, Wolfgang. 1909. “Ein homerischer Rundschild mit eine Bugel.” JÖAI 12: 1–70. Helbig, Wolfgang. 1911. “Über die Einführungszeit der geschlossenen Phalanx.” Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften 12: 3–41. Holladay, A. James. 1982. “Hoplites and heresies.” JHS 102: 94–103. Hornblower, Simon. 2007. “Warfare in Ancient Literature: The Paradox of War.” In Philip Sabin, Hans van Wees and Michael Whitby (eds.), The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Warfare, Volume I: Greece, the Hellenistic World and the Rise of Rome, Cambridge, 22–53. Hunt, Peter. 2007. “Military Forces.” In Philip Sabin, Hans van Wees and Michael Whitby (eds.), The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Warfare, Volume I: Greece, the Hellenistic World and the Rise of Rome, Cambridge, 108–146. Hunt, Peter. 2009. “War and Society.” In George Boys-Stones, Barbara Graziosi and Phiroze Vasunia (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Hellenic Studies, Oxford, 226–237. Hurwit, Jeffrey M. 2002. “Reading the Chigi Vase.” Hesperia 71.1: 1–22. Jarva, Eero. 1995. Archaiologia on Archaic Greek Body Armour. Rovaniemi. Jarva, Eero. 2013. “Arms and Armor. Part I. Arming Greeks for Battle.” In Brian Campbell and Lawrence A. Tritle (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Warfare in the Classical World, Oxford, 395–418. Kagan, Donald and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.). 2013a. Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece. Princeton. Kagan, Donald and Gregory F. Viggiano. 2013b. “The Hoplite Debate.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 1–56. Keegan, John. 1976. The Face of Battle. London. Konijnendijk, Roel. 2016. “Mardonios’ Senseless Greeks.” CQ 66.1: 1–12. Konijnendijk, Roel. 2018. Classical Greek Tactics. A Cultural History. Leiden. Krentz, Peter. 1985. “The Nature of Hoplite Battle.” ClAnt 4.1: 50–61. Krentz, Peter. 1994. “Continuing the Othismos on Othismos.” AHB 8.2: 45–49. Krentz, Peter. 2000. “Deception in Archaic and Classical Greek Warfare.” In Hans van Wees (ed.), War and Violence in Ancient Greece, London, 167–200. Krentz, Peter. 2002. “Fighting by the Rules: The Invention of the Hoplite Agôn.” Hesperia 71.1: 23–39. 94 Fernando Echeverría Krentz, Peter. 2007a. “Warfare and Hoplites.” In H. Alan Shapiro (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Archaic Greece, Cambridge, 61–84. Krentz, Peter. 2007b. “Part I: Archaic and Classical Greece: War.” In Philip Sabin, Hans van Wees and Michael Whitby (eds.), The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Warfare, Volume I: Greece, the Hellenistic World and the Rise of Rome, Cambridge, 147–185. Krentz, Peter. 2010. The Battle of Marathon. New Haven. Krentz, Peter. 2013a. “Hoplite Hell: How Hoplites Fought.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 134–156. Krentz, Peter. 2013b. “Marathon and the Development of the Exclusive Hoplite Phalanx.” In Christopher Carey and Michael Edwards (eds.), Marathon—2,500 Years. Proceedings of the Marathon Conference 2010. London, 35–44. Kromayer, Johannes and Georg Veith. 1903–1907. Antike Schlachtfelder in Griechenland, vol. I. Berlin. Kromayer, Johannes and Georg Veith. 1928. Heerwesen und Kriegführung der Griechen und Römer. Handbuch der Altertumswissenschaft 4.3.2. Munich. Lammert, Eberhard. 1899. “Die geschichtliche Entwicklung der griechischen Taktik.” Neue Jahrbücher für das Klassische Altertum, Geschichte und Deutsche Literatur und für Pädagogik 3: 1–29. Latacz, Joachim. 1977. Kampfparänese, Kampfdarstellung und Kampfwirkichkeit in der Ilias, bei Kallinos und Tyrtaios. München. Lazenby, John F. 1991, “The Killing Zone.” In Victor D. Hanson (ed.), Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience, London, 87–109. Lazenby, John F. and David Whitehead. 1996. “The Myth of the Hoplite’s Hoplon.” CQ 46.1: 27–33. Lee, John W.I. 2013. “The Classical Greek Experience.” In Brian Campbell and Lawrence A. Tritle (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Warfare in the Classical World, Oxford, 143–161. Lendon, John E. 2005. Soldiers and Ghosts: A History of Battle in Classical Antiquity. New Haven and London. Lloyd, Matthew. 2017. “Unorthodox Warfare? Variety and Change in Archaic Greek Warfare (ca. 700–ca. 480 BCE).” In Brian Hughes and Fergus Robson (eds.), Unconventional Warfare from Antiquity to the Present Day, Cham, Switzerland, 231–252. Lorimer, Hilda L. 1947. “The Hoplite Phalanx with Special Reference to the Poems of Archilochus and Tyrtaeus.” ABSA 42: 76–138. Luginbill, Robert D. 1994. “Othismos: The Importance of the Mass-Shove in Hoplite Warfare.” Phoenix 48: 51–61. Matthew, Christopher A. 2009. “When Push Comes to Shove: What Was the Othismos of Hoplite Combat?” Historia 58.4: 395–415. Meyer, Eduard. 1893. Geschichte des Altertums. Zweiter Band, Geschichte des Abendlandes bis auf die Perserkriege. Stuttgart. Millett, P.C. 2013. “Writers on War. Part I Greece: Winning Ways in Warfare.” In Brian Campbell and Lawrence A. Tritle (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Warfare in the Classical World, Oxford, 46–74. Mitchell, Stephen. 1996. “Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece.” In Alan B. Lloyd, (ed.), Battle in Antiquity, London, 87–105. Morgan, Catherine. 2001. “Symbolic and Pragmatic Aspects of Warfare in the Greek World of the 8th to the 6th Centuries BC.” In Tonnes Bekker-Nielsen and Lise Hannestad (eds.), War as a Cultural and Social Force. Essays on Warfare in Antiquity, Copenhagen, 20–44. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 95 Morris, Ian. 1987. Burial and Ancient Society. The Rise of the Greek City-State. Cambridge. Morris, Ian. 1996. “The Strong Principle of Equality and Archaic Origins of Greek Democracy.” In Josiah Ober and Charles Hedrick (eds.), Demokratia: A Conversation on Democracies, Ancient and Modern, Princeton, 19–48. Mossé, Claude. 1968. “Le role politique des armées dans le monde grec a l’époque classique.” In Jean-Pierre Vernant (ed.), Problèmes de la Guerre en Grèce Ancienne, Paris, 221–230. Murray, Oswyn. 1980. Early Greece. Brighton. Nafissi, Massimo. 2009. “Sparta.” In Kurt A. Raaflaub and Hans van Wees (eds.), A Companion to Archaic Greece, Oxford and Malden, 117–137. Nilsson, Martin. 1928. “Die Hoplitentaktik und das Staatswesen.” Klio 22: 240–249. Nilsson, Martin. 1929. “The Introduction of Hoplite Tactics at Rome: Its Date and Its Consequences.” JRS 19: 1–11. Ober, Josiah. 1991. “Hoplites and Obstacles.” In Victor D. Hanson (ed.), Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience, London, 173–196. Ober, Josiah. 1994. “The Rules of War in Classical Greece.” In Michael Howard, George J. Andreopoulos and Mark R. Shulman (eds.), The Laws of War. Constraints on Warfare in the Western World, New Haven, 12–26, 227–230. Osborne, Robin. 1996/20092. Greece in the Making, 1200–479 BC. London. Polignac, François. 1984. La Naissance de la Cité Grecque. Cultes, espace et société, VIIIe-VIIe siècles avant J.-C. Paris. Pritchett, W. Kendrick. 1971–1991. The Greek State at War, 5 vols. Berkeley and Los Angeles. Raaflaub, Kurt A. 1993. “Homer to Solon. The Rise of the Polis. The Written Sources.” In Mogens Herman Hansen (ed.), The Ancient Greek City-State. Symposium on the Occasion of the 250th Anniversary of The Royal Danish Academy of Sciences and Letters, July 1–4 1992. Copenhagen, 41–105. Raaflaub, Kurt A. 1996. “Equalities and Inequalities in Athenian Democracy.” In Josiah Ober and Charles Hedrick (eds.), Demokratia: A Conversation on Democracies, Ancient and Modern, Princeton, 139–174. Raaflaub, Kurt A. 1997. “Soldiers, Citizens and the Early Greek Polis.” In Lynette G. Mitchell and Peter J. Rhodes (eds.), The Development of the Polis in Archaic Greece, London, 49–59. Raaflaub, Kurt A. 2005. “Homerische Krieger, Protohopliten und die Polis: Schritte zur Lösung alter Probleme.” In Burkhardt Meissner, Oliver Schmitt and Michael Sommer (eds.), Krieg, Gesellschaft, Institutionen. Beiträge zu einer vergleichenden Kriegsgeschichte, Berlin, 229–266. Raaflaub, Kurt A. 2008. “Homeric Warriors and Battles: Trying to Resolve Old Problems.” CW 101: 469–483. Raaflaub, Kurt A. 2013a. “Early Greek Infantry Fighting in a Mediterranean Context.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 95–111. Raaflaub, Kurt A. 2013b. “Homer und die Agonie des Hoplitenkampfes.” In Cédric Brélaz and Sylvian Fachard (eds.), Pratiques militaires et art de la guerre dans le monde grec antique: Études offertes à Pierre Ducrey à l’occasion de son 75e anniversaire, Paris, 17–33. Rawlings, Louis. 2000. “Alternative Agonies: Hoplite Martial and Combat Experiences Beyond the Phalanx.” In Hans van Wees (ed.), War and Violence in Ancient Greece, London, 233–259. Rawlings, Louis. 2007. The Ancient Greeks at War. Manchester and New York. Rawlings, Louis. 2013. “War and Warfare in Ancient Greece.” In Brian Campbell and Lawrence A. Tritle (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Warfare in the Classical World, Oxford, 3–28. 96 Fernando Echeverría Ridley, Ronald T. 1979. “The Hoplite as Citizen: Athenian Military Institutions in Their Social Context.” AC 48: 508–548. Rüstow, Wilhelm and Hermann Köchly. 1852. Geschichte des Griechischen Kriegswesens von der Ältesten Zeit bis auf Pyrrhos. Aurau. Salmon, John. 1977. “Political Hoplites?” JHS 97: 84–101. Santosuosso, Antonio. 1997. Soldiers, Citizens, and the Symbols of War. Boulder. Schwartz, Adam. 2002. “The Early Hoplite Phalanx: Order or Disarray?” C&M 53: 31–64. Schwartz, Adam. 2009. Reinstating the Hoplite. Arms, Armour and Phalanx Fighting in Archaic and Classical Greece. Stuttgart. Schwartz, Adam. 2013. “Large Weapons, Small Greeks: The Practical Limitations of Hoplite Weapons and Equipment.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 157–175. Sealey, Raphael. 1976. A History of the Greek City States, ca. 700–338 B.C. Berkeley. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1964. Early Greek Armour and Weapons from the End of the Bronze Age to 600 BC. Edinburgh. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1965a. “The Hoplite Reform and History.” JHS 85: 110–122. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1965b. “L’introduzione degli opliti in Grecie e in Italia.” RSI 77: 434–444. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1967. Arms and Armor of the Greeks. London. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1971. The Dark Age of Greece. An Archeaeological Survey of the Eleventh to the Eighth Centuries BC. Edinburgh. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1980. Archaic Greece. The Age of Experiment. Berkeley. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1986. “Interaction by Design: The Greek City-States.” In Colin Renfrew and John F. Cherry (eds.), Peer Polity Interaction and Socio-Political Change, Cambridge, 47–58. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 1993. “The ‘Hoplite Reform’ Revisited.” DHA 19.1: 47–61. Snodgrass, Anthony M. 2013. “Setting the Frame Chronologically.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 85–94. Storch, Rudolph H. 1998. “The Archaic Greek ‘Phalanx’, 750–650 BC.” AHB 12.1–2: 1–7. Trundle, Matthew. 2001. “The Spartan Revolution: Hoplite Warfare in the Late Archaic Period.” War and Society 19.2: 1–17. van Wees, Hans. 1986. “Leaders of Men? Military Organizations in the Iliad.” CQ 36: 285–303. van Wees, Hans. 1988. “Kings in Combat. Battles and Heroes in the Iliad.” CQ 38.1: 1–24. van Wees, Hans. 1992. Status Warriors: War, Violence and Society in Homer and History. Amsterdam. van Wees, Hans. 1994a. “The Homeric Way of War: The Iliad and the Hoplite Phalanx—I.” G&R 41.1: 1–18. van Wees, Hans. 1994b. “The Homeric Way of War: The Iliad and the Hoplite Phalanx—II.” G&R 41.2: 131–155. van Wees, Hans. 1995. “Politics and the Battlefield: Ideology in Greek Warfare.” In Anton Powell (ed.), The Greek World, London, 153–178. van Wees, Hans. 1996. “Heroes, Knights and Nutters, Warrior Mentality in Homer.” In Alan B. Lloyd, (ed.), Battle in Antiquity, London, 1–86. van Wees, Hans. 1997. “Homeric Warfare.” In Ian Morris and Barry S. Powell (eds.), New Companion to Homer, Leiden, 668–693. The “Hoplite Revolution” and the Nature of Hoplite Warfare 97 van Wees, Hans. 2000. “The Development of the Hoplite Phalanx: Iconography and Reality in the Seventh Century.” In Hans van Wees (ed.), War and Violence in Ancient Greece, London, 125–166. van Wees, Hans. 2001. “The Myth of the Middle-Class Army: Military and Social Status in Ancient Athens.” In Tonnes Bekker-Nielsen and Lise Hannestad (eds.), War as a Cultural and Social Force. Essays on Warfare in Antiquity, Copenhagen, 45–71. van Wees, Hans. 2002. “Tyrants, Oligarchs and Citizen Militias.” In Angelos Chaniotis and Pierre Ducrey (eds.), Army and Power in the Ancient World, Stuttgart, 61–82. van Wees, Hans. 2004. Greek Warfare: Myths and Realities. London. van Wees, Hans. 2006. “Mass and Elite in Solon’s Athens: The Property Classes Revisited.” In Josine H. Blok and André Lardinois (eds.), Solon of Athens. New Historical and Philological Approaches, Leiden, 351–389. van Wees, Hans. 2013. “Farmers and Hoplites: Models of Historical Development.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 222–255. Vidal-Naquet, Pierre. 1968. “La tradition de l’hoplite athénien.” In Jean-Pierre Vernant (ed.), Problèmes de la Guerre en Grèce Ancienne, Paris, 161–181. Viggiano, Gregory F. 2013. “The Hoplite Revolution and the Rise of the Polis.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 112–133. Viggiano, Gregory and Hans van Wees. 2013. “The Arms, Armor, and Iconography of Early Greek Hoplite Warfare.” In Donald Kagan and Gregory F. Viggiano (eds.), Men of Bronze. Hoplite Warfare in Ancient Greece, Princeton, 57–73. Weber, Maximilian. 1922. Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Tübingen. Wheeler, Everett L. 1991. “The General as Hoplite.” In Victor D. Hanson (ed.), Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience, London, 121–170. Wheeler, Everett L. 2007, “Battle. A. Land Battles.” In Philip Sabin, Hans van Wees and Michael Whitby (eds.), The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Warfare, Volume I: Greece, the Hellenistic World and the Rise of Rome, Cambridge, 186–223. Wheeler, Everett L. 2011. “Greece: Mad Hatters and March Hares.” In Lee L. Brice and Jennifer T. Roberts (eds.), Recent Directions in the Military History of the Ancient World, AAH 10, Claremont, CA, 53–104.