Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Commoning the Political, Politicizing the common: Community and the Political in Jean-Luc Nancy, Roberto Esposito and Giorgio Agamben

2018

Setting out from the work of Jean-Luc Nancy, this article engages with post-Heideggerian thought on community, seeking to bring out and to enhance its political thrust for contemporary democracies. It shows how Jean-Luc Nancy, Roberto Esposito and Giorgio Agamben, 'common the political', that is, how they reconsider politics in light of a fundamental sense of coexistence which clears the ground for social openness, solidarity, plurality and autonomy. It then responds to a series of pertinent objections by further politicizing the post-Heideggerian vision of the common. I set out to translate the ontologies of the common into more concrete political logics by relating them to actual political practices and by joining them to the political theory of hegemony and antagonism set out by Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe. Their conjunction of the 'common' with the antagonistic politics of hegemony is tension-ridden, as they draw from conflicting understandings of 'the political', pitting plurality and horizontal relations against division and uneven power. To mitigate that conflict, these two approaches should be situated at different sites of political action, and the hege-monic framework should be recast so as to bring it more into line with horizontalist 'common' politics.

Article Commoning the political, politicizing the common: Community and the political in Jean-Luc Nancy, Roberto Esposito and Giorgio Agamben Alexandros Kioupkiolis School of Political Sciences, Faculty of Economics and Political Sciences, Aristotle University, 54124 Thessaloniki, Greece. alkioup@polsci.auth.gr Abstract Setting out from the work of Jean-Luc Nancy, this article engages with post-Heideggerian thought on community, seeking to bring out and to enhance its political thrust for contemporary democracies. It shows how Jean-Luc Nancy, Roberto Esposito and Giorgio Agamben, ‘common the political’, that is, how they reconsider politics in light of a fundamental sense of co-existence which clears the ground for social openness, solidarity, plurality and autonomy. It then responds to a series of pertinent objections by further politicizing the post-Heideggerian vision of the common. I set out to translate the ontologies of the common into more concrete political logics by relating them to actual political practices and by joining them to the political theory of hegemony and antagonism set out by Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe. Their conjunction of the ‘common’ with the antagonistic politics of hegemony is tension-ridden, as they draw from conflicting understandings of ‘the political’, pitting plurality and horizontal relations against division and uneven power. To mitigate that conflict, these two approaches should be situated at different sites of political action, and the hegemonic framework should be recast so as to bring it more into line with horizontalist ‘common’ politics. Contemporary Political Theory (2017). doi:10.1057/s41296-017-0156-5 Keywords: common; political; plurality; community; antagonism; hegemony In recent years, political thought has evinced a renewed interest in thinking and refiguring community, the commons or, more generically, the ‘common’ (see e.g. Esposito, 2010, 2011, 2013; Dardot and Laval, 2014; Gilbert, 2014; Hardt and Negri, 2009, 2012; Nancy, 2000). What drives such inquiries is arguably not a nostalgia for the ‘lost communities’ of the past, fuelled by resentment and  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory www.palgrave.com/journals Kioupkiolis insecurity in a globalized world. It is rather the quest for new schemes of common action and understanding at a time when there are few collective resistances against the hollowing-out of democracy, when ecological degradation is not effectively addressed through global coordination, when cultural diversity and migration flows fan the flames of racism and xenophobia (Dardot and Laval, 2014, pp. 11–16; Esposito, 2013, p. 43). Responding to such circumstances, the existentialist philosophies of Jean-Luc Nancy, Giorgio Agamben and Roberto Esposito have theorized ways of tying social knots which overcome both fragmentation and the exclusions of closed communities. They envision collective convergences which weld together a plurality of singularities without enclosing them in organic totalities, predefined models and fixed boundaries – ethnic, cultural, ideological or any other (Nancy, 1991, 2000; Agamben, 1993; Esposito, 2013). Such relations construct ‘inessential commonalities’, in which differences can act in concert and in solidarity without fusing together (Agamben, 1993, pp. 86–87). Promising as they may seem, these endeavours to reconfigure the ‘common’ have come in for a battery of criticisms which castigate them as politically irrelevant or impotent. Nancy, Esposito and Agamben remain stuck on the abstract level of a ‘fundamental ontology’ of being-together. They construe the ‘common’ as an ontology of co-existence detached from any actual politics. They do not wrestle with topical issues of democratic politics, such as the dominant forms of power and the specific modes of collective action which could uphold democracy in our times (Marchart, 2012, pp. 173–183; Elliott, 2011; Wagner, 2006; Norris, 2012, p. 155; Dardot and Laval, 2014, pp. 14–15). Delving into the work of Nancy and alluding to cognate ideas of Esposito and Agamben (in The Coming Community), this article engages with post-Heideggerian thought on community and the common driven by the belief that this carries valuable insights and directions for democratic politics today. My aim is precisely to bring out and to enhance its political thrust. As a first step, this article seeks to show how Nancy along with Esposito and Agamben ‘common the political’, that is, how they reconsider politics in light of a fundamental sense of co-existence which clears the ground for social openness, solidarity, plurality and autonomy. At the same time, this article points out the political limits of this existentialist thought. Facing up to them, the argument seeks, at a second stage, to further politicize the post-Heideggerian vision of the common in ways which seek to increase its political import. This is a process of ‘politicizing the common’ which comes after an initial commoning of the political and supplements it. Following in the footsteps of previous similar attempts (Schwarzmantel, 2007; Armstrong, 2009; Vyrgioti, 2015), this article sets out to translate the ontologies of the common into more concrete political logics by relating them to actual political practices and by joining them to the political theory of hegemony and antagonism set forth by Laclau and Mouffe (1985), Mouffe (2000, 2005) and Laclau (2000, 2005). The latter offer a  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common conception of the political which comes to grips with antagonistic conflicts and hegemonic systems of power with a view to forging more democratic relations. The conjunction of the ‘common’ with the antagonistic politics of hegemony is tension-ridden, to say the least, as they draw from conflicting ontologies and understandings of ‘the political’, pitting plurality and horizontal relations – the ‘common’ – against division, exclusion and uneven power – hegemony. This article affirms, however, that their combination can help to advance democracy and that, in order to do so, the clash between the two logics should be mitigated by way of certain crucial moves which are initiated here. Commoning the Political Jean-Luc Nancy embarked on a rethinking of community and the political in a historical circumstance of the 1980s which he grasped as ‘the retreat of the political’ (Lacoue-Labarthe and Nancy, 1997). From the outset, thus, Nancy’s philosophy of the community was animated by a concern with the political. The ‘retreat of the political’ implies the dissolution of politics and democracy into a play of economic and technical forces (Nancy, 1991, pp. xxxviii–xli, 40). It entails also the eclipse of political theology, i.e. of totalitarian politics and political programs which aspire to the realization of an essence of community (Nancy, 2000, p. 37; Nancy, 2010b, pp. 41, 50; 1991, pp. xxxviii–xxxix). These shifts lay bare our fundamental condition of ‘being-with’, stripping it of any transcendent references and exposing it as pure space and numbers (Nancy, 1992, p. 373). The retreat initiates, furthermore, a re-tracing: it raises anew the question of the political starting out from the question of relation as such, rather than from the categories of sovereignty, the subject, the state, metaphysical grounds or managerial criteria (Lacoue-Labarthe and Nancy, 1997, pp. 112, 118–134). This questioning begins at the end of Marxism, and it looks beyond neoliberalism and the new political conformism (p. 145). Hence, Nancy’s rethinking of our existence in common was intended to refigure the political in light of a new ontological reflection on the common. This has been a fundamental theoretical choice and undertaking, which has motivated Nancy’s thought on the political but has also invited several critiques that have taken issue with the very project of elaborating a fundamental ontology, an account of being in general, in order to establish a broad framework for rethinking community and politics (Armstrong, 2009, p. 63; Norris, 2012, p. 144). Indeed, Nancy construes community in terms of a basic ontology of existence, which is primarily a ‘being-in-common’ with others. The originary plurality of beings in the world is at the foundation of Being (Nancy, 2000, p. 12; emphasis in original). Nancy’s quest for a fundamental ontology takes its bearings from Heidegger’s philosophy and its claim that being-with – Mitsein – is essential to  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis existence itself – Dasein. Nancy reconsiders thus the very meaning of politics through the prism of an originary condition of ‘being-many-together’ which precedes and exceeds any particular ‘society’ and ‘individuals’ (pp. xv, 25–26, 93, 41; Nancy, 1992, p. 377). Nancy’s ontology is anti-essentialist as it divests individuals and societies of definite and permanent essence(s). Community is a mode of contiguity and contact between multiple singularities (Nancy, 2000, pp. 5–7; 1991, pp. xxxvii–xxxviii; emphasis in original). Singularities are ‘infraindividual. It is never the case that I have met Pierre or Marie per se, but I have met him or her in such and such a ‘‘form’’, in such and such a ‘‘state’’, in such and such a ‘‘mood’’, and so on’ (Nancy, 2000, p. 8). Community is thus devoid of a proper substance of common Being – of the people, the nation or generic humanity. It cannot be reduced to a unified totality, an Idea, a Subject or a Concept (pp. 47, 54–55, 59–60, 146; Nancy, 1991, pp. xxxviii– xl). Community is just a relation among a plurality of singularities (pp. 4, 6). Community happens, it is an act of association which sets up a space of coappearance and relations. It is a mélange, a dialogue of plural voices, encounters, reciprocal action open to diversity and change, a praxis of sharing, a network of singularities which touch each other without melting together. Hence, what we share in community is essentially a lack of identity (‘finitude’), and the variable limits that render us singular carving out a space between us. By contrast, the fusion of atoms in a collective is the political project of totalitarianism, which brings about the death of community as relations of singularities (pp. 12, 35). It is evident that Nancy’s take on community gestures beyond mainstream ideas of organic community and modern society. An intimate, organic community (the first Christian communities, the Athenian polis, etc.) would be made up of tight and harmonious ties after the model of family and love, while society is typically identified with ‘a simple association and division of forces and needs’ (pp. 9, 76). Nancy’s ‘being-singular-plural’ breaks both with the nostalgia of a lost community (in Rousseau, Hegel and other modern philosophers) and with a figure of ‘society’ whose emergence supposedly dissolved communitarian intimacy into an aggregation of separate atoms. Hence, Nancy’s rethinking of the ‘common’ could help to envision a politics of solidarity and coalescence amidst plurality and openness. On the other hand, its ontological framing is bound, indeed, to raise serious doubts under the late modern pluralism of ‘comprehensive views’ and an increased scepticism over the possibility of objective universal knowledge. A contemporary interpretation of being should reflectively recognize its partiality, its weak grounding and its contestability (White, 2000; Marchart, 2007, pp. 82–83; Dardot and Laval, 2014, pp. 281–282). This recognition and any ensuing attempt to come to grips with the lack of strong foundations are lacking in Nancy. Hence, his vision of a new politics of the common is fully exposed to reasonable objections bearing on the derivation of this politics from a controversial  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common ontological dogma. Furthermore, advancing propositions about being-in-common which would hold true in any time and place seems to contradict head-on the antiessentialist tenor of Nancy, who claims to dispense with permanent essences. Finally, an intellectual labour which operates primarily at the highest level of ‘ontological’ abstraction and does not immerse itself in particular contexts will, most likely, fail to reckon with the specific constraints and possibilities of the latter, hence the numerous charges against the post-Heideggerian ontologies of community, which take them to task for their abstract philosophism, their failure to connect ontology with concrete politics of the common (Dardot and Laval, 2014, pp. 276–283; Marchart, 2007, pp. 80–81; Fynsk, 1991, pp. x–xi; Norris, 2012, p. 155; Elliott, 2011; Wagner, 2006, pp. 93–94). These critiques are pertinent, but they should be partly qualified, and they should not entail a complete dismissal of Nancy’s idea of politics, which can be appropriately revised and supplemented. This reworking is what we will undertake after outlining Nancy’s thought on the political in some detail. Giving the lie to any facile charges of complete apoliticism, Nancy calls for the pursuit of another politics in view of his ontology of being-with. He strives to move beyond the two poles between which modern politics has oscillated: politics as police, the order of power, calculations and relations of force, and the politics of the common subject-substance (Nancy, 1992, pp. 389–390; 1991, pp. xxxvii–xli, 40; Nancy, 2000, p. 25). He does not ignore the political in the guise of power relations, class struggles or the formal abstraction of law, management, the rule of capital and technocratic administration (Nancy, 2000, p. 47). Nor does he deduce directly a model of political organization from his account of plural co-existence. Nancy seeks rather to outline another vision of the political as ‘the place where community as such is brought into play’ (1991, pp. xxxvii), sketching a horizon within which politics should be rethought and remade (Nancy, 2000, pp. 47–55). The community of plural singularities is not only an ontology, but it is also ‘an ethos and a praxis’ (p. 65; emphasis in original). Being-with sets thus limits to legitimate politics, demanding a politics that opens community to the ongoing sharing of multiplicity, the interweaving of singularities who resist completion and fixity (Nancy, 1991, pp. 80–81). It is true that Nancy does not spell out the specific forms which a politics beyond sovereignty, technocracy and common essence could possibly assume. His aim is rather to provide a fundamental background and a norm through which other modes of politics, beyond power and identity, could be figured out in greater detail (pp. xl, 80–81). From this standpoint, ‘the political’ pertains generally to a type of social interaction in which singularities undergo consciously the experience of nonorganic community (p. 40). Thus understood, the political implies primarily openness, plurality, variation, creativity, freedom, equality, infinite justice and struggle. The political turns against atomization and totality, homogenization, fusion, sovereignty, the sacrifice to a cause, the realization of a fixed identity of  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis soil, blood, community or self (Nancy, 1997, pp. 89–91, 103–107, 122). This is the nub of Nancy’s endeavour to ‘common the political’, that is, to refashion politics in accord with his ontology of being-with a plurality of singularities. Let us unpack it. To begin with, Nancy’s favoured politics undertakes to tie social knots through a dialogue among plural voices which persist in their irreducible plurality and escape any unitary truth (Nancy, 1991, p. 76; 1997, pp. 90–93). This politics incessantly weaves a network of links among singularities without conforming to a predefined model. Its sole end is the singular, each time, interlacing of singularities (pp. 111–114). Accordingly, politics should not order the ends of the community; it should not be responsible for the identity and the destiny of the common (Nancy, 2010a, p. 41). Politics should rather provide access to other, not properly political, spheres, which craft meanings and forms of life in common, seeking indefinite ends-inthemselves: arts, language, thought, science, love. A non-totalizing politics should only enable an indefinite multiplicity of creative activities in common, without subsuming their diversity to an all-encompassing figure or an overarching end (p. 26). In Nancy’s view, then, politics is only the process that opens up or sustains the possibility of infinite ends and forms made in common. Democratic politics, however, engages in an ongoing reflection on the limits of politics and the other spheres (2009, pp. 83, 91–94; Nancy, 2010a, p. 33). Furthermore, Nancy’s politics draws the ‘combined lesson of war, law, and ‘‘technological civilization’’… sovereignty is nothing’ (2000, p. 141). In the wake of this insight, the multiplicity of peoples may seek to avoid both the hegemony of a single people and the desire for a sovereign separation of everyone, opting instead for the political articulation of a world federation. In it, each people would give up the modern claim to full sovereignty (p. 141). Nancy concedes that all this is an inconceivable task to be assumed (p. 141). Finally, politics should seek to regulate power according to an ‘incommensurable justice’ of equal freedom (Nancy, 2010a, pp. 50–51; 1993, pp. 71–72). This affirms the incomparable value of any singular being among everyone: ‘Each one…is unique by virtue of a unicity or singularity that obligates infinitely…But, at the same time, strict equality is the regime where these incommensurable(s) are shared (out)’ (Nancy, 2010a, pp. 24–25; emphasis in original). The politics of justice respects the real equality of each unique singularity and the equal sharing of incommensurable freedom (Nancy, 1997, p. 114; 1993, pp. 71–72). Freedom, for Nancy, is primarily the creation of the new and freedom from every established framework. This is ‘the task of politics as the liberation of freedom, as the (re)opening of the space of its inaugural sharing’ (p. 79). Hence, freedom and justice call on politics to configure itself as a space and a practice of contest which allow for the questioning of any given arrangement and any measure of justice. Justice must be done to the singular, and this escapes any prevailing just measure (pp. 75–77).  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common On an endnote, Nancy has occasionally rehearsed the term ‘communism’. But this refers to nothing else but the ontology of being-with, which comes before politics and forces on politics two exigencies: to open the common space to the common itself and to provide for the needs of common life (Nancy, 2010b, pp. 148–151). Nancy states, moreover, that it is necessary to question the ‘ism’ of communism which implies a certain ideologization (p. 149). Hence, Nancy’s ontology of the common and the ‘inoperative community’ turn out to be a questioning and reformulation of historical communism from the standpoint of a post-Heideggerian ontology of Mitsein (see also Nancy, 1991, pp. 43–81). It is apparent, now, that Nancy does articulate a vision of pluralist and open politics which is committed to ‘incommensurable’ freedom and equality beyond both atomization and totalization. However, this idea of politics is, indeed, deeply controversial on account of its ontological framing. Crucially, it is also clear that it remains on a high level of abstraction, and it can be political debilitating in some respects. To begin with, Nancy’s thought dwells largely on a philosophical conception of ‘being singular plural’ without fleshing out the particular figures of political action and organization that could enact it in practice (Marchart, 2012, pp. 178–181). Nancy admits explicitly that his lofty politics, which lives the world as a system of plural singularities beyond sovereignty, ‘does not let itself be conceived of easily’ (Nancy, 2000, p. 141) Translating his ontology into a pragmatic politics remains ‘an unheard-of, inconceivable task’ that we must assume (Nancy, 2000, p. 141). Moreover, he fails to adequately grapple with ‘the political’ in the sense of power relations, divisions, antagonism and the making of collective subjects. Nancy (2000, p. 47) does acknowledge that politics involves also power and struggle. Moreover, at the latest stage of his work, he endorses a notion of politics which regulates force (Nancy, 2010a, pp. 50–51). What is missing, however, is any in-depth engagement with the questions of power, hegemony, antagonism, institutions and the forging of links among differences in order to construct collective subjects (Marchart, 2007, pp. 81–82; Marchart, 2012; Wagner, 2006, pp. 100–101). Accordingly, Nancy’s take on the common and the political seems to be an instance of those pluralist theories castigated by Chantal Mouffe on the grounds that they ‘envisage a pluralism without antagonism….pluralism as a mere valorization of multiplicity, thereby eluding the constitutive role of conflict and antagonism’ (Mouffe, 2013, pp. 14–15). Lastly, Nancy’s recurrent injunction to distance politics from any collective project, end or work (Nancy, 2010a, pp. 26, 41; 1997, pp. 111–116; Elliott, 2011, p. 268; Wagner, 2006, pp. 93–94) seems to install a self-defeating ban on the political determination of collective ends and the pursuit of political projects through collective action. Nancy (1997, p. 89) identifies such politics with totalitarianism and the sacrifice to a cause. But it is not clear why a body politic which undertakes common projects cannot also make room for other ends and  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis activities carried out by particular groups or individuals. Moreover, what is left for politics, beyond technocratic administration and management, if it should refrain from collective choices and works? In a display of self-contradiction, the very kind of politics championed by Nancy – a politics which affords access to multiple spheres of common activity by regulating force according to ‘incommensurable justice’ – must set itself the aim to do so. Despite their divergences from Nancy, the cognate conceptualizations of community put forth by Roberto Esposito and Giorgio Agamben in The Coming Community (1993) do not effectively remedy the defects of his take on politics. These authors share a similar, post-Heideggerian point of departure. And, like Nancy, Esposito – to begin with – has set out to imagine another politics in light of his rethinking of community. The vacuum of ideas brought about by the collapse of communism, the erection of walls around closed communities, the bodies of starving people and refugees urge us to reactivate thought on community (Esposito, 2013, pp. 43–44, 78). Drawing his bearings from Martin Heidegger and George Bataille, Esposito (2013) grasps again community as an originary opening to the others and an escape from the self (pp. 25, 44). Community is a transcendental condition of our existence which calls on us to preserve it by opposing the collapse of community into its opposite: closure to otherness, identity and fusion (pp. 14, 29, 36). As in Nancy, community is a pure relation that joins multiple subjects without forming a subject or an entity and without tying bonds of belonging around language, soil and ethnicity (pp. 29, 38, 48, 53; Esposito, 2010, pp. 15–16, 135–138). Community exposes everyone to an irreducible alterity. The common does not pertain thus to an authentic and proper self, but to the improper; what is general, anonymous, undetermined by any essence, race or sex (Esposito, 2013, pp. 29–30, 45–46). The aspiration to a community which embodies a unified totality marks the logic of totalitarianism, which leads to the death of community as a primary aperture and relation (pp. 15, 17, 29–30). Esposito breaks new conceptual ground by associating community with an original ‘munus’ and with processes of immunization. Esposito (2013) posits, in effect, a fundamental, conflictual conjunction of communitas and immunitas (pp. 48–49; Esposito, 2011, pp. 5–6, 9). The Latin etymology of community derives the common from munus, which means obligation and gift (communitas: cum + munus). What binds us together is a reciprocal gift and a duty which obligate us to the others, inducing us to care for them in a non-invasive way (Esposito, 2013, pp. 14, 18, 25–26, 48–49; 2010, pp. 2–6, 97). Community destabilizes thus the boundaries of the person, exposing them to contagion by others. This exposure engenders risks and fears, and it stimulates thus counter-processes of immunization. ‘Whereas communitas opens, exposes, and turns individuals inside out, freeing them to their exteriority, immunitas returns individuals to themselves, encloses them once again in their own skin’ (Esposito, 2013, p. 49). Through immunity, individual or  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common collective entities close in upon themselves and seek to relieve themselves of obligations towards others, conserving their ‘essence’ as owners of their selves (Esposito, 2013, pp. 38–43, 48–49; 2010, p. 13; 2011, pp. 2–5, 44, 154–155). Immunization in its diverse manifestations defines the historical moment we live (Esposito, 2013, p. 58). The logic of immunity fuels political fundamentalism, nationalism, racism and fascism. Hence, according to Esposito (2013, pp. 55–6), the challenge for politics today is to counteract this logic and to foster instead community and freedom. Against the dynamics of immunization, we should embrace then a singular and plural logic in which differences are affirmed as the bond that holds the world together, living and enacting the global system of differences (pp. 65, 71–74). Esposito’s ‘affirmative biopolitics’ would connect a diversity of impersonal singularities rather than individuals caught up in exclusionary identities. Singularities are internally multiple, impure, and they liaise with external multiplicities. Impersonal singularity breaks through static barriers and identities, constituting a unique being which is both singular and plural (Esposito, 2012, pp. 145, 150–151). Esposito (2013) admits that ‘transforming this philosophical formula into actual practice, into a political logic, isn’t easy. And yet we have to find a way…’ (p. 65; see also p. 78). The problem of philosophic abstraction from concrete political practices and orientation besets thus again Esposito’s theorization of community and the political. The political irrelevance of this current of thought is only compounded by the very fact that Nancy and Esposito locate their ontological framing of politics, i.e. their construal of being-in-common, on the plane of an originary and fundamental condition. By definition, this condition is given from the outset. It is not something to be produced or instituted. Hence, it is not the object of a politics (Fynsk, 1991, pp. x–xi). In their defence, Nancy and Esposito could remind us that, on their view, the fundamental situation of being singular plural can be, and has been, distorted by totalizing politics or atomization. They suggest, thus, that their ontology of beingin-common should orient politics as a limit and a condition to uphold (Nancy, 2000, pp. 47–65, 141; 1991, pp. 80–81; 2010a; Esposito, 2013, pp. 65, 71–74). Yet, even with this qualification, they can always foment political quietism insofar as they assert that plurality, openness and relations free of fixed identities are the ontological ground of our existence, rather than contingent objectives and precarious forms which should be politically constructed and striven for (Elliott, 2011). Finally, in his Coming Community, Giorgio Agamben, too, takes up the themes of the singular and the common in order to outline the politics of improper singularity in a community-to-come. Singularities appear and act in common without holding on to any determinate identity or bonds of belonging (Agamben, 1993, pp. 86–7, 105). Pure singularities that communicate with each other but are shorn of any common property are ‘the exemplars of the coming community’ (p.  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis 11). Such singularities are ‘whatever’; they appear and they act in particular manners. But their manners are indeterminate and variable, open to new possibilities (pp. 2, 19, 29, 44, 57). If ‘humans were to succeed in belonging to impropriety as such… a singularity without identity…only the thus, their singular exteriority and their face, then they would for the first time enter into a community without presuppositions and without subjects’ (p. 65). According to Agamben, this is the political task of our times: to select the features that will enable contemporary human beings to survive as singularities who are only the faces and the modes of being that they expose each time, and who communicate only this variable exteriority, rather than any internal essence or abiding predicate (pp. 65, 93–94). A community of singularities features an ‘inessential commonality, a solidarity that in no way concerns an essence’ (p. 18; emphasis in original). It is what takes place among them, their communication, which does not unite them in an identity but scatters them in existence (p. 19). The common place of singularities is a space of ‘ease’, an empty place in which they can move freely and approximate each other at an opportune time (p. 25). The politics of whatever singularity is thus devoid of determinate content. It is a common appearance, action and pure cobelonging that refuse to vindicate any identity which can be represented in the State. Hence, the ‘novelty of the coming politics is that it will no longer be a struggle for the conquest or control of the State, but….an insurmountable disjunction between whatever singularity and the State organization’ (p. 85). It would seem that, as distinct from Nancy and Esposito, Agamben envisions primarily a coming politics of singularity and community, rather than a fundamental condition of co-existence which is already there. Yet, this discrepancy should not be overstated (as in Vyrgioti, 2015). In a later Postface to the 2001 Italian edition, Agamben intimates that ‘the coming does not mean the future’ and that the condition of ‘whatever singularity’ is becoming a reality in the present time which ‘comes after the last day’ (Agamben, 2001, p. 91; emphasis in original). On the other hand, both Nancy and Esposito also call for ‘a politics to come’, a politics of plural singularities in common who resist the contemporary disfiguration of community and the power politics of modernity (see e.g. Nancy, 2000, pp. 47–65; Esposito, 2013, pp. 65, 71–74). The crux is, however, that just like Nancy’s and Esposito’s, Agamben’s politics of a ‘community to come’ (in the homonymous essay) remains vague and elusive. Agamben sees some elements of a political realization in the Tiananmen demonstrations, only to end on an impasse: ‘Wherever these singularities peacefully demonstrate their being in common there will be a Tiananmen, and, sooner or later, the tanks will appear’ (1993, p. 87).  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common Politicizing the Common These valid criticisms notwithstanding, we will make now the case that postHeideggerian thought on community can be re-politicized, or more fully politicized, in ways which rescue its political value for the contemporary world. The work of repoliticization or deeper politicization will involve several different gestures. Coming to grips with hegemonic structures of power, antagonisms, the making of political ties and alternative institutions is necessary, indeed, in order to effectively challenge and change the ruling regime of neoliberal power by welding together broad alliances out of dispersed differences. It is necessary in order to advance precisely the kind of open pluralist and egalitarian commons cherished by post-Heideggerian philosophers. Otherwise, we are left indeed in a political vacuum of ethical injunctions and abstract philosophizing. Such objections are to the point, but they should not entail a dismissal of Nancy’s, Esposito’s and Agamben’s notions of the common and the political. Openness to the others, plurality, sharing and solidarity beyond differences, variation, creativity, singularity and equality, infinite justice, resistance to homogenization, totality and atomization, opposition to closed identities of soil, blood, community or self: all these are cardinal values of a politics which aspires to equal freedom and justice in a globalized, diverse, fragmented and dramatically unequal world. The critiques should trigger, rather, efforts to politicize the ontologies of being singular plural, turning them into political orientations and bringing them closer to the rough ground of actual politics. A first move in this direction should set out to politicize ontology. Every politics is informed by a particular sense of being – of the way human actors, society and nature are (see White, 2000). Ontological reflection contributes thus to clarity, selfunderstanding, critique and change. But there is no place today for an objective fundamental ontology that would lay claim to universal validity. Every account of how ‘things are’ is partial, in conflict with other understandings of the real and inflected by political values and choices. Hence, any ontology of being singular plural should be recast as political: an interpretation of social being which rests on reasonable arguments and evidence but does not grasp the whole, it is imbued with value choices and it remains subject to question. Moreover, solidarity beyond specific identities (national, ideological, racial, etc.), and being-in-common beyond atomization and homogenization are not a fundamental fact of the world but partial moments, and values to be actively pursued. Therefore, political ontology should be further transcribed into a political logic, a political orientation that guides collective action, rather than posing as an already existing reality and foundation.  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis This transcription already signals a third gesture of politicization. Political action, particularly when it seeks to overturn prevailing systems of power, should not condemn itself to a subsidiary role, subservient to ends which are determined in established social fields. Hence, political praxis cannot forswear the determination of collective ends and projects. Nancy is right to oppose a totalizing politics which intends to pre-empt the ends of all social activities and to demand a sacrifice to ultimate causes. But there is no reason why political activity which engages in common enterprises could not forgo such totalizing aspirations and make also room for undertakings which are not designed by the body politic. Democratic politics is about the collective and deliberate determination of common ends. But it needs not, and should not, be totalizing. Nancy seems to pose a false alternative between totalitarian politics or politics that sets itself no ends and projects. In any case, politics is effectively located in any field of action where collective choices are made – through struggle, relations of power or egalitarian decision-making in common. A fourth major step in the work of politicization should link the idea of community sketched out by Nancy, Esposito and Agamben with contemporary political activities which partly instantiate it. Such an empirical grounding can demonstrate the actual pertinence of the philosophy of plural being in common. It also helps to develop a middle level of theorizing, which is situated beyond abstract, general philosophizing and the detailed description of particular cases. In effect, since the turn of the century, a vast literature on social movements has shown that a wide array of collective mobilizations are marked by the precise features that single out ‘inessential community’ in Nancy, Esposito and Agamben’s thought. A variety of organizations, resistances and collective initiatives which have surged forth over the last decades in Latin America, across Europe and in various other sites configure open and horizontal associations which manage directly their affairs through consensus and decentralized decision-making. They build loose network coalitions, but they are pluralist and they do not adhere to a master plan of social restructuring, nor do they strive to forcibly implement their models (see Day, 2005, pp. 25–45, 186–197; Dixon, 2014; Arditi, 2007; Beasley-Murray, 2010; Holloway, 2005). Such communities exceed thus the logic of state politics, sovereign power, definite political programs, fixed models, common substances and closed identities. More recently, the Indignados and Occupy mobilizations in 2011–2012 embodied likewise communities of action rather than of a common ethnic, religious, etc. substance. They performed openness, plurality and solidarity beyond particular identities, dismissing ideological closures, state sovereignty and hegemonic structures (see e.g. Sitrin and Azzellini, 2014; Taylor et al, 2011; Dhaliwal, 2012; Giovanopoulos and Mitropoulos, 2011).  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common To begin with, they crafted open communities of political participation. The movements were organized in public squares where they set up popular assemblies, creating thus spaces of free and plural action in concert. The very choice of public squares and streets to establish assemblies, in its contrast to decision-making behind closed doors, makes evident the will to open up political activity to any and all (Nez, 2012, p. 131) Their processes of collective decision-making opened political power to common citizens, striking down informal and institutional barriers to participation (Dhaliwal, 2012, pp. 265–266). Occupied squares were redesigned as ‘spaces to do politics without politicians’ (Dhaliwal, 2012, p. 263) available to ordinary citizens, poor, non-experts and socially marginalized people (see also Giovanopoulos and Mitropoulos, 2011, pp. 43–54, 221). As a result, the squares became ‘a magnetic furnace where strangers that once walked anywhere alone meet, mix’, performing Agamben’s community as a space of ease in which people can move freely and approximate each other as they wish (Dhaliwal, 2012, p. 259; Agamben, 1993, p. 25). Second, openness went hand in hand with plurality and diversity. The Indignados and Occupy rose up against material inequalities, debt, foreclosures and the economic system that engenders them in complicity with states. But they were ‘movement[s] with people of many … political persuasions’ (Harcourt, 2011). They actively promoted diversity by foreswearing ideological closures and strict programmatic definitions and by articulating, through their assemblies, a spacious discourse hospitable to many different people (Dhaliwal, 2012, pp. 263–265; see also Stavrides, 2012; Nez, 2012; Giovanopoulos and Mitropoulos, 2011, pp. 43–54, 221). Moreover, Occupy and the Indignados helped diverse singularities to converge by knitting horizontal, decentralized networks which enable collaboration without suppressing the freedom of singularities (Castells, 2012; Tejerina and Perugorria, 2012). Openness and plurality in such communities of action were further nurtured by a political culture which cultivates critical respect for differences, civility, generosity, a relaxed atmosphere of debate, and an affective politics which sustains relations of care among diverse people (see Dixon, 2014, pp. 90, 228–229). Hence, the 2011 ‘square movements’ broke with the homogeneous unity of the people or the masses and made open plurality the very foundation of their cohesion, pitting a variety of forces, ideas and actions against a common enemy. Finally, the movements in question opposed the politics of representation, state sovereignty and hegemony, championing instead horizontality and political equality. They refused to make demands on the state, and the deliberately sought to enforce the equal rule of all against the hegemony of leaders and sovereign representatives by working out new practices of self-governance through an egalitarian and consensual deliberation that is accessible to all. The 2011 democratic movements implemented, thus, binding mandates and alternation in the posts of spokespersons, discussion moderators and special working-groups.  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis They set strict time limits and used rotation and lot to allocate the opportunity to speak in the assembly. They recognized only individuals, and no groups, as equal participants in the procedures of political deliberation. (Dhaliwal, 2012, pp. 262–263; Stavrides, 2012; Nez, 2012, pp. 132–134; Giovanopoulos and Mitropoulos, 2011, pp. 52–66, 113, 333; Lorey, 2014, pp. 50–55; Graeber, 2012; Sitrin and Azzellini, 2014; Taylor et al, 2011). In all these respects, the recent ‘square movements’ and other contemporary figures of collective action exemplify the idea of community put forth by Nancy, Esposito and Agamben: community as an open relation among a plurality of singularities, a happening, an act of association, a dialogue of plural voices, reciprocal action exposed to diversity and change, a practice of sharing which is never complete, a network of singular differences, a space of free convergence, politics beyond sovereignty and the state. A fifth and last politicizing intervention should combine being in common as construed by Nancy and Esposito with a political conception that thinks through two key political dimensions which are left unaddressed in their philosophy: antagonism in the sense of division and conflict between irreconcilable positions, and hegemony as the relations of force underlying the dominant order of society and the effective process of building new political communities. The work of Laclau and Mouffe (1985), Laclau (1990, 2005) and Mouffe (2000, 2005, 2013) is particularly suited to this task. It is a major contribution to the contemporary rethinking of both hegemony and antagonism, which is intended to promote plural and egalitarian democracy. However, the conjunction of the plural, open and horizontal common with hegemonic politics is a controversial idea and a daunting task since they embody antagonistic political logics and practices. As a political logic, hegemony entails the drawing of political frontiers, exclusions and processes of concentration of power, convergence on common identities and representation, which set limits to plurality, the affirmation of singularity, openness, horizontality and sharing (Laclau, 2000, pp. 207–212). In the thought of Mouffe and Laclau, hegemony is informed by an ontology of ‘the political’ which sees it ‘as a space of power, conflict and antagonism’ (Mouffe, 2005, p. 9; ‘the moment of negativity (radical investment, opaqueness of representation, division of the object) is irreducible…It is around a constitutive lack that the social is organized’ (Laclau, 2005, pp. 239, 244). For Nancy, what is primary is community as the ongoing sharing of multiplicity, ‘the interweaving of singularities’, and ‘the political’ is reconsidered in light of this idea. By contrast, Laclau and Mouffe accord primacy to division, antagonism, lack and hegemony as unequal power relations. Although for both post-Heideggerians and Laclau-and-Mouffe ‘plurality’ is constitutive of community and the political, the latter oppose head-on any conception of plurality as a pure multiplicity which does not entail intrinsically division, lack of unity and the need for hegemonic  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common constructions; they contradict, that is, precisely the notion of plurality found in the work of Nancy, Esposito and Agamben (in The Coming Community). For Laclau and Mouffe, plurality implies essentially antagonism and failed unity, which call intrinsically for ‘hegemony’ and ‘articulation’ in order to construct partial and precarious social formations (Mouffe, 2013, pp. 14–15; Laclau, 2005, pp. 223–224; Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, pp. 93–148). These deeper ontological and theoretical collisions between the theory of Laclau and Mouffe and post-Heideggerian views of the political as the common translate also into more specific political oppositions, which I will discuss in detail later on. The remainder of the paper will carry on with the last step of ‘politicizing the common’ by facing up to challenge of welding together the contradictory logics of the plural common and hegemony. I will put forward three relevant claims, among others. First, any attempt at joining together the two logics should remain fully alert to their conflict so as to be able to partly control and to mitigate it. Second, hegemony and the plural common could be brought together mainly as political strategies and orientations (‘logics’), not as fundamental general ontologies whose claim to universality would rule out antagonistic alternatives. Third, a constructive conjunction which serves the politics of plural, open and egalitarian communities should activate the two logics at different levels and sides. The logic of the common should inform primarily the internal workings of democratic communities of action and struggle, while the logic of hegemony and antagonism should apply mainly to the confrontation with the enemies of plurality, openness, equality and sharing. Last, to limit the effects of their mutual subversion, particularly the destruction of the open common by the centralizing and homogenizing grip of hegemony, the latter should be critically recast so as to become more congruent with plurality, horizontality, egalitarianism and openness. The following, final section initiates the attempt to reconfigure hegemonic politics in the spirit of the common. Hegemony and the Common From the standpoint of Laclau and Mouffe, hegemony is necessary in order to transform contemporary societies in the direction of open and plural communities. A randomly dispersed plurality of movements, fights and alternative practices of the ‘common’ is unlikely to bring about broader social change as it is likely to founder on incoherence, conflicts among heterogeneous courses of action and the weakness of fragmented, isolated forces which are confronted with vested interests. To achieve a minimum of convergence among diverse struggles and to amass enough force to challenge the status quo, we need to engage in the politics of hegemony which articulates wider political communities through chains of  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis equivalence, defines an enemy, draws frontiers between ‘us’ and ‘them’, and instils into different actors a modicum of collective identity (Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, pp. 140–141, 178–184; Mouffe, 1991, p. 70; 2013, pp. 73–74). Hegemony is, more specifically, the political practice which constructs a new social order starting out from an antagonistic confrontation between rival social sectors. Diverse demands and groups can become equivalent by means of their common opposition to an enemy. They forge thus a ‘chain of equivalence’ that unites them beyond their particularities. This chain will coalesce into a collective subject if a particular force within it rises to become the general representative of all equivalent struggles and claims, functioning as a centre of cohesion. To this end, the identity of a particular actor must be partly divested of its particular contents so as to serve as a wider symbol that represents and brings together the entire community of differences (Laclau, 2005, pp. 93, 2000, pp. 207–212). Hegemony is based on an unequal distribution of power within the oppositional front, since a particular actor must accede to a position of leadership, and against the enemy who must be excluded and eventually overwhelmed in order to found a new hegemonic order (Laclau, 2000, pp. 207–208). Hegemonic politics is also a politics of representation, insofar as a particular force pursues common ends and projects in the name of an entire bloc of forces (Laclau, 1996, pp. 98–100). Laclau and Mouffe have championed a particular idea of radical democratic community drawing on a conception of ‘the political’ which is elided with hegemony and antagonism (Mouffe, 2005, pp. 8–9, 17; 2000, pp. 22, 130; Laclau and Mouffe, pp. 134–145). Antagonism consists in an unbridgeable division between ‘us’ and ‘them’, ‘friend’ and ‘enemy’, whereby the presence of the other negates my identity (Mouffe, 2005, pp. 15–18; Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, pp. 111–114, 125–130). Antagonism is an always present possibility of social relations, because plurality generates radical disagreement in the realm of politics and justice. Hence, for Laclau and Mouffe, ‘the political’ pertains to ‘a choice between conflicting alternatives’. And when they are taken amidst dissent, political decisions settle on one or the other alternative according to the prevalent relations of force (Mouffe, 2000, p. 130; 2000, p. 105; Laclau, 1991, p. 90). Every social order is thus hegemonic in that it rests upon a particular configuration of forces and a set of political exclusions (Mouffe, 2005, pp. 17–18; Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, pp. 134–145). The hegemonic conception the plural common converges partly with the contemporary existentialist ways. For Laclau and Mouffe, what holds together a radical and plural democratic community, which is hegemonically established, is not a substantive notion of the common good, but a collective identification with the political principles of freedom and equality and a shared commitment to their expansion (Mouffe, 1991, pp. 76–82; Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, pp. 176–186). Hence, as in the thought of Nancy, Esposito and Agamben, the common of radical democracy is plural and open. It escapes the dichotomy between a modern society  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common diluted into an aggregate of atoms and a premodern community organized around a specific idea of the good (Mouffe, 1991, p. 75). In Laclau and Mouffe’s radical democratic common, the mutual recognition of certain ethico-political values respects individual liberty and allows for a diversity of more specific allegiances. The political community lacks thus a fully fixed identity or a final unity. It is subject to ongoing re-enactment and it does not make up a unitary subject. The common consists, rather, in the precarious and provisional articulation of a multiplicity of spaces, social relations, movements, forms of identification and democratic practices which retain their partial autonomy (Mouffe, 1991, pp. 77, 79–80; Laclau, 1991, pp. 95–96; Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, pp. 176–193). However, a sea of distance still separates Laclau and Mouffe’s hegemonic conception of a plural common from Nancy, Esposito and Agamben’s being-incommon. For the latter, the common exceeds and negates boundaries, exclusions, fixed demarcations, sovereignty, top-down rule and the state (Nancy, 1991, pp. xxxvii–xli, 40, 80–81; 1997, pp. 89–91, 103–107, 122; 2010a, p. 26; 1993, p. 79; Esposito, 2013, pp. 14, 25, 29, 36, 49; Agamben, 1993, pp. 19, 25, 85–7, 105). In sharp contrast, the politics of hegemony dictates the concentration of force, a measure of substantive collective identity, political frontiers and exclusions, an involvement with the state. For Mouffe (2013, pp. 75–78, 84, 124), division, delimitation from others, partially fixed collective identities, the state and political representation are key constituents of her radical and plural democracy, hence Mouffe’s uneasiness with contemporary movements such as Occupy and Indignados. Their aspiration to plurality and openness without boundaries, their opposition to institutional representation, their commitment to consensus, horizontality and decentralization, their quest for the ‘common’ outside the state are denounced as an inadequate strategy for democratic transformation, which is rooted in a flawed conception of ‘the political’ (pp. 109–127). According to her, ‘15 M [the ‘Indignados’ in Spain] would have come to nothing without Podemos’, i.e. without political representation and engagement with state institutions (Mouffe in Mouffe and Errejón, 2016, pp. 70, 76). Commenting on the 2011 ‘anti-institutional’ mobilizations, Laclau (2014, p. 9) has also affirmed unequivocally that ‘the horizontal dimension of autonomy will be incapable, left to itself, of bringing about long-term historical change if it is not complemented by the vertical dimension of ‘‘hegemony’’ – that is, a radical transformation of the state’. It seems thus that the post-Marxist, hegemonic approach to the making of plural democratic commons clashes head-on with the fully inclusionary, wildly diverse, horizontal, consensual, decentralized, caring, non-sovereign, non-statist and nonrepresentative spirit of the common which animates both post-Heideggerian thought and contemporary mobilizations. The two, accordingly, appear impossible to combine so as to enable horizontal communities to come to grips with  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis antagonisms, power structures and the need to craft broader political communities of struggle and change. Yet, both Laclau and Mouffe have called for such an alliance between the logic of hegemony and the plural logic of autonomy, even in most recent years. ‘Instead of opposing extra-parliamentary to parliamentary struggle, thereby eschewing the possibility of common action, the objective should be to jointly launch a counterhegemonic offensive against neo-liberalism’. ‘It’s clear that the democratic demands that exist in our societies cannot find an expression solely through the vertical form, that they also need horizontal forms of expression’ (Mouffe, 2013, p. 127; Mouffe in Mouffe and Errejón, 2016, p.125). For Laclau (2014, p. 9), the Indignados, Occupy Wall Street and the piqueteros in Argentina, among others, incarnate the horizontal dimension of ‘‘autonomy’’: ‘To advance both in the direction of autonomy and hegemony is the real challenge to those who aim for a democratic future’. In the work of Laclau and Mouffe, however, the awareness of a conflictual bind between hegemony and autonomy has not given rise to any systematic endeavour to work through the tension with a view to reducing the risk of destruction, mainly of autonomous plural politics by hegemonic forces. Such an undertaking is vital for any contemporary politics that seeks to bring together the two logics so as to canvass an adequate strategy for the expansion of open, diverse and self-organized commons. It should be stressed, however, that the combination of the two political logics could only be partial, risky and tension-ridden as they move in different directions (horizontality vs verticality, openness and diversity vs frontiers and exclusions, etc.). A first step towards moderating the conflict would dispense with essentialist hegemonic definitions which identify ‘the political’ solely with antagonism, exclusions and power relations, ruling out consensus, maximum inclusion and an equal distribution of power. ‘The political’ as the active determination of social relations and collective ends manifests itself in various guises, which display both strife and dialogue, both antagonism and attempts at a mutually acceptable agreement, both power struggles and solidarity, both preservation of the status-quo and creative transformations. A complementary step is to pass from the level of ontological speculation to the level of political practices and orientations – from political ontology to political logic(s), which imply different modes of organizing political action and of governing political associations. This gesture parallels and supplements the same transition we commended above for the ontological thought of Nancy, Esposito and Agamben. If we remain on the plane of ontology, the two contending approaches are impossible to combine. Their ontologies claim to offer a comprehensive and fundamental account of the real, and their respective pictures are at odds with each other and could not coexist in the same world. For Nancy, for example, what is fundamental and primordial, before societies and individuals, is ‘being-many 2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common together’. For Laclau and Mouffe, it is ‘being-many-against’: division, antagonism, lack of unity. Furthermore, to avert the absorption of grassroots horizontal communities by the bureaucratic institutions of the state or the market, the conjunction between horizontalism and verticalism should be disjunctive, sustaining thus the mutual agonistic contest and the independence of each political practice. An enhanced awareness of the tensions between the different aspects of counter-hegemonic politics and a committed effort to keep them apart will be necessary in order to effectively uphold the different qualities of political agency in its various directions. Moreover, the politics of hegemony and the politics of open and plural commons should be performed with different strengths at different sides and levels of sociopolitical activity. The drawing of antagonistic frontiers, the making of collective identities, the banding of forces, the exclusion of particular politics and social forms, the struggle to overpower the opponent should be undertaken primarily outwards – against the advocates and the beneficiaries of unjust, oppressive, exclusionary, homogenizing and unequal relations. The drive to create inclusionary, free, egalitarian and diverse commons should inform mostly the ties and interactions within the multiple movements which coalesce against common adversaries: the political forces which defend old or new enclosures, hierarchies and injustices. In other words, the politics of hegemony should be turned against its upholders with a view to minimizing structures of domination, expulsion and closed identity across all social fields. Finally, a series of particular attitudes, ethics, arts and strategies can help to successfully negotiate the tension between the two logics in favour of the open and plural common. The hegemonic leg of the pair is typically more powerful and imperious as it is better resourced, better organized, relatively isolated from direct collective influence and, most often, power-mongering. Therefore, effective steps need to be taken in order to tilt the balance of force between vertical hegemony and the plural autonomy of the common in favour of the latter. First, any higher-level concentration of power in representative institutions, spoke councils, etc. should emanate from the bottom, and grassroots communities should be configured in ways which promote openness, diversity and the decentralization of decision-making. Second, any residues of hegemonic politics – of unification, leadership and representation – that are still accepted within horizontal communities on the grounds of political efficacy should be radically transfigured in ways which foster egalitarianism, autonomy and a spacious diversity. Among others, a regular rotation in roles of responsibility and leadership, such as those of co-ordinator or spokesperson, can contribute to a wide sharing of knowledge and power, the acquisition of skills and the empowerment of large numbers of people. Moreover, full transparency, accountability and revocability of councilpersons, delegates and representatives enable the collective grassroots to  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis retain control over leadership functions (Dixon, 2014, pp. 186–188, 190–196; della Porta and Rucht, 2015, pp. 222–131). Besides, in order to safeguard the plurality and openness of the common, different modes of unification and community-building are in order, opposing drives towards homogeneity and closure. Hence, diversity, inclusion and a shared opposition to forces which impose uniform models could become the very foundation of convergence and community. This has been indeed the case with various recent democratic movements, such as Occupy Wall Street, which stood up in common against the ‘1%’ but celebrated the diversity of perspectives, intentions and desires which they encompassed (Harcourt, 2011). Conclusion Ours is a time of pervasive social diversity, tighter global interconnections, social fragmentation, disillusionment with democracy, growing oligarchic tendencies, steepening inequalities and rising xenophobia. It is urgent, thus, to rethink the social bond and collective action. And this rethinking should be conducted in terms of an irreducible plurivocity and a political praxis that knits an open network of links among singularities without conforming to pre-established models or substantial closed identities, hence the importance of Nancy, Esposito and Agamben’s thought on ‘inessential’ commonality. To put flesh on the bones of this idea of the common and to make it politically relevant, contemporary philosophy needs to politicize its abstract ontological discourse, while preserving its cutting edges and its broader remit. A key step in this direction is to regain contact with real politics on the ground. Recent mobilizations such as the Indignados and Occupy Wall Street have formed communities of action which are open, consensual and self-organized. They embrace diversity, they empower ordinary people on a footing of equality and they oppose fixed hierarchies and closed ideologies. In all these respects, they have staged specific enactments of the open, plural, free and ‘inessential’ common envisioned by Nancy, Esposito and Agamben. Hence, they indicate how an elusive theorizing about ‘being singular plural’ and ‘the coming community’ could be transcribed into more specific political action. A second major gesture would be to join the philosophy of the plural common to political thought and practice which give due recognition to what the former leaves unaddressed: power structures, fundamental antagonisms, the construction of collective identities and the organization of collective action. Laclau and Mouffe’s ‘theory of hegemony’ and agonistic democracy contains valuable intellectual resources on this front. But their conception, and any other ‘realistic’ take on power politics, should be radically revised in order to minimize repression, exclusion and inequality in the new commons of democratic struggles. This can help to strike a  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common productive balance between political efficacy and the actual cultivation of another ethos of the common. About the Author Alexandros Kioupkiolis is assistant professor in contemporary political theory at the School of Political Sciences, Aristotle University, in Thessaloniki, Greece. His research interests lie in modern philosophies of freedom, theories of democracy and the commons, critical theories of power. He has published four books and numerous articles on these topics. Recent publications include the edited volume Radical Democracy and Collective Movements Today (Ashgate/Routledge, 2014); the monographs Freedom after the Critique of Foundations: Marx, Liberalism and Agonistic Autonomy (Palgrave/Macmillan, 2012), The Commons of Freedom (in Greek, Exarchia Editions, 2014); and the articles ‘Common Democracy. Political Representation beyond Representative Democracy’, Democratic Theory (2017), 4.1, pp. 35–58, and ‘Acts, events and the Creation of the New’, Constellations (2017), 24.1, pp. 27–39. References Agamben, G. (1993) The Coming Community, Translated by M. Hardt. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press. Agamben, G. (2001) La comunità che viene, Nuova edizione accresciuta. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri. Armstrong, P. (2009) Reticulations: Jean-Luc Nancy and the Networks of the Political. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Arditi, B. (2007) Post-hegemony: politics outside the usual post-Marxist paradigm. Contemporary Politics 13(3): 205–226. Beasley-Murray, J. (2010) Posthegemony: Political Theory in Latin America. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Castells, M. (2012) Where are the ‘indignados’ going? http://www.irishleftreview.org/2012/01/27/ indignados/, accessed 25/03/2013. Dardot, P. and Laval, C. (2014) Commun. Paris: La Découverte. Day, R.J.F. (2005) Gramsci is dead. Anarchist Currents in the Newest Social Movements. London: Pluto Press. Porta, D. and Rucht, D. (2015) Power and democracy: concluding remarks. In: D. Porta and D. Rucht (eds.) Meeting Democracy Power and Deliberation in Global Justice Movements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 214–235. Dhaliwal, P. (2012) Public squares and resistance: the politics of space in the Indignados movement. Interface: a journal for and about social movements 4(1): 251–273. Dixon, C. (2014) Another Politics. Talking across Today’s Transformative Movements. Oakland: University of California Press.  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Kioupkiolis Elliott, B. (2011) Community and resistance in Heidegger, Nancy and Agamben. Philosophy & Social Criticism 37(3): 259–271. Esposito, R. (2010) Community. The Origin and Destiny of Community, Translated by T. Campbell. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Esposito, R. (2011) Immunitas. The Protection and Negation of Life, Translated by Z. Hanafi. Cambridge: Polity. Esposito, R. (2012) Third Person. Politics of Life and Philosophy of the Impersonal, Translated by Z. Hanafi. Cambridge: Polity. Esposito, R. (2013) Terms of the Political. Community, Immunity, Biopolitics, Translated by R.N. Welch. New York: Fordham University Press. Fynsk, C. (1991) Foreword. In: J.-L. Nancy, The Inoperative Community, Translated by P. Connor et al. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 7–37. Gilbert, J. (2014) Common Ground. Democracy and Collectivity in an Age of Individualism. London: Pluto Press. Giovanopoulos, C. and Mitropoulos, D. (eds.) (2011) Dglojqasi9a under construction. Athens: A/Synecheia Editions. Graeber, D. (2012) The Democracy Project A History, a Crisis, a Movement. London and New York: Penguin. Harcourt, B. (2011) Occupy Wall Street’s Political Disobedience. The New York Times, 13 October 2011. http://goo.gl/HVE0RM, accessed 2 December 2011. Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2009) Commonwealth. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2012) Declaration. New York: Melanie Jackson Agency. Holloway, J. (2005) Change the World without Taking Power. London: Pluto Press. Lacoue-Labarthe, P. and Nancy, J.-L. (1997) Retreating the Political. London and New York: Routledge. Laclau, E. (1990) New Reflections on the Revolution of Our Time. London and New York: Verso. Laclau, E. (1991) Community and Its Paradoxes Richard Rorty’s ‘Liberal Utopia’. In: Laclau, E. (eds.) Community at Loose Ends. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 83–98. Laclau, E. (1996) Emancipation(s). London and New York: Verso. Laclau, E. (2000) Structure, History and the Political. In: J. Butler, E. Laclau and S. Zizek (eds.) Contingency, Hegemony, Universality. London and New York: Verso, pp. 182–212. Laclau, E. (2005) On Populist Reason. London and New York: Verso. Laclau, E. (2014) The Rhetorical Foundations of Society. London and New York: Verso. Laclau, E. and Mouffe, C. (1985) Hegemony and Socialist Strategy. London and New York: Verso. Lorey, I. (2014) The 2011 occupy movements: Rancière and the crisis of democracy. Theory, Culture and Society 31(7/8): 43–65. Marchart, O. (2007) Post-Foundational Political. Thought Political Difference in Nancy, Lefort, Badiou and Laclau. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Marchart, O. (2012) Being With Against: Jean-Luc Nancy on Justice, Politics and the Democratic Horizon. In: B.C. Hutchens (ed.) Jean-Luc Nancy, Justice, Legality and World. London and New York: Continuum, pp. 172–184. Mouffe, C. (1991) Democratic Citizenship and the Political Community. In: Mouffe, C. (eds.) Community at Loose Ends. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 72–80. Mouffe, C. (2000) The Democratic Paradox. London and New York: Verso. Mouffe, C. (2005) On the Political. London and New York: Routledge. Mouffe, C. (2013) Agonistics. Thinking the World Politically. London and New York: Verso. Mouffe, C. and Errejón, Í. (2016) Podemos. In the Name of the People, Translated by S. C. Donnay. London: Lawrence and Wishart. Nancy, J.-L. (1991) The Inoperative Community, Translated by P. Connor et al. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press.  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Commoning the political, politicizing the common Nancy, J.-L. (1992) La Comparution/The Compearance: From the Existence of ‘Communism’ to the Community of ‘Existence’, Translated by T.B. Strong. Political theory 20 (3): 371–398. Nancy, J.L. (1993). The Experience of Freedom, Translated by B. McDonald. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Nancy, J.L. (1997) The Sense of the World, Translated by J. S. Librett. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Nancy, J.-L. (2000) Being Singular Plural, Translated by R. D. Richardson, A. E. O’Byrne. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Nancy, J.-L. (2009) Démocratie finie et infinie. In: G. Agamben, A. Badiou, D. Bensaı̈d, W. Brown, J.-L. Nancy, J. Rancière, K. Ross and S. Žižek, (eds.) Démocratie dans quel état?. Paris: La fabrique, pp. 77–94. Nancy, J-L. (2010a) The Truth of Democracy, Translated by P.-A. Brault, M. Naas. New York: Fordam University Press. Nancy, J.-L. (2010b) Communism, the Word. In: C. Douzinas, S. Žižek (eds.) The Idea of Communism. London and New York: Verso, pp. 145–153. Nez, H. (2012) Among Militants and Deliberative Laboratories: The Indignados. In: B. Tejerina and I. Perugorria (eds.) From Social to Political, New Forms of Mobilization and Democratization. Conference Proceedings. Bilbao: University of the Basque Country, pp. 123–139. Norris, A. (2012) Jean-Luc Nancy on the Political after Heidegger and Schmitt. In: P. Gratton and M.-E. Morin (eds.) Jean-Luc Nancy and Plural Thinking. Albany NY: State University of New York Press, pp. 143–158. Schwarzmantel, J. (2007) Community as communication: Jean-Luc Nancy and ‘being-in-common’. Political Studies 55(2): 459–476. Sitrin, M. and Azzellini, D. (2014) They Can’t Represent Us: Reinventing Democracy from Greece to Occupy. London and New York: Verso. Stavrides, S. (2012) Squares in Movement. South Atlantic Quarterly 111 (3): 585–596. Taylor, A., Gessen, K. et al. (eds.) (2011) Occupy! Scenes from Occupied America. London and New York, Verso. Tejerina, B. and Perugorria, I. (eds.) (2012) From Social to Political, New Forms of Mobilization and Democratization. Conference Proceedings. Bilbao: University of the Basque Country. Vyrgioti, M. (2015) Community beyond Identity: Rethinking Radical Politics with Nancy, Agamben, and Esposito. International Journal of Civic, Political, and Community Studies 13 (3): 1–9. Wagner, A. (2006) Jean-Luc Nancy: A Negative Politics? Philosophy & Social Criticism 32(1): 89–109. White, S.K. (2000) Sustaining Affirmation. The Strengths of Weak Ontology in Political Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.  2017 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory