Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

nLab regular category

Redirected from "regular categories".
Contents

Contents

Idea

A regular category is a finitely complete category which admits a good notion of image factorization. A primary raison d’être behind regular categories CC is to have a decently behaved calculus of relations in CC (see Rel).

Regular categories also provide a natural semantic environment to interpret a particularly well behaved positive fragment of first order logic having connectives \top, {\wedge}, \exists; in other words, their internal logic is regular logic.

Definition

Definition

(regular category)

A category CC is called regular if

  1. it is finitely complete;

  2. the kernel pair

    d× cd p 1 d p 2 f d f c \array{ d\times_c d &\stackrel{p_1}{\longrightarrow}& d \\ {{}^\mathllap{p_2}} \big\downarrow && \big\downarrow{{}^\mathrlap{f}} \\ d &\stackrel{f}{\longrightarrow}& c }

    of any morphism f:dcf: d \to c admits a coequalizer d× cddcoeq(p 1,p 2)d \times_c d \,\rightrightarrows\, d \to coeq(p_1,p_2);

  3. the pullback of a regular epimorphism along any morphism is again a regular epimorphism.

Remark

The kernel pair is always a congruence on dd in CC; informally, ker(f)=d× cd\ker(f) = d\times_c d is the subobject of d×dd \times d consisting of pairs of elements which have the same value under ff (sometimes called the “kernel” of a function in Set). The coequalizer above is supposed to be the “object of equivalence classes” of ker(f)\ker(f) as an internal equivalence relation.

Remark

A map which is the coequalizer of a parallel pair of morphisms is called a regular epimorphism. In fact, in any category satisfying the first two conditions in Def. , every regular epimorphism is the coequalizer of its kernel pair. (See for instance Lemma 5.6.6 in Practical Foundations.)

Remark

The last condition in Def. may equivalently be stated in the form “coequalizers of kernel pairs are stable under pullback”. However, it is not generally true in a regular category that the pullback of a general coequalizer diagram

edce \;\rightrightarrows\; d \to c

along a morphism ccc' \to c is again a coequalizer diagram (nor need a regular category have coequalizers of all parallel pairs).

In fact, a characterization equivalent to Def. is:

Proposition

A regular category is a finitely complete category with pullback-stable image factorizations in that

  1. every morphism factors as a regular epimorphism followed by a monomorphism

  2. these factorizations are preserved under pullback.

(eg. Gran 2020, Thm. 1.14, cf. also MO:a/252842)

See also familial regularity and exactness for a generalization of this approach to include coherent categories as well.

Examples

Examples of regular categories include the following:

Example

Set is a regular category.

Example

More generally, any topos is regular.

(Barr, Grillet & von Osdol 1971, p. 17, Borceux 1994III, Prop. 3.4.14, Johnstone 2002, p. 92)

Example

Even more generally, a locally cartesian closed category with coequalizers is regular, and so any quasitopos is regular.

Example

The category of models of any finitary algebraic theory (i.e., Lawvere theory) TT is regular. This applies in particular to the category Ab of abelian groups.

Example

The category Grp of all groups (including non-abelian groups) is regular.

(e.g. Borceux 1994 II, Ex. 2.4.3)

Example

Actually, any category that is monadic over Set is regular. For example, the category of frames FrmLoc opFrm \simeq Loc^{op} is regular, and the category of compact Hausdorff spaces is regular. A proof may be found here.

Example

Any abelian category is regular.

Example

If CC is regular, then so is the functor category C DC^D for any category DD.

Example

If CC is regular and TT is a Lawvere theory, then the category Mod(T,C)Mod(T, C) of TT-models in CC is also regular. See Theorem 5.11 in Barr’s Exact Categories.

Example

A slice of a regular category is also regular; cf. locally regular category. So is any co-slice. (Source: Borceux-Bourn, Appendix section 5.)

Example

If QQ is a quasitopos, then Q opQ^{op} is regular. Source: A2.6.3(i) in the Elephant.

Example

The opposite category Topop^{op} is regular. The key facts are that regular monomorphisms in TopTop are the same as subspace inclusions, and that the pushout of a subspace inclusion is a subspace inclusion as proven there.

Example

The category of (Hausdorff) Kelley spaces is regular (however, is not locally cartesian closed, nor is it exact) (Cagliari-Matovani-Vitale 95)

Example

(counter-examples) Examples of categories which are not regular include

The following example proves failure of regularity in all three cases:

Let AA be the poset {a,b}×(01)\{a, b\} \times (0 \to 1); let BB be the poset (012)(0 \to 1 \to 2), and let CC be the poset (02)(0 \to 2). There is a regular epi p:ABp: A \to B obtained by identifying (a,1)(a, 1) with (b,0)(b, 0), and there is the evident inclusion i:CBi: C \to B. The pullback of pp along ii is the inclusion {0,2}(02)\{0, 2\} \to (0 \to 2), which is certainly an epi but not a regular epi. Hence regular epis in PosPos are not stable under pullback.

Interpreting the posets as categories, the same example works for CatCat, and also for preorders. On the other hand, the category of finite preorders is equivalent to the category of finite topological spaces, so this example serves to show also that the category Top of all topological spaces is not regular.

However:

Example

(compactly generated Hausdorff spaces form a regular category)
The convenient full subcategories

kTopkHausTop kTop \xhookrightarrow{\;} kHaus \xhookrightarrow{\;} Top

of compactly generated Hausdorff spaces and of compactly generated weakly Hausdorff spaces are regular (Cagliari, Matovani & Vitale 1995, p. 3).

Example

(compactly generated GG-spaces form a regular category) For GGrp(kTop)G \,\in\, Grp(kTop) a compactly generated weak Hausdorff topological group, its category of internal actions, hence the category of CGWH-topological G-spaces GAct(kTop)G Act(kTop) is a regular category.

Proof

The forgetful functor GAct(kTop)kTopG Act(kTop) \xrightarrow{\;} kTop creates all limits and colimits (this Prop.). Since regularity is entirely a condition on limits and colimits (this Def.) the statement follows from Ex. .

Example

If TT is a Mal'cev theory (e.g., the theory of groups), then the category Top TTop^T of TT-models in Top is regular. This is because for TT Mal’cev, coequalizer maps in Top TTop^T are necessarily open surjections, and open surjections are stable under pullback.

Properties

Epimorphisms

Proposition

For a morphism ff in a regular category, the following conditions are all equivalent:

  1. ff is an effective epimorphism;

  2. ff is a regular epimorphism;

  3. ff is a strong epimorphism;

  4. ff is an extremal epimorphism.

Pullback and pasting law

In a regular category, the usual pasting law implication also applies along regular epimorphisms also in the reverse direction, :

Proposition

In a regular category, consider a commuting diagram of the form where

  1. the left square is a pullback;

  2. the bottom left morphism is an regular epimorphism.

Then right right square is a pullback iff the total rectangle is.

(e.g. Gran 2020, Lem. 1.15)

Factorization properties

Proposition

image factorization

In a regular category, every morphism f:xyf : x\to y can be factored – uniquely up to isomorphism – through its coimage coim(f)coim(f) as

f:xecoim(f)iy, f : x \stackrel{e}{\to} coim(f) \stackrel{i}{\to} y \,,

where ee is a regular epimorphism and ii a monomorphism.

Proof

Let e:xcoim(f)e : x \to coim(f) be the coequalizer of the kernel pair of ff. Since ff coequalizes its kernel pair, there is a unique map i:coim(f)yi: coim(f) \to y such that f=ief = i e. It may be shown from the regular category axioms that ii is monic and in fact represents the coimage of ff, i.e., the smallest subobject through which ff factors.

This is the mere definition of first isomorphism theorem.

A proof is spelled out on p. 30 of (vanOosten).

Proposition

The classes of regular epimorphism, monomorphisms in a regular category CC form a factorization system.

Embedding properties

Remark

If a regular category is small, it admits particularly nice embeddings into presheaf categories. See Barr embedding theorem for more.

Axiomatizability properties

Roughly speaking, regular categories tend to be relatively well-behaved when it comes to desribing them in formalized logics.

Regular functors over a small regular category

Proposition

(Makkai)
If a regular category \mathcal{R} is small, then the full subcategory of the functor category [,Set][\mathcal{R},\mathsf{Set}] consisting of the regular functors only is an elementary class w.r.t. the signature given by (the underlying graph) of \mathcal{R}.

Stronger conditions

Exactness

If a regular category additionally has the property that every congruence is a kernel pair (and hence has a quotient), then it is called a (Barr-) exact category. Note that while regularity implies the existence of some coequalizers, and exactness implies the existence of more, an exact category need not have all coequalizers (only coequalizers of congruences), whereas a regular category can be cocomplete without being exact.

Regularity and exactness can also be phrased in the language of Galois connections, as a special case of the notion of generalized kernels.

Higher arity

As exactness properties go, the ones possessed by general regular categories are fairly moderate; the main condition is of course stability of regular epis under pullback. A natural generalization is to include (finite or infinite) unions of subobjects, or equivalently images of (finite or infinite) families as well as of single morphisms. This leads to the notion of coherent category.

Just as regularity implies the existence of certain coequalizers, coherence implies the existence of certain coproducts and pushouts, but not all. A lextensive category has all (finite or infinite) coproducts that are disjoint and stable under pullback. It is easy to see that a lextensive regular category must actually be coherent.

The regular topology

Any regular category CC admits a subcanonical Grothendieck topology whose covering families are generated by single regular epimorphisms: the regular coverage. If CC is exact or has pullback-stable reflexive coequalizers, then its codomain fibration is a stack for this topology (the necessary and sufficient condition is that any pullback of a kernel pair is again a kernel pair).

Making categories regular

Any category CC with finite limits has a reg/lex completion C reg/lexC_{reg/lex} with the following properties:

  • There is a full and faithful functor CC reg/lexC\hookrightarrow C_{reg/lex}
  • Each object of CC becomes projective in C reg/lexC_{reg/lex}
  • Each left-exact functor CDC\to D, where DD is regular, extends to an essentially unique regular functor C reg/lexDC_{reg/lex}\to D.

In particular, the reg/lex completion is a left adjoint to the forgetful functor from regular categories to lex categories (categories with finite limits). The reg/lex completion can be obtained by “formally adding images” for all morphisms in CC, or by “closing up” CC under images in its presheaf category [C op,Set][C^{op},Set]; see regular and exact completions. In general, even if CC is regular, C reg/lexC_{reg/lex} is larger than CC (that is, it is a free cocompletion rather than merely a completion), although if CC satisfies the axiom of choice (in the sense that all regular epimorphisms are split), then CC reg/lexC\simeq C_{reg/lex}.

Regular categories of the form C reg/lexC_{reg/lex} for a lex category CC can be characterized as those regular categories in which every object admits both a regular epi from a projective object and a monomorphism into a projective object, and the projective objects are closed under finite limits. In this case CC can be recovered as the subcategory of projective objects. In fact, the construction of C reg/lexC_{reg/lex} can be extended to categories having only weak finite limits, and the regular categories of the form C reg/lexC_{reg/lex} for a “weakly lex” category CC are those satisfying the first two conditions but not the third.

When the reg/lex completion is followed by the ex/reg completion which completes a regular category into an exact one, the result is unsurprisingly the ex/lex completion. See regular and exact completions for more about all of these operations.

categoryfunctorinternal logictheoryhyperdoctrinesubobject posetcoverageclassifying topos
finitely complete categorycartesian functorcartesian logicessentially algebraic theory
lextensive categorydisjunctive logic
regular categoryregular functorregular logicregular theoryregular hyperdoctrineinfimum-semilatticeregular coverageregular topos
coherent categorycoherent functorcoherent logiccoherent theorycoherent hyperdoctrinedistributive latticecoherent coveragecoherent topos
geometric categorygeometric functorgeometric logicgeometric theorygeometric hyperdoctrineframegeometric coverageGrothendieck topos
Heyting categoryHeyting functorintuitionistic first-order logicintuitionistic first-order theoryfirst-order hyperdoctrineHeyting algebra
De Morgan Heyting categoryintuitionistic first-order logic with weak excluded middleDe Morgan Heyting algebra
Boolean categoryclassical first-order logicclassical first-order theoryBoolean hyperdoctrineBoolean algebra
star-autonomous categorymultiplicative classical linear logic
symmetric monoidal closed categorymultiplicative intuitionistic linear logic
cartesian monoidal categoryfragment {&,}\{\&, \top\} of linear logic
cocartesian monoidal categoryfragment {,0}\{\oplus, 0\} of linear logic
cartesian closed categorysimply typed lambda calculus

References

The notion of regular categories was introduced in:

Historical context:

Introduction:

Textbook accounts:

The following set of course notes has a section on regular categories

An application of the regularity condition1 is found in:

Generalization of the notion of regular categories to enriched category theory:

Regularity of (Hausdorff) compactly generated topological spaces:


  1. Knop’s condition for regularity is slightly different from that presented here; he works with categories that when augmented by an absolutely initial object are regular in the terminology here. In the paper, Knop generalizes a construction of Deligne by showing how to construct a symmetric pseudo-abelian tensor category out of a regular category through the calculus of relations.

Last revised on November 17, 2023 at 19:53:33. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.