Abstract
One of the most dominant approaches to semantics for relevant (and many paraconsistent) logics is the Routley–Meyer semantics involving a ternary relation on points. To some (many?), this ternary relation has seemed like a technical trick devoid of an intuitively appealing philosophical story that connects it up with conditionality in general. In this paper, we respond to this worry by providing three different philosophical accounts of the ternary relation that correspond to three conceptions of conditionality. We close by briefly discussing a general conception of conditionality that may unify the three given conceptions.
Similar content being viewed by others
References
Anderson, A. R., & Belnap, N. D. (1975). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity (Vol. 1). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Barwise, J. (1993). Constraints, channels, and the flow of information. In S. Peters, & D. Israel (Eds.), Situation theory and its applications. Palo Alto: CSLI Publications (CSLI Lecture Notes).
Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Beall, J. (2009). Spandrels of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bimbó, K., & Dunn, J. M. (2008). Generalized Galois logics. Relational semantics of nonclassical logical calculi. Palo Alto: CSLI Publications (CSLI Lecture Notes).
Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2001). Modal logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dunn, J. M. (1987). Incompleteness of the binary semantics for R. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, Polish Academy of Sciences, 16, 107–110.
Dunn, J. M. (1990). Gaggle theory: An abstraction of galois connections and residuation with applications to negations and various logical operators. In Logics in AI, Proceedings of E uropean workshop JELIA 1990 (Lecture Notes in Computer Science #478) (pp. 31–51). Berlin: Springer. LNCS.
Dunn, J. M. (1993). Star and perp: Two treatments of negation. In J. Toberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives: Language and logic (Vol. 7, pp. 331–357).
Dunn, J. M. (2001). Representation of relation algebras using Routley–Meyer frames. In C. A. Anderson, & Zeleny, M. (Eds.), Logic, meaning and computation: Essays in memory of Alonzo Church (pp. 77–108). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Dunn, J. M. (2001). Ternary relational semantics and beyond. Logical Studies, 7, 1–20.
Dunn, J. M., & Meyer, R. K. (1997). Combinators and structurally free logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 5, 505–537.
Fine, K. (1974). Models for entailment. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3, 347–372.
Krabbe, E. C. W. (1978). Note on a completeness theorem in the theory of counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 7(1), 91–93.
Lewis, C. I., & Langford, C. H. (1959). Symbolic logic. Mineola: Dover.
Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Lycan, W. G. (2001). Real conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mares, E. (2004). Relevant logic: A philosophical interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Meyer, R. K., & Routley, R. (1974). Classical relevant logics II. Studia Logica, 33(2), 183–194 (1974)
Meyer, R. K., & Slaney, J. (1997). Logic for two: The semantics of distributive substructural logics. In Proceedeings of the first international joint conference on qualitative and quantitative practical reasoning (pp. 554–567).
Nute, D. (1975). Counterfactuals and the similarity of worlds. Journal of Philosophy, 72(21), 773–778.
Peirce, C. S. (1992). Reasoning and the logic of things. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Edited by Kenneth Laine Ketner, with an introduction by Kenneth Laine Ketner and Hilary Putnam.
Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic: From if to is. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Priest, G. (2009). Is the ternary R depraved? Presented at the July 2009 meeting of the Australasian Association for Logic, Melbourne.
Restall, G. (1995). Information flow and relevant logics. In J. Seligman, & D. Westerståhl (Eds.), Logic, language, and computation: The 1994 Moraga proceedings (pp. 463–477). Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Restall, G. (1999). Negation in relevant logics: How I stopped worrying and learned to love the Routley star. In D. Gabbay, & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (pp. 53–76). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Restall, G. (2000). An introduction to substructural logics. London: Routledge.
Routley, R., & Meyer, R. K. (1972). Semantics of entailment—II. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, 53–73.
Routley, R., & Meyer, R. K. (1972). Semantics of entailment—III. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, 192–208.
Routley, R., & Meyer, R. K. (1973). Semantics of entailment. In H. Leblanc (Ed.), Truth, syntax and modality (pp. 194–243). Amsterdam: North Holland. Proceedings of the Temple University conference on alternative semantics.
Routley, R., & Meyer, R. K. (1976). Every sentential logic has a two-valued world semantics. Logique et Analyse, 19, 345–365.
Routley, R., Meyer, R. K., Plumwood, V., & Brady, R. T. (1982). Relevant logics and their rivals 1. Atascadero: Ridgeview.
Slaney, J. (1990). A general logic. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68, 74–88.
Thomason, R. (1970). A Fitch-style formulation of conditional logic. Logique et Analyse, 52, 397–412.
Urquhart, A. (1972). Semantics for relevant logics. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 37(1), 159–169.
van Benthem, J. (1984). Review of ‘On when a semantics is not a semantics’ by B. J. Copeland. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 49(3), 994–995.
van Benthem, J. (1991). Language in action. Categories, lambdas and dynamic logic. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
van Fraassen, B. C. (1975). Theories and counterfactuals. In H.-N. Castañeda (Ed.), Action, knowledge, and reality: Studies in honor of Wilfrid S ellars (pp. 237–263). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
This paper emerged from some working sessions at the University of Melbourne in 2009. Beall, Brady, Hazen, Priest, Restall, Ripley, and Slaney were involved on the ground. The work of Dunn and Mares kept coming up during the sessions, and the paper greatly benefited from their joining the effort after the event. Looming even larger in the initial discussions were two others: despite their deaths, much of the early work of Sylvan and Meyer was heavily represented. While we can’t speak for the current views of Bob (Meyer) or Richard (Sylvan), we wanted to honor them for their starting this ternary-relation idea in the first place. Hence, we include them as authors. While not all of us (authors) agree on all ideas herein, we do agree with the main thrust of this paper: namely, that, despite first appearances, the ternary-relation approach to conditionality is very much philosophically plausible as capturing an important aspect of conditionality.
R. K. Meyer and R. Sylvan (formerly Routley), both deceased.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Beall, J., Brady, R., Dunn, J.M. et al. On the Ternary Relation and Conditionality. J Philos Logic 41, 595–612 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-011-9191-5
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-011-9191-5