Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Skip to main content
Log in

Skepticism, virtue and transmission in the theory of knowledge: an anti-reductionist and anti-individualist account

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This contribution to the topical collection presents an overview of my previous work in epistemology. Specifically, I review arguments for the claim that important skeptical arguments in the history of philosophy motivate externalism in epistemology. In effect, only externalist epistemologies can be anti-skeptical epistemologies. I also review motivations for adopting a virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Such an account, I argue, has considerable explanatory power regarding the nature, value and scope of knowledge. In addition, a virtue-theoretic account is tailor made for externalism. In effect, it shows how externalist epistemologies can also be normative epistemologies. Finally, I review arguments in favor of a general framework for understanding the epistemology of testimony, and, in particular, the transmission of knowledge. The framework motivates anti-reductionism in the epistemology of testimony, as well as the common anti-reductionist theme that trust can be epistemically significant, as opposed to merely practically significant. The framework, I argue, also weds nicely to a virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity, and in doing so answers an important objection to virtue epistemology—that the view is overly individualistic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bertrand Russel, Problems of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997): pp. 25–26.

  2. John Greco, Putting Skeptics in Their Place: The Nature of Skeptical Arguments and Their Role in Philosophical Inquiry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).

  3. For the present purposes we can put issues about Hume interpretation aside. The point is to construct an interesting skeptical argument rather than to capture Hume’s intentions.

  4. For example, see Barry Stroud, Hume (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977, p. 56), n11; and D. C. Stove, Probability and Hume's Deductive Scepticism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973, p. 51).

  5. Notice that this is true even on Berkeley’s radical idealism, where objects in “external” reality are constituted by stable and coherent bundles of ideas. That is, it is only a contingent fact, if it is a fact at all, that present appearances are a reliable indication of stable and coherent bundles.

  6. John Greco, Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).

  7. Adapted from Chisholm Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edition (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1977, p. 105).

  8. In what follows I refer to Jeter circa 1999.

  9. Jennifer Lackey, “Why We Don't Deserve Credit for Everything We Know,” Synthese 158, 3 (2007): 345–361; and “Knowledge and Credit,” Philosophical Studies 142, 1 (2009, pp. 27–42).

  10. John Greco, The Transmission of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020).

  11. Edward Craig, Knowledge and the State of Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).

  12. Elizabeth Fricker, “Second-hand knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73, 3 (2006): 592–618: p. 596. Italics original.

  13. Moran and Hinchman also defend this idea. See Edward Hinchman, “Telling as Inviting to Trust,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70:3 (2005, pp. 562–587); Richard Moran, “Getting Told and Being Believed,” in Jennifer Lackey and Ernest Sosa, eds., The Epistemology of Testimony (Oxford: Oxford University Press, (2006, pp. 272–306); and Moran, The Exchange of Words: Speech, Testimony, and Intersubjectivity (New York: Oxford University Press, 2018).

  14. For similar reasons, the new view also avoids a dilemma put forward by Duncan Pritchard. We saw that, according to Lackey, traditional virtue epistemology cannot correctly analyze both (a) testimonial knowledge and (b) standard Gettier cases, her idea being that the two kinds of case pull in different directions, making it impossible for virtue epistemology to accommodate both. In similar fashion, Pritchard argues that traditional virtue epistemology cannot accommodate both (a) testimonial knowledge and (b) barn facade-style cases involving environmental luck; again, the idea being that the two kinds of case pull the view in opposing theoretical directions. [For example, see Duncan Pritchard, “Knowledge and Understanding,” in Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, and Duncan Pritchard, The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2010)]. The new view avoids Pritchard’s dilemma in essentially the same way that it avoids Lackey’s—by giving up the idea that all testimonial knowledge is attributable to the intellectual virtues of the hearer.

References

  • Chisholm, R. (1977). Theory of knowledge (2nd ed.). Prentice-Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (2006). Second-hand knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73(3), 592–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2000). Putting skeptics in their place: The nature of skeptical arguments and their role in philosophical inquiry. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2020). The transmission of knowledge. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hinchman, E. (2005). Telling as inviting to trust. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(3), 562–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2007). Why we don’t deserve credit for everything we know. Synthese, 158(3), 345–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2009). Knowledge and credit. Philosophical Studies, 142(1), 27–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2006). Getting told and being believed. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2018). The exchange of words: Speech, testimony, and intersubjectivity. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2010). Knowledge and understanding. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge three investigations. Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Russel, B. (1997). Problems of philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stove, D. C. (1973). Probability and Hume’s deductive scepticism. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (1977). Hume. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

It is a great honor to have a topical collection in Synthese dedicated to my work in epistemology. My heartfelt thanks go to Nuno Venturinha for organizing and editing the volume, and to each of the contributors for their participation.

Funding

N/A.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

N/A.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Greco.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Ethical approval

N/A.

Consent for publication

Yes.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Greco, J. Skepticism, virtue and transmission in the theory of knowledge: an anti-reductionist and anti-individualist account. Synthese 200, 421 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03893-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03893-7

Keywords

Navigation