Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Skip to main content

Intelligent Design and the Nature of Science: Philosophical and Pedagogical Points

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 1))

Abstract

This chapter offers a critique of intelligent design arguments against evolution and a philosophical discussion of the nature of science, drawing several lessons for the teaching of evolution and for science education in general. I discuss why Behe’s irreducible complexity argument fails, and why his portrayal of organismal systems as machines is detrimental to biology education and any understanding of how organismal evolution is possible. The idea that the evolution of complex organismal features is too unlikely to have occurred by random mutation and selection (as recently promoted by Dembski) is very widespread, but it is easy to show students why such small probability arguments are fallacious. While intelligent design proponents have claimed that the exclusion of supernatural causes mandated by scientific methods is dogmatically presupposed by science, scientists have an empirical justification for using such methods. This justification is instructive for my discussion of how to demarcate science from pseudoscience. I argue that there is no universal account of the nature of science, but that the criteria used to judge an intellectual approach vary across historical periods and have to be specific to the scientific domain. Moreover, intellectual approaches have to be construed as practices based on institutional factors and values, and to be evaluated in terms of the activities of their practitioners. Science educators should not just teach scientific facts, but present science as a practice and make students reflect on the nature of science, as this gives them a better appreciation of the ways in which intelligent design falls short of actual science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    While traditional classroom instruction thoroughly covers different aspects of microevolution, using non-human animals as examples, it is essential to present more examples about macroevolutionary transformations, including the evolution of humans. This stems from the fact that young children can more easily conceive of microevolutionary changes than of macroevolutionary changes (Samarapungavan 2011) and a person can use multiple epistemologies, leaving room for the possibility that while using a scientific epistemology for microevolution, students may use a non-scientific epistemology when thinking about human origins (Evans et al. 2011).

  2. 2.

    ID proponents have only leveled arguments against evolutionary theory, and there is no intelligent design theory that makes predictions and explains phenomena. For this reason, ‘ID proponent’ has to henceforth refer to someone endorsing the ‘intelligent design’ label, and more concretely someone who is part of the intelligent design movement (Sect. 5).

  3. 3.

    One difference is that while Paley argued against a natural origin of organisms by mere chance, Behe argues (and has to argue) against an evolutionary origin by natural selection.

  4. 4.

    For a historical discussion of the concept of evolvability and its relation to the concept of developmental constraint see Brigandt (in press-b), and for a connection to the phenomenon of homology see Brigandt (2007).

  5. 5.

    Dawkins’s (1989) presentation also construes organisms as largely passive machines (controlled by genes), while portraying genes as active agents that have desires (selfish aims) and carry out actions (building organisms). However, while it may make the material more attractive, the anthropomorphizing of nature in classrooms can have negative effects on students’ epistemological development (Evans et al. 2011).

  6. 6.

    Section 2.2 pointed out that exploratory behavior and other aspects of developmental processes permit several coordinated and instantaneous phenotypic changes to result from a simple genetic change.

  7. 7.

    For instance, Dembski does not infer design simply from an event being extremely improbable, but from it being improbable and specified (exhibiting a pattern), although he has not offered a consistent account of specificity.

  8. 8.

    The discussion on evolvability in Sect. 2.2 mentioned further relevant aspects of the evolutionary process.

  9. 9.

    A similar conflation of two distinct conditional probabilities can occur not only in small probability arguments against evolution, but also in more direct ‘arguments’ for intelligent design. Inferring that an irreducibly complex or machine-like object is likely to have been designed on the grounds that (human) designers frequently produce irreducibly complex and machine-like objects is a fallacy. For while the premise is that P(machine-like object|designed) is high, the conclusion states that P(designed|machine-like object) is high.

  10. 10.

    If one does not want to toss a coin 500 times, using two decks of cards likewise yields an outcome whose probability is smaller than the universal probability bound.

  11. 11.

    In addition to persons being poor at reasoning with probability and detecting patterns where there are none, Elsberry and Shallit (2011) point to cognitive science studies according to which humans have agency attribution systems, which may be biased toward overdetection of agency.

  12. 12.

    If ID is made more concrete so that predictions result, there is still the question of whether it fits the known evidence to a higher degree than evolutionary theory. Young Earth creationism of course makes concrete, testable claims (e.g., about the age of the Earth and the occurrence of a worldwide flood), which have been shown to be false.

  13. 13.

    In the case of the use of the telescope for astronomical observations, even though this method was controversial upon its introduction, some reasons for its increased acceptance were that repeated observations gave consistent orbits and that telescope-based predictions on the future positions of planetary bodies were borne out. Moreover, it was demonstrated that the telescope reliably represented distant objects on Earth, whose properties could be verified by naked eye observation. Using lamps, Galileo showed that, unlike telescopic observations, naked eye observations overestimated the size of distant bright lights against a dark background, so that he was in a position to explain the inconsistency of the apparent size of the planets and stars viewed by naked eye vs. telescope. Thus, a previously accepted scientific method (naked eye observation) can be used to show the reliability and even superiority of a new method (telescopic observation), yielding an empirical justification for a change in method.

  14. 14.

    Another drawback is that the notion of falsifiability stems from Karl Popper’s (1959) falsificationism. This general doctrine of confirmation assumes that while it is possible to conclusively disconfirm (falsify) a theory, there is no incremental confirmation of theories by evidence. Falsificationism maintains that it is not rationally possible to inductively increase one’s degree of belief in a theory as evidence accumulates. In fact, one cannot have any degree of confidence in its truth—one may only believe that a particular theory has shown to be false. However, even if a theory is incompatible with some observations, scientists may very well continue using the theory if it is supported by other lines of evidence and if there is no better alternative available, as opposed to rejecting it as ‘falsified’. More importantly, the only way to rationally justify one’s actions is with reference to factual beliefs for which one has some support, so there has to be some degree of positive belief in theoretical claims. Since scientists do have rational support for their (limited) endorsement of a theory (e.g., mechanics) and since scientists and policy makers use this theory for further action (e.g., building space rockets), philosophers of science have generally rejected falsificationism (Godfrey-Smith 2003).

  15. 15.

    Here is an analogy: While biological attempts to define ‘life’ exist, such definitions are fraught with difficulties (see Cleland and Zerella, this volume). This is not a problem, as biology offers many insights into the features of living organisms independently of a definition of life. The biology of viruses offers empirical understanding even if it is not settled whether or not a virus is a living entity. Biologists pursue various aims and address concrete questions about particular organism groups, but defining life is not an aim of biology. In the same vein, philosophy can address various normative issues about scientific approaches without aiming at a definition of ‘science’.

  16. 16.

    Footnote 15 argued that just like developing a definition of life is not a genuine aim of biology, so philosophy of science need not aim at a definition of science. The biology–philosophy analogy can be extended further. Similar to biology making progress by understanding various life processes, philosophers should not ask what science is, but analyze how science works and judge the credentials of intellectual traditions based on their epistemic and social practices.

  17. 17.

    Arguing that the question is not whether theories are scientific, but whether epistemic practices are so, Chinn and Buckland (2011) compare the practices of evolutionary biologists, young Earth creationists, intelligent design proponents, and the nineteenth century scientist-creationists of Darwin’s era. The latter’s practice turns out to be more scientific than the practice of contemporary intelligent design proponents.

  18. 18.

    See http://www.arn.org/odesign/odesign.htm (1996–2000) and http://www.iscid.org/pcid.php (2002–2005). The latter was abandoned just after Kitzmiller v. Dover ruled the teaching of intelligent design to be unconstitutional. In late 2009, largely the same group of editors set up a new journal http://bio-complexity.org, though in the last 3 years only 11 articles or reviews (all but one research article co-authored by the editors) have appeared.

  19. 19.

    From an internal Discovery Institute memo leaked to the public: “Governing Goals: To defeat scientific materialism and its destructive moral, cultural and political legacies. To replace materialistic explanations with the theistic understanding that nature and human beings are created by God. […] Twenty Year Goals: […] To see design theory permeate our religious, cultural, moral and political life.” (http://www.antievolution.org/features/wedge.pdf)

  20. 20.

    http://www.dissentfromdarwin.org

  21. 21.

    Compare the statements made in the ‘documentary’ Expelled: No Intelligence Allowed with http://www.expelledexposed.com

  22. 22.

    I have argued in Sect. 4.2 that whereas a framing of philosophy of science in terms of a demarcation of science from pseudoscience erroneously suggests that approaches can be evaluated on a one-dimensional scale from scientific to unscientific, theoretical approaches differ in many respects. Considerations about ethical, social, and political consequences are yet other philosophical considerations that can be brought to bear in the assessment of epistemic traditions.

References

  • Alberts, Bruce. 1998. The cell as a collection of protein machines: Preparing the next generation of molecular biologists. Cell 92: 291–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 1995. Knowledge, human interests, and objectivity in feminist epistemology. Philosophical Topics 23: 27–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, William, and Adele Abrahamsen. 2005. Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36: 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beckwith, Francis J. 2003a. Law, Darwinism, and public education: The establishment clause and the challenge of intelligent design. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckwith, Francis J. 2003b. Science and religion twenty years after McLean v. Arkansas: Evolution, public education, and the new challenge of intelligent design. Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 26: 455–499.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behe, Michael J. 1996. Darwin’s black box: The biochemical challenge to evolution. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behe, Michael J. 2007. The edge of evolution: The search for the limits of Darwinism. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlinski, David. 2008. The Devil’s delusion: Atheism and its scientific pretensions. New York: Crown Forum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottaro, Andrea, Matt A. Inlay, and Nicholas J. Matzke. 2006. Immunology in the spotlight at the Dover ‘Intelligent Design’ trial. Nature Immunology 7: 433–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. 2007. Typology now: Homology and developmental constraints explain evolvability. Biology and Philosophy 22: 709–725.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. 2010. Beyond reduction and pluralism: Toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis 73: 295–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. 2011. Critical notice of Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science by Elliott Sober, Cambridge University Press, 2008. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41:159–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. 2012. The dynamics of scientific concepts: The relevance of epistemic aims and values. In Scientific concepts and investigative practice, ed. Uljana Feest and Friedrich Steinle. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. 2013. Explanation in biology: Reduction, pluralism, and explanatory aims. Science & Education 22: 69–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. in press-a. Evolutionary developmental biology and the limits of philosophical accounts of mechanistic explanation. In Explanation in biology: An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences, eds. Pierre-Alain Braillard and Christophe Malaterre. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. in press-b. From developmental constraint to evolvability: How concepts figure in explanation and disciplinary identity. In Conceptual change in biology: Scientific and philosophical perspectives on evolution and development, ed. Alan C. Love. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo, and Alan C. Love. 2008. Reductionism in biology. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reduction-biology.

  • Chinn, Clark A., and Luke A. Buckland. 2011. Differences in epistemic practices among scientists, young earth creationists, intelligent design creationists, and the scientist-creationists of Darwin’s era. In Epistemology and science education: Understanding the evolution vs. intelligent design controversy, ed. Roger S. Taylor and Michel Ferrari, 38–76. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, Richard. 1989. The selfish gene, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, William A. 1998a. The design inference: Eliminating chance through small probabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, William A. 1998b. Introduction: Mere creation. In Mere creation: Science, faith & intelligent design, ed. William A. Dembski, 13–30. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, William A. 2002a. Naturalism’s argument from invincible ignorance: A response to Howard Van Till. http://www.designinference.com/documents/2002.09.Van_Till_Response.htm. Accessed 1 Apr 2011.

  • Dembski, William A. 2002b. No free lunch: Why specified complexity cannot be purchased without intelligence. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, Heather. 2009. Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downes, Stephen M. 1993. Socializing naturalized philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science 60: 452–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, Richard A., and Richard E. Grandy. 2011. Demarcation in science education: Toward an enhanced view of scientific method. In Epistemology and science education: Understanding the evolution vs. intelligent design controversy, ed. Roger S. Taylor and Michel Ferrari, 3–19. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, Gerald M., and Joseph A. Gally. 2001. Degeneracy and complexity in biological systems. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 98: 13763–13768.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elsberry, Wesley, and Jeffrey Shallit. 2011. Information theory, evolutionary computation, and Dembski’s ‘complex specified information’. Synthese 178: 237–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Margaret E., Cristine H. Legare, and Karl S. Rosengren. 2011. Engaging multiple epistemologies: Implications for science education. In Epistemology and science education: Understanding the evolution vs. intelligent design controversy, ed. Roger S. Taylor and Michel Ferrari, 111–139. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, Carla, and Kathryn Plaisance. 2010. Socially relevant philosophy of science: An introduction. Synthese 177: 301–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsentein, Joe. 2007. Has natural selection been refuted? The arguments of William Dembski. Reports of the National Center for Science Education 27(3–4): 20–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, Branden, Christopher Stephens, and Elliott Sober. 1999. Review: How not to detect design. Philosophy of Science 66: 472–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, Barbara. 2010. It’s Déjà vu all over again: The intelligent design movement’s recycling of creationist strategies. Evolution: Education and Outreach 3: 170–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, Barbara. 2011. The non-epistemology of intelligent design: Its implications for public policy. Synthese 178: 331–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, Barbara, and Paul R. Gross. 2004. Creationism’s Trojan horse: The wedge of intelligent design. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gauger, Ann K., and Douglas D. Axe. 2011. The evolutionary accessibility of new enzyme functions: A case study from the biotin pathway. BIO-Complexity 2011: 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2003. Theory and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goering, Sara. 1994. Women and underserved populations: Access to clinical trials. In “It Just Ain’t Fair”: The ethics of health care for African Americans, ed. Annette Dula and Sara Goering, 182–192. Westport: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Häggström, Olle. 2007. Intelligent design and the NFL theorems. Biology and Philosophy 22: 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendrikse, Jesse L., Trish E. Parsons, and Benedikt Hallgrímsson. 2007. Evolvability as the proper focus of evolutionary developmental biology. Evolution and Development 9: 393–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, Paul. 2008. Systematicity: The nature of science. Philosophia 36: 167–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Phillip E. 1991. Darwin on trial. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Phillip E., and Denis O. Lamoureux (eds.). 1999. Darwinism defeated? The Johnson-Lamoureux debate on biological origins. Vancouver: Regent College Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Alison M., Candace M. Tingen, and Teresa K. Woodruff. 2010. Sex bias in trials and treatment must end. Nature 465: 688–689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, Marc W., and John C. Gerhart. 1998. Evolvability. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 95: 8420–8427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, Marc W., and John C. Gerhart. 2005. The plausibility of life: Resolving Darwin’s dilemma. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, Marc W., John C. Gerhart, and Tim Mitchison. 2000. Molecular ‘vitalism’. Cell 100: 79–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 2001. Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, Janet A. 2010. Philosophy of science after feminism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lamoureux, Denis O. 2008. Evolutionary creation: A Christian approach to evolution. Eugene: Wipf & Stock Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, Larry. 1983. The demise of the demarcation problem. In Physics, philosophy, and psychoanalysis: Essays in honor of Adolf Grünbaum, ed. Robert S. Cohen and Larry Laudan, 111–127. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen E. 2002. The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, Alan C. 2008. Explaining evolutionary innovation and novelty: Criteria of adequacy and multidisciplinary prerequisites. Philosophy of Science 75: 874–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, Alan C. 2013. Interdisciplinary lessons for the teaching of biology from the practice of evo-devo. Science & Education 22: 255–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Stephen C. 2009. Signature in the cell: DNA and the evidence for intelligent design. New York: HarperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaels, David. 2008. Doubt is their product: How industry’s assault on science threatens your health. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Sandra D. 2009. Unsimple truths: Science, complexity, and policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Numbers, Ronald L. 2009. That creationism is a uniquely American phenomenon. In Galileo goes to jail and other myths about science and religion, ed. Ronald L. Numbers, 215–223. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olofsson, Peter. 2008. Intelligent design and mathematical statistics: A troubled alliance. Biology and Philosophy 23: 545–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, Naomi, and Erik M. Conway. 2010. Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paley, William. 1802. Natural theology, or evidences of the existence and attributes of the deity, collected from the appearances of nature. London: R. Faulder.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pallen, Mark J., and Nicholas J. Matzke. 2006. From The Origin of Species to the origin of bacterial flagella. Nature Reviews Microbiology 4: 784–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennock, Robert T. 2011. Can’t philosophers tell the difference between science and religion? Demarcation revisited. Synthese 178: 177–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perakh, Mark. 2004. Unintelligent design. Amherst: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, Massimo, and Maarten Boudry. 2011. Why machine-information metaphors are bad for science and science education. Science & Education 20: 453–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, Jason. 2004. Embryology, epigenesis, and evolution: Taking development seriously. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, Michael (ed.). 1988. But is it science? The philosophical question in the creation/evolution controversy. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samarapungavan, Ala. 2011. Ontological assumptions about species and their influence on students’ understanding of evolutionary biology. In Epistemology and science education: Understanding the evolution vs. intelligent design controversy, ed. Roger S. Taylor and Michel Ferrari, 77–94. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, Sahotra. 2007. Doubting Darwin? Creationist designs on evolution. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, Sahotra. 2011. The science question in intelligent design. Synthese 178: 291–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, Eugenie C. 2004. Evolution vs. creationism: An introduction. Berkley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sewell, Granville. 2000. A mathematician’s view of evolution. The Mathematical Intelligencer 22: 5–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sewell, Granville. 2001. Can anything happen in an open system? The Mathematical Intelligencer 23: 8–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, Niall. 2004. God, the devil, and Darwin: A critique of intelligent design theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, Niall, and Karl H. Joplin. 1999. Redundant complexity: A critical analysis of intelligent design in biochemistry. Philosophy of Science 66: 268–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinatra, Gale M., and Louis Nadelson. 2011. Science and religion: Ontologically different epistemologies? In Epistemology and science education: Understanding the evolution vs. intelligent design controversy, ed. Roger S. Taylor and Michel Ferrari, 173–193. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, Elliott. 1999. Testability. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 73: 47–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, Elliott. 2007. What is wrong with intelligent design? The Quarterly Review of Biology 82: 3–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, Elliott. 2008. Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Miriam. 2001. Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, Karola. 2006. Molecular epigenesis: Distributed specificity as a break in the central dogma. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 28: 527–544.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, Paul. 2011. Evolution, creation, and the philosophy of science. In Epistemology and science education: Understanding the evolution vs. intelligent design controversy, ed. Roger S. Taylor and Michel Ferrari, 20–37. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, Nancy. 2010. Leading with ethics, aiming for policy: New opportunities for philosophy of science. Synthese 177: 471–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, Andreas. 2005. Robustness and evolvability in living systems. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells, Johnathan. 2011. The myth of junk DNA. Seattle: Discovery Institute Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, Carolyn. 2002. Black battered women: New directions for research and black feminist theory. In Charting a new course for feminist psychology, ed. Lynn Collins, Michelle Dunlap, and Joan Chrisler, 216–237. Westport: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Matt, and Taner Edis (eds.). 2004. Why intelligent design fails: A scientific critique of the new creationism. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to Kostas Kampourakis, Alessandro Minelli, and an anonymous referee for comments on earlier versions of this essay. I thank Emma Kennedy for her thorough copyediting of the manuscript. This work was funded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (Standard Research Grant 410-2008-0400).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ingo Brigandt .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brigandt, I. (2013). Intelligent Design and the Nature of Science: Philosophical and Pedagogical Points. In: Kampourakis, K. (eds) The Philosophy of Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6537-5_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics