Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

skip to main content
article

The Explanatory Role of Computation in Cognitive Science

Published: 01 November 2012 Publication History

Abstract

Which notion of computation (if any) is essential for explaining cognition? Five answers to this question are discussed in the paper. (1) The classicist answer: symbolic (digital) computation is required for explaining cognition; (2) The broad digital computationalist answer: digital computation broadly construed is required for explaining cognition; (3) The connectionist answer: sub-symbolic computation is required for explaining cognition; (4) The computational neuroscientist answer: neural computation (that, strictly, is neither digital nor analogue) is required for explaining cognition; (5) The extreme dynamicist answer: computation is not required for explaining cognition. The first four answers are only accurate to a first approximation. But the "devil" is in the details. The last answer cashes in on the parenthetical "if any" in the question above. The classicist argues that cognition is symbolic computation. But digital computationalism need not be equated with classicism. Indeed, computationalism can, in principle, range from digital (and analogue) computationalism through (the weaker thesis of) generic computationalism to (the even weaker thesis of) digital (or analogue) pancomputationalism. Connectionism, which has traditionally been criticised by classicists for being non-computational, can be plausibly construed as being either analogue or digital computationalism (depending on the type of connectionist networks used). Computational neuroscience invokes the notion of neural computation that may (possibly) be interpreted as a sui generis type of computation. The extreme dynamicist argues that the time has come for a post-computational cognitive science. This paper is an attempt to shed some light on this debate by examining various conceptions and misconceptions of (particularly digital) computation.

References

[1]
Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
[2]
Bechtel, W. (1998a). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist's challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22, 295-318.
[3]
Bechtel, W. (1998b). Dynamicists versus computationalists: Whither mechanists? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 629.
[4]
Bechtel, W. (2001). Representations: From neural systems to cognitive systems. In W. Bechtel, P. Mandik, J. Mundale, & R. S. Stufflebeam (Eds.), Philosophy and the neurosciences: A reader. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
[5]
Bechtel, W. (2009). Constructing a philosophy of science of cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1, 548-569.
[6]
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2002). Connectionism and the mind: Parallel processing, dynamics, and evolution in networks (2nd ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
[7]
Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research (2nd ed.). Cambridge: The MIT Press.
[8]
Beer, R. (forthcoming). Dynamical systems and embedded cognition. In K. Frankish and W. Ramsey (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of artificial intelligence. Cambridge University Press.
[9]
Boden, M. A. (2008). Information, computation, and cognitive science. In P. Adriaans and J. van Benthem (Eds.). Handbook of the philosophy of science, volume 8: Philosophy of information, pp. 741-761. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
[10]
Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139-159.
[11]
Burks A. W., Goldstine, H. H., & von Neumann, J. (1946). Preliminary discussion of the logical design of an electronic computing instrument. In B. Randell (Ed.), The origins of digital computers: Selected papers. (3rd ed. 1982). pp. 399-414. New York: Springer.
[12]
Chalmers, D. (1992). Subsymbolic computation and the Chinese room. In J. Dinsmore (Ed.), The symbolic and connectionist paradigms: Closing the gap (pp. 25-47). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
[13]
Chalmers, D. (1993). Why Fodor and Pylyshyn were wrong: The simplest refutation. Philosophical Psychology, 6, 305-319.
[14]
Chomsky, N. (1992). Language and interpretation: Philosophical reflections and empirical Inquiry. In J. Earman (Ed.), Inference, explanation, and other frustrations: Essays in the philosophy of Science (pp. 99-128). Berkeley: University of California Press.
[15]
Churchland, P. S., Koch, C., & Senjowsky, T. J. (1988). What is computational neuroscience? In E. L. Schwartz (Ed.), Computational neuroscience (pp. 46-55). Cambridge, MA: The MIT press.
[16]
Churchland, P. S., & Senjowsky, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[17]
Clark, A. (1990). Connectionism, competence, and explanation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 41, 195-222.
[18]
Copeland, B. J. (1996). What is computation? Synthese, 108, 335-359.
[19]
Copeland, B. J. (1997). The broad conception of computation. The American Behavioral Scientist, 40, 690-716.
[20]
Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2006). Mechanism. In S. Sarkar & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), Philosophy of science: An encyclopedia (pp. 469-478). New York: Routledge.
[21]
Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
[22]
Dayan, P., & Abbott, L. F. (2001). Theoretical neuroscience: Computational and mathematical modeling of neural systems. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[23]
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. New York: Little, Brown and Company.
[24]
Diederich, J. (1990). Spreading activation and connectionist models for natural language processing. Theoretical Linguistics, 16, 25-64.
[25]
Dodig-Crnkovic, G., & Burgin, M. (2011). Information and computation: Essays on scientific and philosophical understanding of foundations of information and computation. Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company.
[26]
Dreyfus, H. (1972). What computers can't do. New York: Harper and Row.
[27]
Egan, F. (2011). Two kinds of representational contents for cognitive theorizing. Paper presented at the 2011 Philosophy and the Brain conference at the Institute for Advanced Studies, Hebrew University in Jerusalem, Israel. Retrieved May 9, 2011, from https://sites.google.com/site/philosophybrainias 2011/home/conference-papers-1/Egan-TwoKindsofRepContent.pdf?attredirects=0&d=1.
[28]
Eliasmith, C. (2003). Moving beyond metaphors: Understanding the mind for what it is. The Journal of Philosophy, 100, 493-520.
[29]
Eliasmith, C. (2007). Computational neuroscience. In P. Thagard (Ed.), Philosophy of psychology and cognitive science: Handbook of philosophy of science. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
[30]
Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. H. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, representation and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge: MIT Press.
[31]
Fodor, J. A. (1980). Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognition psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 63-109.
[32]
Fodor, J. A. (1981). The mind-body problem. Scientific American, 244, 114-123.
[33]
Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3-71.
[34]
Fresco, N. (2010). A computational account of connectionist networks. Recent Patents on Computer Science, 3, 20-27.
[35]
Froese, T. (2011). Breathing new life into cognitive science. Avant, 2, 113-129.
[36]
Gandy, R. (1980). Church's thesis and principles for mechanisms. In J. Barwise, H. J. Keisler, & K. Kunen (Eds.), The Kleene symposium (pp. 123-148). Amsterdam: North-Holland.
[37]
Hamann, H., & Wörn, H. (2007). Embodied computation. Parallel Processing Letters, 17, 287-298.
[38]
Haugeland, J. (1985). AI: The very idea. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[39]
Horst, S. (1999). Symbols and computation: A critique of the computational theory of mind. Minds and Machines, 9, 347-381.
[40]
Izhikevich, E. M. (2007). Dynamical systems in neuroscience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[41]
Kaplan, D. M., & Bechtel, W. (2011). Dynamical models: An alternative or complement to mechanistic explanations? Topics in Cognitive Science, 3, 438-444.
[42]
Kremer, S. C. (2007). Spatio-temporal connectionist networks. In P. A. Fishwick (Ed.), Handbook of dynamic system modelling. London: Chapman & Hall/CRC.
[43]
Maass, W., & Markram, H. (2004). On the computational power of circuits of spiking neurons. Journal of Computer and System Sciences, 69, 593-616.
[44]
Machamer, P. (2004). Activities and causation: The metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18, 27-39.
[45]
MacLennan, B. J. (2001). Connectionist approaches. In N. J. Smelser & P. B. Baltes (Eds.), International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences (pp. 2568-2573). Oxford: Elsevier.
[46]
MacLennan, B. J. (2004). Natural computation and non-Turing models of computation. Theoretical Computer Science, 317, 115-145.
[47]
Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: W. H. Freeman & Co.
[48]
Matthews, R. (1997). Can connectionists explain systematicity? Mind and Language, 12, 154-177.
[49]
McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biology, 5, 115-133.
[50]
Newell, A. (1980). Physical symbol systems. Cognitive Science, 4, 135-183.
[51]
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1976). Computer science as an empirical enquiry: Symbols and search. Communications of the ACM, 19, 113-126.
[52]
O'Brien, G. (1999). Connectionism, analogicity and mental content. Acta Analytica, 22, 111-131.
[53]
O'Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2006). How do connectionist networks compute? Cognitive Processing, 7, 30-41.
[54]
Pfeiffer, R., & Scheier, C. (1999). Understanding intelligence. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[55]
Piccinini, G. (2008a). Computation without representation. Philosophical Studies, 137, 205-241.
[56]
Piccinini, G. (2008b). Computers. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 89, 32-73.
[57]
Piccinini, G. (2008c). Some neural networks compute, others don't. Neural Networks, 21, 311-321.
[58]
Piccinini, G., & Bahar, S. (2011). Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Paper presented at the Computation and the Brain workshop 2011 at the Institute for Advanced Studies, Hebrew University in Jerusalem, Israel. Retrieved June 2, 2011, from https://sites.google.com/ site/iascomputationbrainhuji2011/home/previous-lectures/Piccinini%26Bahar_NeuralComputation andtheComputationalTheoryofCognition.doc?attredirects=0&d=1.
[59]
Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. F. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283-311.
[60]
Piccinini, G., & Scarantino, A. (2011). Information processing, computation and cognition. Journal of Biological Physics, 37, 1-38.
[61]
Poggio, T., & Koch, C. (1985). Ill-posed problems in early vision: From computational theory to analogue networks. In the proceedings of the Royal Society of London, series B, Biological Sciences, 226, 303-323.
[62]
Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and reality. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[63]
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[64]
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1993). Computers and the symbolization of knowledge. In R. Morelli, W. M. Brown, D. Anselmi, K. Haberlandt, & D. Lloyd (Eds.), Minds brains and computers: Perspectives in cognitive science and artificial intelligence. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
[65]
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1999). What's in your mind? In E. Lepore & Z. W. Pylyshyn (Eds.), What is cognitive science? (pp. 1-25). MA: Blackwell Publishers.
[66]
Rubel, L. A. (1985). The brain as an analog computer. Journal of Theoretical Neurobiology, 4, 73-81.
[67]
Rumelhart, D. E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
[68]
Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.
[69]
Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417-424.
[70]
Searle, J. R. (1990). Is the brain a digital computer? Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 64, 21-37.
[71]
Siegelmann, H. T. (1999). Neural networks and analogue computation: Beyond the Turing limit. Boston: Birkhauser.
[72]
Siu, K. Y., Roychowdhury, V., & Kailath, T. (1995). Discrete neural computation: A theoretical foundation. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
[73]
Smolensky, P. (1988). On the proper treatment of connectionism. The behavioural and brain sciences, 11, 1-23.
[74]
Smolensky, P. (1991). The constituent structure of connectionist mental states: A reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. In T. Horgan & J. L. Tienson (Eds.), Connectionism and the philosophy of mind (pp. 281-308). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
[75]
Smolensky, P. (1995). Constituent structure and explanation in an integrated connectionist/symbolic cognitive architecture. In C. MacDonald & G. MacDonald (Eds.), Connectionism: Debates on psychological explanation (pp. 223-290). U.K.: Blackwell Publishers.
[76]
Smolensky, P., & Legendre, G. (2006). The harmonic mind: From neural computation to optimality-theoretic grammar. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[77]
Spivey, M. (2007). The continuity of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[78]
Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411-444.
[79]
Stepp, N., Chemero, A., & Turvey, M. T. (2011). Philosophy for the rest of cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science, 3, 425-437.
[80]
Thagard, P. (2005). Mind: Introduction to cognitive science (2nd ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press.
[81]
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamical systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: The MIT press.
[82]
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
[83]
Tienson, J. L. (1988). An introduction to connectionism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 26, 1-16.
[84]
Trappenberg, T. (2010). Fundamentals of computational neuroscience (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[85]
van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. The behavioural and brain sciences, 21, 615-665.
[86]
van Gelder, T., & Port, R. F. (1995). It's about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In T. van Gelder & R. F. Port (Eds.), Mind as motion. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[87]
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[88]
von Eckardt, B. (1993). What is cognitive science? Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
[89]
Wallace, B., Ross, A., Davies, J., & Anderson, T. (2007). The mind, the body and the world: Psychology after cognitivism?. Exeter: Imprint Academic.
[90]
Waltz, D. L., & Pollack, J. B. (1985). Massively parallel parsing: A strongly interactive model of natural language interpretation. Cognitive Science, 9, 51-74.
[91]
Weiskopf, D. A. (2011). Models and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183, 313-338.
[92]
White, G. (2011). Descartes among the robots: Computer science and the inner/outer distinction. Minds and Machines, 21, 179-202.
[93]
Zednik, C. (2011). The nature of dynamical explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78, 238-263.

Cited By

View all

Recommendations

Comments

Please enable JavaScript to view thecomments powered by Disqus.

Information & Contributors

Information

Published In

cover image Minds and Machines
Minds and Machines  Volume 22, Issue 4
November 2012
105 pages

Publisher

Kluwer Academic Publishers

United States

Publication History

Published: 01 November 2012

Author Tags

  1. Classicism
  2. Cognitive science
  3. Computation
  4. Computational neuroscience
  5. Computationalism
  6. Connectionism
  7. Dynamicism
  8. Mechanistic explanation
  9. Representation

Qualifiers

  • Article

Contributors

Other Metrics

Bibliometrics & Citations

Bibliometrics

Article Metrics

  • Downloads (Last 12 months)0
  • Downloads (Last 6 weeks)0
Reflects downloads up to 23 Feb 2025

Other Metrics

Citations

Cited By

View all

View Options

View options

Figures

Tables

Media

Share

Share

Share this Publication link

Share on social media