Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Skip to main content
Log in

A Psychologically Plausible Logical Model of Conceptualization

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper discusses how we understand and use a concept or the meaningof a general term to identify the objects falling under the term. There aretwo distinct approaches to research on the problems of concepts and meaningthe psychological approach and the formal (or logical) approach. My majorconcern is to consider the possibility of reconciling these two differentapproaches, and for this I propose to build a psychologically plausibleformal system of conceptualization. That is, I will develop a theory-basedaccount of concepts and propose an explanation of how an agent activates aperspective (which consists of theories) in response to a situation in whichreasoning using a concept is called for. Theories are represented as sets offacts and rules, both strict and defeasible. Each theory is organized in acoherent perspective which stands for an agent's mental state or an agent'smodel of another agent's perspective. Perspectives are organized intohierarchies and the theory for a concept in one perspective may defeat thetheory for the same concept in another perspective. Which perspective issuperior is context-dependent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Explore related subjects

Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.

References

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1983), ‘Ad Hoc Categories’, Memory and Cognition 11, pp. 211–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braisby, N. (1990), ‘Situating Word Meaning’, in R. Cooper, K. Mukai, and J. Perry, eds., Situation Theoryand Its Applications, Stanford University Press, pp. 315–342.

  • Braisby, N., Franks, B., and Myers, T. (1989),’ ‘Partiality andConference in ConceptCombination’, in J. Ezquerro and J. Larrazabal, eds., Cognition, Semantics and Philosophy,Norwell, MA Kluwer, Academic Publisher, pp. 179–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1993), Language and Thought, Wakefield, Rhode Island Moyer Bell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1962), ‘A Transformation Approach to Syntax’, in A. A. Hill, ed., Proceedings of the Third Texas conference on Problems of Linguistic Analysis in English, Austin, TX The University of Texas, pp 124–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1982), Frege An Introduction to his Philosophy,Sussex, Great Britain The Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U., Santambrogio, M., and Violi, P. (1988), Meaning and Mental Representations, Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892), ‘On Sense and Meaning’, in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, New York, NY Oxford University Press. 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1964), The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System, in M. Furth, tr. and ed., Berkeley, CA Uniersity of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1993), ‘The Emergence of Meaning’, Linguistics and Philosophy 16, pp. 285–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geerts, P., Nute, D., and Vermeir, D. (1994), ‘Ordered Logic: Defeasible Reasoning for Multiple Agents’, Decision Support Systems II, pp. 157–190.

  • Johnson-Iaird, P. N. (1988), ‘How Is Meanin Mentally Repesented?’, in U. Eco, M. Santambrogio, and P. Violi, eds., Meaning and Mental Representations, Indiana University Press, pp. 99–118.

  • Katz, J. J. (1981), Language and Other Abstract Objects, Totuwa Rowman and Littlefield.

  • Katz, J. J. (1984), ‘An Outline of Platonist Gramrnar’, in T. Bever, J. Carroll, and L. Miller, eds., Talking Minds, Carnridge, MA The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (1979), Semantic and Conceptual Development: An Ontological Perspective, Cambridge, MA Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (1989), Concepts, Kinds, and Cognitive Development, Cambridge, MA MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (1995), ‘The Growth of Causl Undertandings of Natural Kinds’, in D. Sperber, D. Premack,, and A. J. Premack, eds., Causal Cognition: A Multidisciplinary Debate, New York Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kintsch, W. (1984), ‘Approaches to the Study of the Psychology of Language’, in T. Bever, J. Carroll, and L. Miller, eds., Talking Minds, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronfeld, A. (1990), Reference and Computation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levesque, H. J. (1989), ‘Logic and the Complexity of Axiomatics’, in R.H. Thomason, ed., Philosophical Logic and Artificial Intelligence, Hingham, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lifschitz V. (1985), ‘Closed-World Databases and Circumscription’, Artificial Intelligence 27, pp. 229–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J. (1980), ‘Circumscription–A Formof Nonmonotonic Reasoning’, Artificial Intelligence 13, pp. 27–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDermott, L. C. and Doyle, J. (1984), ‘Non-Monotonic Logic I’, Artificial Intelligence 13, pp. 41–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medin, D. and Wattenmaker, W. (1987), ‘Category Cohesiveness, Theories, and Cognitive Archeology’, in U. Neisser, ed., Concepts and Conceptual Development: The Ecological and Intellectual Factors in Categories, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G. and Medin, D. (1985), ‘The Role of Theories in Conceptual Coherence’, Psychological Review 92, pp. 289–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nute, D. (1989), ‘A Review of Matthew L. Ginsberg, Readings in Nonmonotonic Readings’, Philosophical Psychcology 2, pp. 351–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiter, R. (1980), ‘A Logic for Default Reasoning’, Artificial Intelligence 13, pp. 81–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiter, R. (1987), ‘Nonmonotonic Reasoning’, Annual Review of Computer Science, Palo Alto, CA Annual Review Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz S. P. (1977), Naming, Necessity, and Natural Kinds, Ithaca, N.Y. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, Paul (1992), Conceptual Revolutions, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kim, HG. A Psychologically Plausible Logical Model of Conceptualization. Minds and Machines 7, 249–267 (1997). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008234817601

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008234817601

Navigation