Abstract
This paper deals with the question of what it is for a quantifier expression to be vague. First it draws a distinction between two senses in which quantifier expressions may be said to be vague, and provides an account of the distinction which rests on independently grounded assumptions. Then it suggests that, if some further assumptions are granted, the difference between the two senses considered can be represented at the formal level. Finally, it outlines some implications of the account provided which bear on three debated issues concerning quantification.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Westerståhl [29], Stanley and Szabo [27]. For simplicity we will not consider pragmatic accounts of domain restriction, that is, accounts on which the determination of domains is left to pragmatic factors which determine the communicated content as distinct from what is literally said, such as that outlined in Bach [1].
Peters and Westerståhl define quantifiers this way in [21], pp. 62-64. Note that in Definitions 1-3 no index is attached to A and B to show that they depend on D, but such effect could easily be obtained with some minor adjustment. For example, the notation adopted in Lappin [16] makes A and B systematically depend on D.
Supervaluationism is consistent with (VP) both in its standard version outlined in Fine [10] and in non-standard versions such as that provided in McGee and McLaughlin [19]. Epistemicism is consistent with (VP) at least in the version advocated in Williamson [31]. Other views consistent with (VP) are those suggested in Braun and Sider [8] and in Iacona [12], which qualify as neither supervaluationist nor epistemicist. Finally, (VP) is consistent with some views according to which vagueness is in rebus, as in Barnes [2] and in Barnes and Williams [4] and [3].
The examples (7) and (8) are drawn from Peters and Westerståhl [21], pp. 213.
Iacona [14] provides an argument against the uniqueness assumption.
Sainsbury [23] suggests a criterion of adequate formalization that rests on the idea that formalization must preserve what is said, pp. 161-162.
A direct proof of the first order expressibility of ‘more than half of’ is provided in Iacona [13]. The theorems presented in this section provide a generalization of that result.
Here it is assumed that contextual restrictions are formally represented in the way suggested in Section 4. But note that one would get the same result even if one adopted a formal representation in which a separate predicate letter expresses the restricting condition, because in that case (12) and (13) would be replaced by two formulas ∀x(R x⊃(P x⊃Q x)) and ∀x(S x⊃(P x⊃Q x)) which differ in the first predicate letter.
Note that the converse entailment clearly does not hold. For it may be the case that the sentences containing a quantifier expression e (as it is used on a given occasion) admit non-minimal variation in formal representation even if e does not exhibit quantifier indeterminacy. This is shown by the case of ‘more than half of’, which does not exhibit quantifier indeterminacy even though (3) may be represented as (17) or (18).
Barwise and Cooper [5], p. 162.
Note that, given the restriction mentioned in Section 1, ‘sentence’ refers to simple quantified sentences such as (1)-(6).
Instead, there is a straightforward connection between logicality so understood and first order definability. Iacona [13] proves that every logical quantifier expression is first order definable.
Moss [20], Section 8.2, provides a complete axiomatization of a class of inferences involving sentences containing either ‘most’ or ‘some’. The explanation suggested here seems to hold at least for that class.
Peters and Westerståhl, among others, assume that domains are sets, see p. 48. In Section 5 the same assumption is adopted for the sake of argument.
Note, however, that it might be unclear whether ‘all’ is used unrestrictedly, in which case a similar kind of indeterminacy would arise. Note also that, just like ‘all’ may involve a restriction, the same goes for the general term ‘thing’ as it occurs in ‘all things’. As it is made clear in Lopez de Sa [22], pp. 405-406, (UP) is compatible with recognizing that there might be restricted uses of ‘thing’ that are vague. For in that case, quantifying over every thing in that sense is not the same thing as quantifying over absolutely everything.
I presented the material for this paper in talks at the University of Milan (spring 2014), at the University of Barcelona (spring 2015), and at the University of L’Aquila (fall 2014). The paper has benefited enormously from the questions, objections, and suggestions I have received on those occasions. Special thanks go to Dan López De Sa, Sven Rosenkranz and Elia Zardini. I also owe much to two anonymous referees for their sharp and accurate comments.
References
Bach, K. (1994). Conversational impiciture. Mind and Language, 124–162.
Barnes, E. (2010). Ontic vagueness: A guide for the perplexed. Noûs, 44, 601–627.
Barnes, E., & Williams, J.R.G. (2011). Response to Eklund. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 6, 173–182.
Barnes, E., & Williams, J.R.G. (2011). A theory of metaphysical indeterminacy. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 6, 103–148.
Barwise, J., & Cooper, R. (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4, 159–219.
Baumgartner, M., & Lampert, T. (2008). Adequate formalization. Synthese, 164, 93–115.
Bonnay, D., & Westerståhl, D. (2012). Consequence mining: constants versus consequence relations. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 671–709.
Braun, D., & Sider, T. (2007). Vague, So Untrue. Noûs, 41, 133–156.
Brun, G. (2008). Formalization and the objects of logic. Erkenntnis, 69, 1–30.
Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth and logic. Synthese, 30, 265–300.
Glanzberg, M. (2004). Quantification and realism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 541–72.
Iacona, A. (2010). Saying more (or less) than one thing Dietz, R., & Moruzzi, S. (Eds.) Cuts and Clouds: Vagueness, its Nature and its Logic, pages 289–303. Oxford University Press.
Iacona, A. (2015). Quantification and logical form Torza, A. (Ed.) Quantifiers, Quantifiers, and Quantifiers, pages 125–140. Springer.
Iacona, A. (2015). Two notions of logical form. manuscript.
Keenan, E.L., & Stavi, J. (1986). A semantic characterization of natural language determiners. Linguistics and Philosophy, 9, 253–326.
Lappin, S. (2000). An intensional parametric semantics for vague quantifiers. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 599–620.
Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Blackwell.
Liebesman, D., & Eklund, M. (2007). Sider on existence. Noûs, 41, 519–528.
McGee, V., & McLaughlin, B. (1995). Distincions without a difference. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 33, 203–251.
Moss, L.S. (2008). Completeness theorems for syllogistic fragments Hamm, F., & Kepser, S. (Eds.) Logics for Linguistic Structures, pages 143–173. Mouton de Gruyter.
Peters, S., & Westerståhl, D. (2006). Quantifiers in Language and Logic. Oxford University Press.
López De Sa, D. (2006). Is everything precise Dialectica, 60, 397–409.
Sainsbury, M. (1991). Logical Forms. Blackwell.
Sider, T. (2001). Four Dimensionalism. Clarendon Press.
Sider, T. (2003). Against vague existence. Philosophical Studies, 114, 135–146.
Sider, T. (2009). Against vague and unnatural existence: reply to liebesman and eklund. Noûs, 43, 557–567.
Stanley, J., & Szabó, Z.G. (2000). On quantifier domain restriction. Mind and Language, 15, 219–261.
Torza, A. (2014). Vague Existence. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, forthcoming.
Westerståhl, D. (1985). Determiners and Context Sets van Benthem, J., & ter Meulen, A. (Eds.) Generalized Quantifiers in Natural Language, pages 45–71. Dordrecht.
Westerståhl, D. (1985). Logical constants in quantifier languages. Linguistics and Philosophy, 8, 387–413.
Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. Routledge.
Williamson, T. (2003). Everything. Philosophical Perspectives, 17, 415–465.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Iacona, A. Vagueness and Quantification. J Philos Logic 45, 579–602 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-015-9387-1
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-015-9387-1