Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Skip to main content
Log in

Nash implementation in production economies with unequal skills: a characterization

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present study examines production economies with unequal labor skills, where the planner is ignorant of the set of feasible allocations in advance of production. In particular, we characterize Nash implementation by canonical mechanisms by means of Maskin monotonicity and a new axiom, non-manipulability of unused skills (NUS), where the latter represents a weak independence property with respect to changes in skills. Following these characterizations, we show that some Maskin monotonic social choice correspondences are not implementable if information about individual skills is absent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sustainable management requires knowledge on the size of the stocks, their age composition, their distribution, and the environment in which they live. Every year, data from Norwegian scientific surveys and from fishers are compared with data from other countries (Norwegian marine scientists cooperate closely with researchers from other countries, especially Russia) and assessed by ICES, the International Council for the Exploration of the Sea.

  2. This practice is in accordance with international agreements including the 1982 UN Law of the Sea Convention, the 1995 UN Fish Stocks Agreement, and the 1995 FAO Code of Conduct for Responsible Fisheries.

  3. Recently, an ecosystem approach is increasingly being applied to Norwegian fisheries management. This takes into account not only how harvesting affects fish stocks, but also how fisheries affect the marine environment for living marine resources in general.

  4. Given that the total allowable catch in the Barents Sea is allocated through negotiations under international agreements, the country’s quotas are distributed among different groups of fishers and then subdivided and allocated among fishing boats in each group. With this in mind, the resource management mechanism in Norway is expected to implement fishing allocations by monitoring and punishing each fishing boat’s overexploitation of resources.

  5. In addition to the above-mentioned studies, for instance, Suh (1995), Yoshihara (1999), Kaplan and Wettstein (2000), and Tian (2009) all proposed simple or natural mechanisms to implement particular SCCs, whereas Shin and Suh (1997) and Yoshihara (2000) characterized SCCs implementable by simple or natural mechanisms.

  6. The symbol \(\mathbb {R}_{+}\) denotes the set of non-negative real numbers.

  7. The symbol \(\mathbb {R}_{++}\) denotes the set of positive real numbers.

  8. For any two sets X and Y, \(X\subseteq Y\) whenever any \(x\in X\) also belongs to Y, and \(X=Y\) if and only if \(X\subseteq Y\) and \(Y\subseteq X\).

  9. It might be more natural to define labor skill and labor intensity in a discriminative way: for example, if \({\overline{s}}_{i}\in {\mathcal {S}}\) is i ’s labor skill, then i’s labor intensity is a variable \(s_{i}\), where \( 0<s_{i}\le {\overline{s}}_{i}\). In such a formulation, we may view the amount of \(s_{i}\) as being determined endogenously by agent i. In spite of this more natural view, we assume in the following discussion that labor intensity is a constant value, \(s_{i}={\overline{s}}_{i}\), for the sake of analytical simplicity. The main theorems in the following discussion remain valid with a few changes to the settings of the economic environments, even if labor intensity was assumed to be varied.

  10. See Hong (1995), Suh (1995), Shin and Suh (1997), Tian (1999, 2000), and Yoshihara (2000).

  11. Hong (1995) also discusses implementation problems for the case of withholding as a simple extension of the case of not withholding.

  12. Even if f, \({\varvec{x}}\), and w are observed, the exact location of the true skill profile \({\varvec{s}}\) cannot be known before or after the production process. For a detailed discussion on this point, see Yamada and Yoshihara (2008).

  13. It is also possible in the same class of production economies with unknown skills to provide a full characterization of Nash implementation without any restriction on available mechanisms. In this case, the necessary and sufficient condition for Nash implementation is a variation of Condition M (originally introduced in Moore and Repullo (1990)), which has a highly complicated form. For this issue, see Yoshihara and Yamada (2017).

  14. The forthrightness condition was first introduced by Saijo et al. (1996) for implementation problems in pure exchange economies. Lombardi and Yoshihara (2013) then formulated this condition for implementation in abstract social choice problems.

  15. For a detailed explanation about information smuggling and about how forthrightness can exclude this problem, see Lombardi and Yoshihara (2013).

  16. Moreover, in the abstract social choice environments, the monotone transformation takes place within the set of feasible alternatives.

  17. By presuming exactly the same type of skill changes as that of NUS, the independence of unused skills (IUS) axiom introduced by Yamada and Yoshihara (2007) straightforwardly requires that the \(\varphi \)-optimal allocation at the economy \({\varvec{e}}\) should also be \(\varphi \)-optimal at the new economy \({\varvec{e}}^{\prime }\). NUS is much weaker than IUS.

  18. Van Parijs (1995) formulated the EOB principle as undominated diversity (Van Parijs 1995), which is stronger than SIU.

  19. Note \(\partial X\) denotes the upper boundary of the set \(X\subseteq \mathbb {R }_{+}^{2}\).

  20. From now on, we simply write a value of \(g^{*}\) as \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) \) instead of \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}};f\left( \sum s_{k}x_{k}\right) \right) \), without loss of generality. Moreover, let \( g_{j2}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) \) be the second component of \( g_{j}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) \), which is the share of the output produced to agent j specified by the mechanism under \({\varvec{a}} \).

References

  • Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (1996) Fair allocation with unequal production skills: the no-envy approach to compensation. Math Soc Sci 32:71–93

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley D (1967) Resource allocation and the public sector. Yale Econ Essay 7:45–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Hong L (1995) Nash implementation in production economies. Econ Theory 5:401–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz L, Maskin E, Postlewaite A (1995) Feasible Nash implementation of social choice rules when the designer does not know endowments or production sets. In: Ledyard J (ed) The economics of informational decentralization: complexity, efficiency, and stability, essays in honor of stanley reiter. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Amsterdam, pp 367–433

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson MO (2001) A crash course in implementation theory. Soc Choice Welf 18:655–708

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan T, Wettstein D (2000) Surplus sharing with a two-stage mechanism. Int Econ Rev 41:399–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maskin E (1999) Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Rev Econ Stud 66:23–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombardi M, Yoshihara N (2013) A full characterization of Nash implementation with strategy space reduction. Econ Theory 54:131–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore J, Repullo R (1990) Nash implementation: a full characterization. Econometrica 58:1083–1100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer J, Silvestre J (1993) The proportional solution for economies with both private and public ownership. J Econ Theory 59:426–444

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saijo T, Tatamitani Y, Yamato T (1996) Toward natural implementation. Int Econ Rev 37:949–980

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shin S, Suh S-C (1997) Double implementation by a simple game form in the commons problem. J Econ Theory 77:205–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suh S-C (1995) A mechanism implementing the proportional solution. Econ Des 1:301–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Tian G (1999) Double implementation in economies with production technologies unknown to the designer. Econ Theory 13:689–707

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tian G (2000) Incentive mechanism design for production economies with both private and public ownerships. Games Econ Behav 33:294–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tian G (2009) Implementation in economies with non-convex production technologies unknown to the designer. Games Econ Behav 66:526–545

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tian G, Li Q (1995) On Nash-implementation in the presence of withholding. Games Econ Behav 9:222–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs P (1995) Real freedom for all. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Yamada A, Yoshihara N (2007) Triple implementation by sharing mechanisms in production economies with unequal labor skills. Int J Game Theory 36:85–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamada A, Yoshihara N (2008) A mechanism design for a solution to the tragedy of commons. Rev Econ Des 11:253–270

    Google Scholar 

  • Yoshihara N (1999) Natural and double implementation of public ownership solutions in differentiable production economies. Rev Econ Des 4:127–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Yoshihara N (2000) A characterization of natural and double implementation in production economies. Soc Choice Welf 17:571–599

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yoshihara N, Yamada A (2010) Nash implementation in production economies with unequal skills: a complete characterization. CCES Discussion Paper Series 38, Hitotsubashi University

  • Yoshihara N, Yamada A (2017) Nash implementation in production economies with unequal skills: complete characterizations. mimeo

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Naoki Yoshihara.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We wish to give our special thanks to the editor in charge and two reviewers of this journal, whose comments and suggestions substantially improved the paper. We are also grateful to Arunava Sen, Guoqiang Tian, Michele Lombardi, Hans Peters, Yoshi Saijo, William Thomson, and Takuma Wakayama for their helpful discussions and to all the participants of the International Meeting of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare in Moscow in July 2010, the Annual Meeting of the Japanese Economic Association in June 2010, and the workshops at Maastricht University, Ecole Polytechnique, and Keio University.

Appendix

Appendix

As a preliminary step, we construct two auxiliary functions, which are used in the proofs of Theorem 2. Given \({\varvec{x}}\in \left[ 0,{\bar{x}} \right] ^{n}\) and \(i\in N\), let

$$\begin{aligned} \pi \left( {\varvec{x}}_{-i}\right) \equiv \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \max _{j\ne i\text { s.t. }x_{j}<{\bar{x}}}\frac{x_{j}+{\bar{x}}}{2} &{}\quad \text {if there exists }j\in N\backslash \left\{ i\right\} \text { such that }x_{j}< {\bar{x}}\text {,} \\ {\bar{x}} &{}\quad \text {otherwise.} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

Let the notation \(\sigma _{i}\in {\mathcal {S}}\) represent the announced skill of agent i, which is not necessarily identical to a truthful skill \( s_{i}\in {\mathcal {S}}\) of agent i, and \(\varvec{\sigma }=\left( \sigma _{i}\right) _{i\in N}\in {\mathcal {S}}^{n}\) represent a profile of the announced skills of all agents. Then,

  • Let \(d^{{\varvec{y}}}\) be such that for each \(w\in \mathbb {R} _{+}\), each \(\left( \varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}} \mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \in {\mathcal {S}}^{n}\times \left[ 0, {\bar{x}}\right] ^{n}\times \mathbb {R}_{+}^{n}\), and each \(i\in N\),\(d_{i}^{{\varvec{y}}}\left( \varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,} {\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}},w\right) =\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} w &{} \text {if }x_{i}=\pi \left( {\varvec{x}}_{-i}\right)<{\bar{x}} \text { or }x_{i}<\pi \left( {\varvec{x}}_{-i}\right) ={\bar{x}}\text {, and }y_{i}=0\text {,} \\ 0 &{} \text { otherwise.} \end{array} \right. \)

  • Let \(d^{\varvec{\sigma }}\) be such that for each \(w\in \mathbb {R} _{+}\), each \(\left( \varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \in {\mathcal {S}}^{n}\times \left[ 0, {\bar{x}}\right] ^{n}\times \mathbb {R}_{+}^{n}\), and each \(i\in N\),\(d_{i}^{\varvec{\sigma }}\left( \varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,} {\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}},w\right) =\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} w &{} \begin{array}{l} \text {if }x_{i}=0\text {, }\sigma _{i}>\sigma _{j}\text { for each }j\ne i\text {, } \\ \text {and }y_{i}>\max \left\{ f\left( \sum _{j\ne i}\sigma _{j}{\overline{x}} \right) ,w\right\} \end{array} \\ 0 &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array} \right. \)

The function \(d^{{\varvec{y}}}\) assigns all of the output produced to only one agent who provides the maximal positive amount, but less than \({\bar{x}}\), of labor time and reports zero demand for output. The function \(d^{\varvec{\sigma }}\) assigns all of the output produced to only one agent who reports the highest skill and does not work.

Let us assume that a game form in \(\Gamma \) requires agents to announce their own skills. Moreover, assume that this game form specifies the share of output by using the function \(d^{\varvec{\sigma }}\) whenever the expected output \(f\left( \sum \sigma _{k}x_{k}\right) \) derived from the deta \(\left( \varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\right) \) differs from the realized output \(w\left( {\varvec{s}},{\varvec{x}}\right) \). Then, it has an interesting property as the following Lemma A1 shows.

Lemma A1

Let Assumption 1hold. Let \( \gamma =\left( A,g\right) \in \Gamma \) be a game form, where every agent i is requested to announce his/her own skill, \(\sigma _{i} \), as a part of a message, and the outcome function g specifies the share of the output according to the function \(d^{ \varvec{\sigma }}\) whenever \(f\left( \sum \sigma _{i}x_{i}\right) \ne w\left( {\varvec{s}},{\varvec{x}}\right) \) . Given \(\left( {\varvec{u}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{s}}\right) \in {\mathcal {E}}\), let \( {\varvec{a}}=\left( {\varvec{m}}\mathbf {,}\widehat{{\varvec{x}}} \right) \in \times _{i\in N}A_{i}\)bea Nash equilibrium of \(\left( \gamma ,{\varvec{u}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{s}}\right) \) such that \(f\left( \sum \sigma _{k}{\widehat{x}} _{k}\right) =w\left( {\varvec{s}},\widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\right) \) . Then,for each \(i\in N\) with \({\widehat{x}}_{i}>0\), \( \sigma _{i}=s_{i}\).

This proof is presented exactly as Lemma 1 in Yamada and Yoshihara (2007). Note that the mechanism, \(\gamma ^{*}\), constructed in the proof of Theorem 2 meets the premise of Lemma A1.

Proof of Theorem 2

As a preliminary step, given \({\varvec{s}}\in {\mathcal {S}}^{n}\), \( {\varvec{z}}=\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \in Z^{n}\), and \(p\in \Delta \), let \(B\left( p,s_{i},z_{i}\right) \equiv \left\{ z_{i}^{\prime }\in Z\mid p_{y}y_{i}^{\prime }-p_{x}s_{i}x_{i}^{\prime }\le p_{y}y_{i}-p_{x}s_{i}x_{i}\right\} \). Moreover, define \(B\left( \Delta ^{P}\left( {{\varvec{e}}}, {{\varvec{z}}}\right) ,s_{i},z_{i}\right) \equiv \cup _{p\in \Delta ^{P}\left( {\varvec{e}},{\varvec{z}}\right) }B\left( p,s_{i},z_{i}\right) \).

Let \(p_{\alpha ^{{}}}\left( x_{i};{\varvec{x}}_{-i},{ {\varvec{s}}}\right) \equiv \lim _{x_{i}^{\prime }\rightarrow x_{i}} \frac{f\left( \sum _{j\ne i}s_{j}x_{j}+s_{i}x_{i}^{\prime }\right) -f\left( \sum _{j\ne i}s_{j}x_{j}+s_{i}x_{i}\right) }{s_{i}x_{i}^{\prime }-s_{i}x_{i}} s_{i}\), where \(\alpha =`+\)’ if \(x_{i}^{\prime }>x_{i}\); and \(\alpha =\)‘−’ if \(x_{i}^{\prime }<x_{i}\). Given \(\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{ \sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \in {\mathcal {U}}^{n}\times {\mathcal {S}}^{n}\times \left[ 0,{\bar{x}}\right] ^{n}\times \mathbb {R}_{+}^{n}\), let

$$\begin{aligned}&N\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,} {\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \\&\quad \equiv \left\{ i\in N\mid \exists \left( x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \in Z\text { s.t. }\left( \left( x_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{x}} _{-i}\right) ,\left( y_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{y}}_{-i}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \right\} . \end{aligned}$$

Let us see how the set \(N\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma } \mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \) can function in the mechanism. When \(i\in N\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}} \mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \), there are two cases: one is \(x_{i}=0\), and the other is \( x_{i}>0\).

Let \(x_{i}=0\) for \(i\in N\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma } \mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \). Then, \(\sigma _{i}\) may be a false announcement whenever there exists \(\left( \sigma _{i}^{\circ },x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \), rather than just \(\left( x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \), such that \(\left( \left( x_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{x}}_{-i}\right) ,\left( y_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{y}}_{-i}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\left( \sigma _{i}^{\circ }, \varvec{\sigma }_{-i}\right) \right) \) holds. If such a profile exists, then this agent could be a potential deviator in her announcements of not only her consumption vector but also her skill. Therefore, the mechanism would assign a ‘punishment outcome’ to this agent by taking \(\left( \sigma _{i}^{\circ },x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \) as a potential true message. However, such a potential true message would not necessarily be uniquely specified, in that there may be multiple potential true messages. In such a case, we specify how to select one from the set of multiple potential true messages in the following way. For \(i\in N\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma } \mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \) with \(x_{i}=0\), let \(\left( \sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}},x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}},y_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}\right) \) be selected by:

$$\begin{aligned}&\left( \sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}},x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}},y_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}\right) \\&\quad =\arg \min _{\left\{ \left( \sigma _{i}^{\circ },x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \mid \left( \left( x_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{x}}_{-i}\right) ,\left( y_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{y}}_{-i}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\left( \sigma _{i}^{\circ },\varvec{\sigma } _{-i}\right) \right) \right\} } y_{i}^{\circ }-p_{\alpha ^{{}}}\left( x_{i}^{\circ };{\varvec{x}}_{-i},\left( \sigma _{i}^{\circ },\varvec{\sigma }_{-i}\right) \right) x_{i}^{\circ }\text {.} \end{aligned}$$

Here, if \(\sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}>0\), then \( y_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}- p_{\alpha ^{{}}}\left( x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}; {\varvec{x}}_{-i}, \left( \sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}},\varvec{\sigma }_{-i}\right) \right) x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}=y_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}- p_{-}\left( x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}; {\varvec{x}}_{-i},\left( \sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}},\varvec{\sigma } _{-i}\right) \right) x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}\), while if \(\sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}=0\), then \(y_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}-p_{\alpha ^{{}}}\left( x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}};{\varvec{x}}_{-i},\left( \sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}, \varvec{\sigma }_{-i}\right) \right) x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}=y_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}-p_{+}\left( x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}};{\varvec{x}}_{-i},\left( \sigma _{i}^{\mu ^{{}}},\varvec{\sigma }_{-i}\right) \right) x_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}=y_{i}^{\mu ^{{}}}\).

Next, consider \(x_{i}>0\) for \(i\in N\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{ \sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \). In this case, \(\sigma _{i}\) may be the ture information as discussed below. Then, as there exists \(\left( x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \) such that \(\left( \left( x_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{x}}_{-i}\right) ,\left( y_{i}^{\circ },{\varvec{y}}_{-i}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \) by definition of \(N\left( {\varvec{u}} ,\varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,} {\varvec{y}}\right) \), such \(\left( x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \) is a potential true message for agent i. Then, the mechanism would assign a ‘punishment outcome’ to this agent by taking \(\left( x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \) as a potential true message. Note that, again there may be multiple potential true messages. However, in this case, any selection from the set of potential true messages leaves the agent indifferent, as \(u_{i}\left( x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) =u_{i}\left( x_{i}^{\prime \circ },y_{i}^{\prime \circ }\right) \) holds for any different potential true messages \(\left( x_{i}^{\circ },y_{i}^{\circ }\right) \) and \(\left( x_{i}^{\prime \circ },y_{i}^{\prime \circ }\right) \), given that \(\varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \subseteq P\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \). Therefore, in this case, the specification of a ‘punishment outcome’ is not difficult, as discussed below.

Now, we are ready to discuss the construction of a mechanism. Denote the upper boundary of \(L\left( z_{i},u_{i}\right) \) by \(\partial L\left( z_{i},u_{i}\right) \equiv \left\{ z_{i}^{\prime }\in L\left( z_{i},u_{i}\right) \mid u_{i}\left( z_{i}^{\prime }\right) =u_{i}\left( z_{i}\right) \right\} \). For the sake of simplifying notations, given \( \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \in {\mathcal {E}}\) and \(\left( z_{j}^{\circ },\left( {\varvec{x}}_{-j}, {\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}, \varvec{\sigma }\right) \), we will sometimes use \(L\left( z_{j}^{\circ },u_{j};\varvec{\sigma }\right) \) instead of the precise statement \(L\left( \left( z_{j}^{\circ },\left( {\varvec{x}}_{-j}, {\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) ,u_{i};\varvec{\sigma }\right) \) in the following discussion. We define a canonical mechanism \( \gamma ^{*}=\left( A^{*},g^{*}\right) \in \Gamma _{C}^{*}\) with \(A_{i}^{*}\equiv \)\(M_{i}\times \left[ 0,{\bar{x}}\right] \), where \( M_{i}\equiv {\mathcal {U}}^{n}\times {\mathcal {S}}\times Z\) with generic element \( \left( {\varvec{u}}^{i},\sigma _{i},z_{i}\right) \), for each \(i\in N\) , as follows:

For each \({\varvec{a}}=\left( \left( {\varvec{u}} ^{i}\right) _{i\in N},\varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{z}}, \widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\right) \equiv \left( {\varvec{u}}^{i},\sigma _{i},z_{i}, {\widehat{x}}_{i}\right) _{i\in N}\in \times _{i\in N}\left( M_{i}\times \left[ 0,{\bar{x}}\right] \right) \) and for each output \(w=w\left( {\varvec{s}}, \widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\right) \in \mathbb {R}_{+}\),

Rule 1: if \(f\left( \sum \sigma _{k}{\widehat{x}} _{k}\right) =w\), and

1–1: there exists \({\varvec{u}}\in {\mathcal {U}} ^{n} \) such that \({\varvec{u}}^{i}={\varvec{u}}\) for each \( i\in N\), and \(\sum y_{k}\le w\) and

1–1-a): if \(\left( \widehat{{\varvec{x}} }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \), then \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}} ;w\right) =\left( \widehat{{\varvec{x}}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \),

1–1-b): if \(\left( \widehat{{\varvec{x}} }\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \notin \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \), then \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}} ;w\right) =\left( \widehat{{\varvec{x}}},{\mathbf {0}}\right) \),

1–2: there exists \(j\in N\) such that \({\varvec{u}} ^{i}={\varvec{u}}\ne {\varvec{u}}^{j}\) for each \(i\ne j\), \( \left( \widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \notin \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{j},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \), and

1–2-a): if \(j\in N\left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{ \sigma }\mathbf {,}\widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\mathbf {,} {\varvec{y}}\right) \), then \(g_{i}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}};w\right) =\left( {\widehat{x}}_{i},0\right) \) for each \(i\ne j\), and \(g_{j}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}};w\right) =\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \left( {\widehat{x}}_{j},\min \left\{ y_{j}^{\prime \prime },w\right\} \right) &{} \text {if }y_{j}>f\left( \sum \sigma _{k}{\bar{x}}\right) \\ \left( {\widehat{x}}_{j},0\right) &{} \text {otherwise,} \end{array} \right. \)

where \(y_{j}^{\prime \prime }\) is given byFootnote 19

\({\left( {\widehat{x}}_{j},y_{j}^{\prime \prime }\right) \in \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \partial \left[ L\left( z_{j}^{\circ },u_{j};\varvec{\sigma }\right) \cup B\left( \Delta ^{P}\left( \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{ \sigma }\right) ,\left( z_{j}^{\circ },\left( \widehat{{\varvec{x}}} _{-j},{\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \right) ,\sigma _{j},z_{j}^{\circ }\right) \right] &{} \text {if }{\widehat{x}}_{j}>0 \\ \left\{ \left( 0,y_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}-p_{\alpha ^{{}}}\left( x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}; \widehat{{\varvec{x}}}_{-j},\left( \sigma _{j}^{\mu ^{{}}},\varvec{\sigma }_{-j}\right) \right) x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}\right) \right\} &{} \text {otherwise,} \end{array} \right. }\)

for \(z_{j}^{\circ }=(x_{j}^{\circ },y_{j}^{\circ })\) with \(\left( \left( x_{j}^{\circ },\widehat{{\varvec{x}}}_{-j}\right) ,\left( y_{j}^{\circ },{\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\varvec{\sigma }\right) \),

1–2-b): if \(j\notin N\left( {\varvec{u}}, \varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,}\widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\mathbf {,} {\varvec{y}}\right) \) and there exists \((x_{j}^{\circ },y_{j}^{\circ })\in Z\) such that

\(\left( \left( x_{j}^{\circ },\widehat{{\varvec{x}}} _{-j}\right) ,\left( y_{j}^{\circ },{\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \in P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{j},\varvec{ \sigma }\right) \), then \(g_{i}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}};w\right) =\left( {\widehat{x}}_{i},0\right) \) for each \(i\ne j\), and

\(g_{j}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}};w\right) =\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \left( {\widehat{x}}_{j},w\right) &{} \text {if }{\widehat{x}}_{j}>0\text { and } y_{j}>w \\ \left( {\widehat{x}}_{j},0\right) &{} \text {otherwise,} \end{array} \right. \)

1–3: in any other case, \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}} ;w\right) =\left( {\varvec{x}},d^{{\varvec{y}}}\left( \varvec{ \sigma }\mathbf {,}\widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}},w\right) \right) \),

Rule 2: if \(f\left( \sum \sigma _{k}{\widehat{x}} _{k}\right) \ne w\), then \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}};w\right) =\left( {\varvec{x}},d^{\varvec{\sigma }}\left( \varvec{\sigma }\mathbf {,} \widehat{{\varvec{x}}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}},w\right) \right) \).

Lemma A2

Let Assumption 1hold and \( n\ge 3\). Then,\(\gamma ^{*}\) implements any interior and efficient SCC \(\varphi \) satisfyingM and NUS in Nash equilibria.

Proof

Let \(\varphi \) be an interior and efficient SCC satisfying M and NUS. Let \({\varvec{e}}=\left( {\varvec{u}}, {\varvec{s}}\right) \in {\mathcal {E}}\).

(1) First, we show that \(\varphi \left( {\varvec{e}} \right) \subseteq NA\left( \gamma ^{*},{\varvec{e}}\right) \). Let \({\varvec{z}}=\left( {\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,} {\varvec{y}}\right) \in \)\(\varphi \left( {\varvec{e}}\right) \). Let \( {\varvec{a}}=\left( \left( {\varvec{u}}^{i}\right) _{i\in N}, {\varvec{s}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{z}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\right) \in \times _{i\in N}\left( M_{i}\times \left[ 0,{\bar{x}}\right] \right) \) be such that \({\varvec{u}}^{i}={\varvec{u}}\) for each \(i\in N\). Then, \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) =\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \) from Rule 1–1.Footnote 20 Suppose \(j\in N\) deviates to \(a_{j}^{\prime }=\left( {\varvec{u}} ^{j\prime },s_{j}^{\prime },z_{j}^{\prime },x_{j}^{\prime }\right) \in M_{i}\times \left[ 0,{\bar{x}}\right] \). From Assumption 1 and the continuity of the utility functions, if \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime }, {\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) =0\), it implies the worst outcome for j.

If \(a_{j}^{\prime }\) induces Rule 2, then \(x_{j}^{\prime }>0\) and \( g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) =0\). If \( a_{j}^{\prime }\) induces Rule 1-3, then either \(\left( \left( x_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{x}}_{-j}\right) ,\left( y_{j}^{\prime }, {\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{j},\left( s_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{s}}_{-j}\right) \right) \) or \(\sum _{i\ne j}y_{i}+y_{j}^{\prime }>f\left( \sum _{i\ne j}s_{i}x_{i}+s_{j}x_{j}^{\prime }\right) \). In either case, \(y_{j}^{\prime }>0\) holds, and so \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}} _{-j}\right) =0\). If \(a_{j}^{\prime }\) induces Rule 1–2-b, then \( x_{j}=0=x_{j}^{\prime }\) and \(s_{j}^{\prime }\ne s_{j}\). Thus, \( g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) =0\).

If \(a_{j}^{\prime }\) induces Rule 1–2-a, then either \(x_{j}^{\prime }>0\) or \( x_{j}^{\prime }=0\). In the former case, where \(s_{j}^{\prime }=s_{j}\) holds, Rule 1–2-a implies that

$$\begin{aligned} g_{j}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) \in \partial \left[ L\left( z_{j},u_{j};{\varvec{s}}\right) \cup B\left( \Delta ^{P}\left( {\varvec{e}},{\varvec{z}}\right) ,s_{j},z_{j}\right) \right] \subseteq L\left( z_{j},u_{j}\right) , \end{aligned}$$

since any price vector \(p\in \Delta ^{P}\left( {\varvec{e}},{\varvec{z}} \right) \) implies \(B\left( p,s_{j},z_{j}\right) \subseteq L\left( z_{j},u_{j}\right) \). When \(x_{j}^{\prime }=0\), there exists \(\left( \sigma _{j}^{\mu ^{{}}},x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}},y_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}\right) \) such that \( \left( \left( x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}},{\varvec{x}}_{-j}\right) ,\left( y_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}},{\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},\left( \sigma _{j}^{\mu ^{{}}},{\varvec{s}}_{-j}\right) \right) \) and \(y_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}-p_{-}\left( x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}};{\varvec{x}} _{-j},\left( \sigma _{j}^{\mu ^{{}}},{\varvec{s}}_{-j}\right) \right) x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}\le y_{j}-p_{-}\left( x_{j}; {\varvec{x}}_{-j},{\varvec{s}}\right) x_{j}\) or \(y_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}\le y_{j}-p_{-}\left( x_{j}; {\varvec{x}}_{-j},{\varvec{s}}\right) x_{j}\) hold. Let \(p=\left( p_{x},p_{y}\right) \) be the efficiency price which supports \({\varvec{z}}\) as a \(\varphi \)-optimal allocation at \({\varvec{e}}\). Then, \(y_{j}-\frac{p_{x}}{ p_{y}}s_{j}x_{j}\ge y_{j}-p_{-}\left( x_{j};{\varvec{x}}_{-j}, {\varvec{s}}\right) x_{j}\), so that \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime }, {\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) =y_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}-p_{\alpha ^{{}}}\left( x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}};{\varvec{x}}_{-j},\left( \sigma _{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}, {\varvec{s}}_{-j}\right) \right) x_{j}^{\mu ^{{}}}\le y_{j}-\frac{p_{x}}{p_{y}} s_{j}x_{j}\). This implies \(g_{j}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}} _{-j}\right) \in L\left( z_{j},u_{j}\right) \). Finally, if \(a_{j}^{\prime }\) induces Rule 1–1, then \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}} _{-j}\right) =y_{j}^{\prime }\le f(\sum _{i\ne j}s_{i}x_{i}+s_{j}x_{j}^{\prime })-\sum \nolimits _{i\ne j} y_{i}\). Thus, since \({\varvec{z}}\in \)\(P\left( {\varvec{e}}\right) \), \( u_{j}\left( x_{j}^{\prime },y_{j}^{\prime }\right) \le u_{j}\left( z_{j}\right) \). In summary, j has no incentive to switch to \(a_{j}^{\prime }\).

(2) Second, show \(NA\left( \gamma ^{*},{\varvec{e}}\right) \subseteq \varphi \left( {\varvec{e}}\right) \). Since \( g^{*}\) is constant with \({\varvec{x}}\) in \({\varvec{z}}\) , let \({\varvec{a}}=\left( \left( {{\varvec{v}}}^{i}\right) _{i\in N},\varvec{\sigma },{\varvec{z}},{\varvec{x}} \right) \in NE\left( \gamma ^{*},{\varvec{e}}\right) \) without loss of generality.

Suppose that \({\varvec{a}}\) induces Rule 2. Then, either \(N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \equiv \left\{ i\in N\mid x_{i}=0\right\} =\varnothing \) or \(N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \ne \varnothing \) . If \(N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) =\varnothing \), then for each \( i\in N\), \(g_{i2}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) =0\). Then, if \( \sum _{i\ne k}\sigma _{i}x_{i}=\sum _{i\ne k}s_{i}x_{i}\) holds for each \( k\in N\), then \(\left( n-1\right) \cdot \left( \sum \sigma _{i}x_{i}\right) =\left( n-1\right) \cdot \left( \sum s_{i}x_{i}\right) \), which contradicts Rule 2. Thus, for some \(j\in N\), \(\sum _{i\ne j}\sigma _{i}x_{i}\ne \sum _{i\ne j}s_{i}x_{i}\). If j switches to \(a_{j}^{\prime }=\left( {{\varvec{v}}}^{j\prime },\sigma _{j}^{\prime },z_{j}^{\prime },x_{j}^{\prime }\right) \) with \(\sigma _{j}^{\prime }>\max \left\{ \sigma _{i}\mid i\ne j\right\} \), \(y_{j}^{\prime }>\max \left\{ f\left( \sum _{k\ne j}\sigma _{k}{\overline{x}}\right) ,w\right\} \), and \( x_{j}^{\prime }=0\), then \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}} _{-j}\right) >0\) under Rule 2.

Let \(N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \ne \varnothing \) with \( \#N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \ge 2\). Then, for each \(j\in N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \), if j’s deviating strategy \( a_{j}^{\prime }\) is such that for each \(i\ne j\), \(\sigma _{j}^{\prime }>\sigma _{i}\), \(y_{j}^{\prime }>\max \left\{ f\left( \sum _{k\ne j}\sigma _{k}{\overline{x}}\right) ,w\right\} \), and \(x_{j}^{\prime }=0\), then \( g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) =f\left( \sum s_{k}x_{k}\right) \) under Rule 2.

Let \(\#N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) =1\) and \(\#N\backslash N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \ge 2\). Then, there exists \(j\in N\backslash N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \) such that \(\sum _{i\in N\backslash \left( N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \cup \left\{ j\right\} \right) }\sigma _{i}x_{i}\ne \sum _{i\in N\backslash \left( N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) \cup \left\{ j\right\} \right) }s_{i}x_{i}\). Thus, j can switch to \(a_{j}^{\prime }\) such that \( g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) >0\) under Rule 2. This can be shown in a similar way to the case of \(N^{0}\left( {\varvec{x}}\right) =\varnothing \).

Suppose that \({\varvec{a}}\) induces Rules 1–2 or 1–3. Then, there exists \( j\in N\) such that \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) =0\). From Lemma A1, \(\sigma _{j}=s_{j}\) or \(x_{j}=0\). Suppose \({\varvec{a}}\) induces Rule 1-2. Then, \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) =0\) implies that \(y_{j}\le f\left( \sum \sigma _{k}{\overline{x}}\right) \). Then, j can either deviate to Rule 1-3 with \(\sigma _{j}^{\prime }=s_{j}\), \( x_{j}^{\prime }=\pi \left( {\varvec{x}}_{-j}\right) <{\overline{x}}\), and \(y_{j}^{\prime }=0\) or get \( g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) >0\) under Rule 1–2 by \(y_{j}^{\prime }>f\left( \sum _{i\ne j}\sigma _{i}{\bar{x}}+\sigma _{j}^{\prime }{\bar{x}}\right) \). Suppose \({\varvec{a}}\) induces Rule 1–3. Then, there exists \(a_{j}^{\prime }\) such that \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) >0\) under Rule 1–3. In summary, \( {\varvec{a}}\) induces neither Rule 1–2 nor Rule 1–3.

Suppose that \({\varvec{a}}\) induces Rule 1–1-b. Then, \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) =\left( {\varvec{x}},{\mathbf {0}}\right) \). Then, some \(j\in N\) can deviate to induce Rule 1–2, so that \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) >0\), which is a contradiction.

Thus, \({\varvec{a}}\) induces Rule 1–1-a, and \(g^{*}\left( \varvec{a }\right) =\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \). From the definition of Rule 1–1-a, \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}} \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },\varvec{\sigma }\right) \) where \({\varvec{u}}^{\prime }={\varvec{v}}^{i}\) for all \(i\in N\). Since \({\varvec{a}}\in NE\left( \gamma ^{*}, {\varvec{e}}\right) \), \(\sigma _{i}=s_{i}\) holds for any \(i\in N\) with \(x_{i}>0\) according to Lemma A1. Assume, without loss of generality, that there exists at most one unique individual j such that \(x_{j}=0\). Let us consider the following two cases:

Case 1: Let \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },{\varvec{s}} \right) \). Then, we can show that \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },{\varvec{s}}\right) \). Suppose that \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \notin \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}} ^{\prime },{\varvec{s}}\right) \). Then, for the individual \(j\in N\) with \(x_{j}=0\), \(\sigma _{j}\ne s_{j}\). Then, if this j takes the strategy \(a_{j}^{\prime }=\left( {\varvec{u}}^{j},s_{j},z_{j}^{ \prime },x_{j}^{\prime }\right) \) with \({\varvec{u}}^{j}\ne {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }\), \(x_{j}^{\prime }>0\), and \(y_{j}^{\prime }>f\left( \sum s_{k}{\overline{x}}\right) \), then Rule 1–2-b can be applied. This is because NUS implies \(j\notin N\left( {\varvec{u}} ^{\prime },{\varvec{s}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \) by \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },{\varvec{s}} \right) \backslash \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\right) \) and \(x_{j}=0\). Then, if \(x_{j}^{\prime }>0\) is sufficiently small, \(u_{j}\left( g_{j}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime }, {\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) \right) =u_{j}\left( x_{j}^{\prime },f\left( \sum _{i\ne j}s_{i}x_{i}+s_{j}x_{j}^{\prime }\right) \right) >u_{j}\left( 0,y_{j}\right) =u_{j}\left( g_{j}^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}\right) \right) \) holds by the fact that \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \) is an interior allocation, since \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },\varvec{\sigma }\right) \). This implies \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \notin NA\left( \gamma ^{*},\left( {\varvec{u}},{\varvec{s}}\right) \right) \), which is a contradiction. Thus, \( \left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\right) \). Note that \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in NA\left( \gamma ^{*},\left( {\varvec{u}},{\varvec{s}}\right) \right) \) implies that \(\partial L\left( \left( x_{i},y_{i}\right) ,u_{i}^{\prime };{\varvec{s}}\right) \subseteq L\left( \left( x_{i},y_{i}\right) ,u_{i}\right) \cap Z_{i}\left( {\varvec{s}}, {\varvec{z}}_{-i}\right) \) for each \(i\in N\) by Rule 1–2-a. Thus, \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}},{\varvec{s}}\right) \) by M.

Case 2: Let \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \notin P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\right) \). Since \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}} \right) \in P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },\varvec{\sigma }\right) \) , \(\sigma _{j}<s_{j}\) holds for the agent \(j\in N\) with \(x_{j}=0\). In this case, either \(j\in N\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \) or not.

First, suppose that \(j\notin N\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \). Take \({\varvec{u}} ^{j}=\left( u_{j}^{\prime \prime },{\varvec{u}}_{-j}^{\prime }\right) \) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \partial \left[ L\left( \left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) ,u_{j}^{\prime }; {\varvec{s}}\right) \cup \left( \cup _{p\in \Delta ^{P}\left( \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },\varvec{\sigma }\right) ,\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \right) }B\left( p,s_{j},\left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) \right) \right) \right] \subseteq L\left( \left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) ,u_{j}^{\prime \prime }\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Then, \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \in P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{j},{\varvec{s}}\right) \) holds. Then, by \(a_{j}^{\prime }=\left( {\varvec{u}}^{j},s_{j},z_{j}^{*},x_{j}^{*}\right) \) with \(x_{j}^{*}>0\) and \(y_{j}^{*}>f\left( \sum s_{k}{\overline{x}}\right) \), j can induce Rule 1–2-b, and get \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}} _{-j}\right) =f\left( \sum _{i\ne j}s_{i}x_{i}+s_{j}x_{j}^{*}\right) \). Thus, if \(x_{j}^{*}>0\) is sufficiently small, \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \notin NA\left( \gamma ^{**},\left( {\varvec{u}},{\varvec{s}}\right) \right) \), which is a contradiction. Thus, \(j\notin N\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \) does not hold.

Second, let \(j\in N\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },{\varvec{s}} \mathbf {,}{\varvec{x}}\mathbf {,}{\varvec{y}}\right) \). Since \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \notin P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\right) \), there exists \(z_{j}^{\prime }\equiv \left( x_{j}^{\prime },y_{j}^{\prime }\right) \gg {\mathbf {0}}\) such that \(\left( z_{j}^{\prime },\left( {\varvec{x}}_{-j},{\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }, {\varvec{s}}\right) \). In this case, \(y_{j}^{\prime }\ge y_{j}+\frac{p_{x}}{p_{y}} s_{j}x_{j}^{\prime }\) holds for \(p\equiv \left( p_{x},p_{y}\right) \in \Delta ^{P}\left( \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime },{\varvec{s}}\right) ,\left( z_{j}^{\prime },\left( {\varvec{x}}_{-j}, {\varvec{y}}_{-j}\right) \right) \right) \), since \(z_{j},z_{j}^{\prime }\in \left\{ \left( x,y\right) \in Z\mid y=f(\sum _{i\ne j}s_{i}x_{i}+s_{j}x)-\sum _{i\ne j}y_{i}\right\} \) and f is concave. Moreover, since \(z_{j}^{\prime }\notin L\left( \left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) ,u_{j}^{\prime }\right) \) and \( z_{j}^{\prime }\in B\left( p,s_{j},z_{j}^{\prime }\right) \), \(B\left( p,s_{j},z_{j}^{\prime }\right) \nsubseteq L\left( \left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) ,u_{j}^{\prime };{\varvec{s}}\right) \) holds. Then, since \({\varvec{a}} \in NE\left( \gamma ^{*},{\varvec{e}}\right) \), (i) \(\partial \left[ L\left( \left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) ,u_{j}^{\prime };{\varvec{s}}\right) \cup \right. \left. B\left( p,s_{j},z_{j}^{\prime }\right) \right] \subseteq L\left( \left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) ,u_{j}\right) \) and (ii) \(y_{j}^{\prime }=y_{j}+\frac{p_{x}}{p_{y}}s_{j}x_{j}^{\prime }\) hold. Indeed, if (i) does not hold, then j can induce Rule 1–2-a by suitably choosing \(a_{j}^{\prime }=\left( {\varvec{u}}^{j},s_{j},z_{j}^{*},x_{j}^{*}\right) \) with \({\varvec{u}}^{j}\ne {\varvec{u}}^{\prime }\), \(x_{j}^{*}>0\), and \(y_{j}^{*}>f\left( \sum s_{k} {\overline{x}}\right) \), so that \(g_{j2}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime }, {\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) \ge y_{j}+\frac{p_{x}}{p_{y}}s_{j}x_{j}^{*}\) and \(g_{j}^{*}\left( a_{j}^{\prime },{\varvec{a}}_{-j}\right) \notin L\left( \left( x_{j},y_{j}\right) ,u_{j}\right) \), which is a contradiction from \({\varvec{a}}\in NE\left( \gamma ^{**},{\varvec{e}}\right) \). The same argument also follows if (ii) does not hold.

Consider \({\varvec{u}}^{\prime \prime }\equiv \left( u_{j}, {\varvec{u}}_{-j}^{\prime }\right) \). Note that by M, \( \left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime \prime },\varvec{\sigma }\right) \). Then, by Rule 1–1-a, for \({\varvec{a}}^{\prime \prime }=\left( \left( { {\varvec{v}}}^{\prime \prime i}\right) _{i\in N},\varvec{\sigma } ,{\varvec{z}},{\varvec{x}}\right) \) with \( {\varvec{v}}\)\(^{\prime \prime i}={\varvec{u}}^{\prime \prime }\) (\(\forall i\in N\)), \(g^{*}\left( {\varvec{a}}^{\prime \prime }\right) =\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \) and \( {\varvec{a}}^{\prime \prime }\in NE\left( \gamma ^{*}, {\varvec{e}}\right) \) hold. Suppose \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}} \right) \notin \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime \prime }, {\varvec{s}}\right) \). Then, since \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in P\left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime \prime },{\varvec{s}}\right) \), j can induce Rule 1–2-b by the same reasoning as in Case 1, so that \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \notin NA\left( \gamma ^{*}, {\varvec{e}}\right) \), which is a contradiction. Thus, \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{u}}^{\prime \prime },{\varvec{s}}\right) \). Then, \({\varvec{a}} ^{\prime \prime }\in NE\left( \gamma ^{*},{\varvec{e}}\right) \) and \(\left( {\varvec{x}},{\varvec{y}}\right) \in NA\left( \gamma ^{*},{\varvec{e}}\right) \) imply that \(\partial L\left( \left( x_{i},y_{i}\right) ,u_{i}^{\prime };{\varvec{s}}\right) \subseteq L\left( \left( x_{i},y_{i}\right) ,u_{i}\right) \) holds for each \(i\in N\backslash \left\{ j\right\} \) by Rule 1–2-a. Thus, \(\left( {\varvec{x}}, {\varvec{y}}\right) \in \varphi \left( {\varvec{e}}\right) \) by M. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 2. From Lemma A2, we obtain the desired result. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yoshihara, N., Yamada, A. Nash implementation in production economies with unequal skills: a characterization. Soc Choice Welf 53, 113–134 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01174-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01174-w

Navigation