Abstract
By ‘informational entropy’, we understand an inherent boundary to knowability, due e.g. to perceptual, theoretical, evidential or linguistic limits. In this paper, we discuss a logical framework in which this boundary is incorporated into the semantic and deductive machinery, and outline how this framework can be used to model various situations in which informational entropy arises.
The research of the third author is supported by the NWO Vidi grant 016.138.314, the NWO Aspasia grant 015.008.054, and a Delft Technology Fellowship awarded in 2013.
Access this chapter
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
A formal context [17], or polarity, is a structure such that A and X are sets, and \(I\subseteq A\times X\) is a binary relation. Every such induces maps \((\cdot )^\uparrow : \mathcal {P}(A)\rightarrow \mathcal {P}(X)\) and \((\cdot )^\downarrow : \mathcal {P}(X)\rightarrow \mathcal {P}(A)\), respectively defined by the assignments \(B^\uparrow : = I^{(1)}[B]\) and \(Y^\downarrow : = I^{(0)}[Y]\). A formal concept of is a pair \(c = (B, Y)\) such that \(B\subseteq A\), \(Y\subseteq X\), and \(B^{\uparrow } = Y\) and \(Y^{\downarrow } = B\). Given a formal concept \(c = (B,Y)\) we will often write \([\![{c}]\!]\) for B and \((\![{c}]\!)\) for Y and, consequently, \(c = ([\![{c}]\!], (\![{c}]\!))\). The set of the formal concepts of can be partially ordered as follows: for any ,
$$\begin{aligned} c\le d\quad \text{ iff } \quad B_1\subseteq B_2 \quad \text{ iff } \quad Y_2\subseteq Y_1. \end{aligned}$$With this order, is a complete lattice, the concept lattice of . Any complete lattice is isomorphic to the concept lattice of some polarity .
- 2.
Applying the notation (2) to a graph-based \(\mathcal {L}\)-frame , we will sometimes abbreviate \(E^{[0]}[Y]\) and \(E^{[1]}[B]\) as \(Y^{[0]}\) and \(B^{[1]}\), respectively, for each \(Y, B\subseteq Z\). If \(Y= \{y\}\) and \(B = \{b\}\), we write \(y^{[0]}\) and \(b^{[1]}\) for \(\{y\}^{[0]}\) and \(\{b\}^{[1]}\), and write \(Y^{[01]}\) and \(B^{[10]}\) for \((Y^{[0]})^{[1]}\) and \((B^{[1]})^{[0]}\), respectively. Notice that, by Lemma 3, \(Y^{[0]} = I_{E^c}^{(0)}[Y] = Y^{\downarrow }\) and \(B^{[1]} = I_{E^c}^{(1)}[B] = B^{\uparrow }\), where the maps \((\cdot )^\downarrow \) and \((\cdot )^\uparrow \) are those associated with the polarity .
- 3.
In well-known settings (e.g. [15, 22]), indiscernibility is modelled as an equivalence relation. However, transitivity will fail, for example, when zEy iff \(d(z, y)<\alpha \) for some distance function d. It has been argued in the psychological literature (cf. [21, 25]) that symmetry will fail in situations where indiscernibility is understood as similarity, defined e.g. as z is similar to y iff z has all the features y has.
- 4.
Notice that since the E-relation in this example is only ‘one step’, it is automatically transitive and therefore a pre-order. Hence, unsurprisingly, the associated concept lattice is distributive.
References
Chodorow, M.S., Ravin, Y., Sachar, H.E.: A tool for investigating the synonymy relation in a sense disambiguated thesaurus. In: Second Conference on Applied Natural Language Processing, pp. 144–151 (1988)
Conradie, W., Craig, A.: Relational semantics via TiRS graphs. In: TACL 2015 Extended Abstract (2015)
Conradie, W., Craig, A., Palmigiano, A., Wijnberg, N.: Modelling competing theories. In: Proceedings of the EUSFLAT 2019, Atlantis Studies in Uncertainty Modelling (2019, accepted)
Conradie, W., Craig, A., Palmigiano, A., Zhao, Z.: Constructive canonicity for lattice-based fixed point logics. In: Kennedy, J., de Queiroz, R.J.G.B. (eds.) WoLLIC 2017. LNCS, vol. 10388, pp. 92–109. Springer, Heidelberg (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-55386-2_7. ArXiv preprint arXiv:1603.06547
Conradie, W., et al.: Rough concepts (2019, submitted)
Conradie, W., Frittella, S., Palmigiano, A., Piazzai, M., Tzimoulis, A., Wijnberg, N.M.: Categories: how I learned to stop worrying and love two sorts. In: Väänänen, J., Hirvonen, Å., de Queiroz, R. (eds.) WoLLIC 2016. LNCS, vol. 9803, pp. 145–164. Springer, Heidelberg (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-52921-8_10
Conradie, W., Frittella, S., Palmigiano, A., Piazzai, M., Tzimoulis, A., Wijnberg, N.M.: Toward an epistemic-logical theory of categorization. In: Proceedings of the TARK 2017. EPTCS, vol. 251, pp. 167–186 (2017)
Conradie, W., Palmigiano, A.: Constructive canonicity of inductive inequalities. arXiv preprint arXiv:1603.08341 (2016)
Conradie, W., Palmigiano, A.: Algorithmic correspondence and canonicity for non-distributive logics. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. (2019). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2019.04.003
Conradie, W., Palmigiano, A., Robinson, C., Tzimoulis, A., Wijnberg, N.M.: Modelling socio-political competition (2019, submitted)
Craig, A., Gouveia, M., Haviar, M.: TiRS graphs and TiRS frames: a new setting for duals of canonical extensions. Algebra Universalis 74(1–2), 123–138 (2015)
Craig, A., Haviar, M.: Reconciliation of approaches to the construction of canonical extensions of bounded lattices. Mathematica Slovaca 64, 1–22 (2014)
Craig, A., Haviar, M., Priestley, H.A.: A fresh perspective on canonical extensions for bounded lattices. Appl. Categor. Struct. 21(6), 725–749 (2013)
Davey, B.A., Priestley, H.A.: Introduction to Lattices and Order. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2002)
Fagin, R., Halpern, J., Moses, Y., Vardi, M.: Reasoning About Knowledge. The MIT Press, Cambridge (1995)
Frittella, S., Manoorkar, K., Palmigiano, A., Tzimoulis, A., Wijnberg, N.M.: Towards a Dempster-Shafer theory of concepts (2019, submitted)
Ganter, B., Wille, R.: Formal Concept Analysis: Mathematical Foundations. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)
Gehrke, M., Harding, J.: Bounded lattice expansions. J. Algebra 238(1), 345–371 (2001)
Greco, G., Jipsen, P., Manoorkar, K., Palmigiano, A., Tzimoulis, A.: Logics for rough concept analysis. In: Khan, M.A., Manuel, A. (eds.) ICLA 2019. LNCS, vol. 11600, pp. 144–159. Springer, Heidelberg (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-58771-3_14
Krúdy, Á., Ladunga, K.: Measuring wavelength discrimination threshold along the entire visible spectrum. Periodica Polytechnica Mechanical Engineering 45(1), 41–48
Nosofsky, R.M.: Stimulus bias, asymmetric similarity, and classification. Cogn. Psychol. 23(1), 94–140 (1991)
Pawlak, Z.: Rough set theory and its applications to data analysis. Cybern. Syst. 29(7), 661–688 (1998)
Ploščica, M.: A natural representation of bounded lattices. Tatra Mt. Math. Publ. 5, 75–88 (1995)
Shannon, C.E., Weaver, W.: The Mathematical Theory of Communication. University of Illinois Press, Champaign (1949)
Tversky, A.: Features of similarity. Psychol. Rev. 84(4), 327 (1977)
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Appendices
A Equivalent Compatibility Conditions in Formal Contexts
Lemma 9
-
1.
The following are equivalent for every formal context and every relation \(R\subseteq A\times X\):
-
(i)
\(R^{(0)}[x]\) is Galois-stable for every \(x\in X\);
-
(ii)
\(R^{(0)} [Y]\) is Galois-stable for every \(Y\subseteq X\);
-
(iii)
\(R^{(1)}[B]=R^{(1)}[B^{\uparrow \downarrow }]\) for every \(B\subseteq A\).
-
(i)
-
2.
The following are equivalent for every formal context and every relation \(R\subseteq A\times X\):
-
(i)
\(R^{(1)}[a]\) is Galois-stable for every \(a\in A\);
-
(ii)
\(R^{(1)} [B]\) is Galois-stable, for every \(B\subseteq A\);
-
(iii)
\(R^{(0)}[Y]=R^{(0)}[Y^{\downarrow \uparrow }]\) for every \(Y\subseteq X\).
-
(i)
Proof
We only prove item 1, the proof of item 2 being similar. For \((i)\Rightarrow (ii)\), see [7, Lemma 4]. The converse direction is immediate.
\((i)\Rightarrow (iii)\). Since \((\cdot )^{\uparrow \downarrow }\) is a closure operator, \(B\subseteq B^{\uparrow \downarrow }\). Hence, Lemma 1.1 implies that \(R_{\Box }^{(1)}[B^{\uparrow \downarrow }]\subseteq R_{\Box }^{(1)}[B]\). For the converse inclusion, let \(x\in R_{\Box }^{(1)}[B]\). By Lemma 1.2, this is equivalent to \(B\subseteq R_{\Box }^{(0)}[x]\). Since \(R_{\Box }^{(0)}[x]\) is Galois-stable by assumption, this implies that \(B^{\uparrow \downarrow }\subseteq R_{\Box }^{(0)}[x]\), i.e., again by Lemma 1.2, \(x\in R_{\Box }^{(1)}[B^{\uparrow \downarrow }]\). This shows that \(R_{\Box }^{(1)}[B]\subseteq R_{\Box }^{(1)}[B^{\uparrow \downarrow }]\), as required.
\((iii)\Rightarrow (i)\). Let \(x\in X\). It is enough to show that \((R_{\Box }^{(0)}[x])^{\uparrow \downarrow }\subseteq R_{\Box }^{(0)}[x]\). By Lemma 1.2, \(R_\Box ^{(0)}[x]\subseteq R_\Box ^{(0)}[x]\) is equivalent to \(x\in R_\Box ^{(1)}[R_\Box ^{(0)}[x]]\). By assumption, \(R_{\Box }^{(1)}[R_\Box ^{(0)}[x]]=R_\Box ^{(1)}[(R_\Box ^{(0)}[x])^{\uparrow \downarrow }]\), hence \(x\in R_\Box ^{(1)}[(R_\Box ^{(0)}[x])^{\uparrow \downarrow }]\). Again by Lemma 1.2, this is equivalent to \((R_{\Box }^{(0)}[x])^{\uparrow \downarrow }\subseteq R_{\Box }^{(0)}[x]\), as required.
B Composing Relations on Graph-Based Structures
The present section collects properties of the E-compositions (cf. Definition 5).
Lemma 10
For any graph , relations \(R, S\subseteq Z \times Z\) and \(a, x\in Z\),
Proof
We only prove the identities in the left column.
Lemma 11
If \(R, T\subseteq Z\times Z\) and R is E-compatible, then so are \(R \circ _{E} T\) and \(R \bullet _{E} T\).
Proof
Let \(a\in Z\). By Lemma 10, \((R;T)^{[0]} [a] = R^{[0]}[I^{[0]}[T^{[0]} [a]]]\), hence the following chain of identities holds:
the second identity in the chain above following from the E-compatibility of R and Lemma 4.1. The remaining conditions for the E-compatibility of \(R \circ _{E} T\) and \(R \bullet _{E} T\) are shown similarly.
The following lemma is the counterpart of [5, Lemma 6] in graph-based semantics.
Lemma 12
If \(R,T\subseteq Z\times Z\) are E-compatible, then for any \(B,Y\subseteq Z\),
Proof
We only prove the first identity, the remaining ones being proved similarly.
Lemma 13
If \(R, T, U\subseteq Z\times Z\) are E-compatible, then \((R\circ _E T)\circ _E U = R\circ _E (T\circ _E U)\) and \((R\bullet _E T)\bullet _E U = R\bullet _E (T\bullet _E U)\).
Proof
For every \(x\in Z\), repeatedly applying Lemma 12 we get:
which shows that \(x (R\circ _E (T\circ _E U))^c a\) iff \(x ((R\circ _E T)\circ _E U)^ca\) for any \(x, a\in Z\), and hence \(x (R\circ _E (T\circ _E U)) a\) iff \(x ((R\circ _E T)\circ _E U)a\) for any \(x, a\in Z\), as required. The remaining statements are proven similarly.
C Proof of Proposition 4
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2019 Springer-Verlag GmbH Germany, part of Springer Nature
About this paper
Cite this paper
Conradie, W., Craig, A., Palmigiano, A., Wijnberg, N.M. (2019). Modelling Informational Entropy. In: Iemhoff, R., Moortgat, M., de Queiroz, R. (eds) Logic, Language, Information, and Computation. WoLLIC 2019. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 11541. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-59533-6_9
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-59533-6_9
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg
Print ISBN: 978-3-662-59532-9
Online ISBN: 978-3-662-59533-6
eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)