1. Introduction
For any odd positive integer
x, define two infinite sequences
and
of positive integers by setting:
such that
is odd for all
. The
problem asserts that there is
such that
for all odd positive integers
x. For a survey, see [
1]. For recent developments, see [
2,
3,
4,
5,
6,
7].
Usually, is called the trajectory of x. In this paper, we concentrate on and call it the E-sequence of x. The idea is that we generalize E-sequences to all infinite sequences of positive integers. Given any generalized E-sequence , if it is the E-sequence of the odd positive integer x, it is called -convergent to x and denoted by ; if is not the E-sequence of any odd positive integer, it is called -divergent and denoted by . Subsequently, these generalized E-sequences are also called E-sequences for simplicity.
The
problem in the form (1.1) should be owed to Crandall and Sander et al., see [
8,
9]. E-sequences are some variants of Everett’s parity sequences [
10] and Terras’ encoding representations [
11]. Everett and Terras focused on finite E-sequences resulting from (1.1). What we are concerned with is the
-convergence and
-divergence of any infinite sequence of positive integers, i.e., the generalized E-sequences.
A possible way to prove the
problem was devised by Möller as follows (see [
12]):
Conjecture 1. (i)is periodic for all odd positive integers;
(ii)is the unique pure periodic trajectory.
Usually, we can convert one claim about trajectories into the one about E-sequences. As for E-sequences, we have the following conjecture.
Conjecture 2. Let. Then,
(i) all non-periodic E-sequences are-divergent;
(ii) every E-sequencesatisfyingfor allis-divergent.
Note that Conjecture 2(i) does not hold for some generalizations of the
problem studied by Möller, Matthews, and Watts in [
12,
13]; Conjecture 2(ii) implies that there is some
n such that
in the E-sequence
of every odd positive integer
x, which is a conjecture posed by Terras in [
11] about his
-stopping time.
A remarkable fact is that Conjecture 1(i) is a corollary of Conjecture 2(i) by Theorem 3. This means that the -divergence of all non-periodic E-sequences implies the periodicity of for all positive integers x. Then, Conjecture 2(i) is of significance to the study of the problem. The principal results of this paper are to prove that several classes of non-periodic E-sequences are -divergent. In particular, we prove that:
- (i)
All non-periodic E-sequences with are -divergent.
- (ii)
If is , where if and , otherwise, then ;
- (iii)
Let be an irrational number, and define , then , where denotes the integral part of a for any real a.
Note that we prove the above claim (i) by using Wendel’s inequality and the Matthews and Watts’ formula
. In addition, it seems that our approach cannot help to prove the conjecture 1(ii) of the unique cycle. For such a topic, see [
14].
2. Preliminaries
Let be an E-sequence. In most cases, there is no odd positive integer x such that is the E-sequence of x, i.e., . However, there always exists such that the first n terms of the E-sequence of x are . Furthermore, for any , there always exists such that the first terms of the E-sequence of x are the designated block of , which is illustrated as .
Definition 1. Define , .
Clearly, , , , .
Proposition 1. Let and be defined as in (1.1). Then .
Proof. The proof is by a procedure similar to that of Theorem 1.1 in [
11] and omitted. □
Proposition 2. Given any positive integer n, there exist two integers and such that , , and .
Proof. By , there exist two integers and such that and . Then, by . By , we have . Thus, .
By , we have . Then by . Thus, . Define . Then, , and . Sequentially, define such that , …, . Then, for all .
Suppose that . We then sequentially have , which contradicts . Thus, . □
Note that the validity of Proposition 2 is dependent on the structure of . We formulate the middle part of the above proof as the following proposition.
Proposition 3. Assume that and . Define ,…, . Then, and for all .
Definition 2. For any , define , , , , .
Then, , , , , . Clearly, and are the same as and , respectively.
Proposition 4. Proof. By
and
, we have:
□
Definition 3. For any , define two integers and such that , , and . Further, define , ,…, .
Clearly, and are the same as and in Proposition 2, respectively.
Proposition 5. - (i)
- (ii)
For any , , and
;
- (iii)
;
- (iv)
if and only if ;
- (v)
if and only if .
Proof. (i) is from Proposition 3(ii), which is from (i) and Proposition 1.
(iii) By Definition 3, , . Then, , . Thus, by . Hence, . Therefore, by and .
By (iii), is increasing, then (iv) and (v) hold trivially. □
Proposition 5(iv) shows that if , then for all sufficiently large n. Proposition 5(v) shows the reasonableness of .
4. Non-Periodic E-Sequences
For any real number
,
denotes its fractional part. The following lemma is due to Matthews and Watts (see Lemma 2(b) in [
13]). We present its proof for the reader’s convenience.
Lemma 1. Let be an E-sequence such that and is unbounded. Then, .
Proof. From
, we have
. Then:
Thus:
which we call the Matthews and Watts’ formula (see Lemma 1(b) in [
13]).
Since
is unbounded, all
are distinct. Then:
Theorem 4. Let be a non-periodic E-sequence such that . Then,
Proof. Suppose that for some positive integer . It follows from Lemma 1 and that is bounded. Then, is periodic. Thus, is periodic, which contradicts the non-periodicity of . Hence, . □
The following lemma is the well known Wendel’s inequality (see [
15]). Lemma 3 is a consequence of an easy calculation.
Lemma 2. Let x be a positive real number, and let . Then, .
Lemma 3. Let a and b be two integers with and . Then, .
Lemma 4. for all .
Proof. Let
. Then:
and:
by Wendel’s inequality. Thus,
Let
. Then:
and
by Wendel’s inequality. Thus,
□
Theorem 5. Let such that , , and are distinct integers. Then, .
Proof. From the Matthews and Watts’ formula and Lemma 4, we have:
Then, . Thus, . □
Corollary 1. Let be an irrational number. Define . Then, .
Proof. Let . Then, by . Thus, , as . Hence, by Theorem 5.
Let . Then, . Since is an irrational number, is non-periodic. Thus, by Theorem 4. □
Lemma 5. Let x and n be two positive integers. Then, (i) (ii) for ; (iii) for .
Proof. (i) The proof is by induction on n. For the base step, let , then . For the induction step, assume that . Then, Thus, the inequality holds for all . The proof of (ii) is similar to that of (i) and omitted.
(iii) Let . Since , then . Thus, . Hence, . Therefore, .
Assume that . Since , then . Thus, . □
Lemma 6. Let such that , , for all . Then, (i) if for all ; (ii) if for all ; (iii) if for all ; (iv) if for all .
Proof. (i) From
, we have:
Then, by Lemma 5(i). Thus, .
(ii) From
, we have:
Then,
by Lemma 5(i). Thus:
Hence, .
(iii) Let . Then, . Thus, . Hence, . Therefore, .
Let . By Lemma 5(iii), we have . Then, . Thus, . Hence,
(iv) By Lemma 5(ii), we have:
Then, . □
A direct consequence of Lemma 6 is the following theorem, which may imply something unknown.
Theorem 6. Let such that , , for all . Then:
(i) implies for some ;
(ii) implies for some ;
(iii) implies for some ;
(iv) implies for some .
Theorem 7. Let be an E-sequence such that (i) for all ; (ii) there is a constant such that there are infinitely many distinct pairs of positive integers such that , . Then, .
Proof. It follows from (i) that for all by induction on n. by Proposition 6.
Let , , . Then, , by Proposition 5(ii). By , , we have . Thus, for some . Hence, . Therefore, . If there are only finitely many distinct k in all pairs , , as ; otherwise, , as . Then, . □
Corollary 2. Let be the E-sequence , where if and otherwise. Then, .
Proof. Take , , and . Then, , for all Thus, by Theorem 7. □
Theorem 8. Let be an E-sequence such that (i) for all ; (ii) there is a constant such that there are infinitely many distinct pairs of positive integers such that , , for all , i.e., is contained in . Then, .
Proof. Let , , . Then, , by Proposition 5(ii). By , we have .
Let
,
,
. Then,
. By Proposition 5(iii), we have
. Let
. Then,
by
. Thus:
Hence, . □
Theorem 9. Let , and define . Then, .
Proof. If is a rational number, then is purely periodic, and the result follows from Theorem 1. Let be an irrational number in the following. By the Hurwitz theorem, there are infinite convergents of such that . There are two cases to be considered.
Case 1. There are infinite convergents
of
such that
. We prove that
for all
. By
, we have
Then,
Thus,
Hence,
. Then, we have the following periodic table for
.
| | ⋯ | | ⋯ | |
| | ⋯ | | ⋯ | |
| | ⋯ | | | |
By Proposition 7(ii), for some .
By
, we have:
Thus, , as . Hence, .
Case 2. There are infinite convergents of such that .
Firstly, we prove for all , . By , we have . Then, . By , , we have . Then, . Thus, .
Secondly, we prove , . By , , we have . By , we have . Then, . By taking , we have , .
Let , then and . Thus, .
Let . Then, and . Thus, .
By easy calculation, we have , .
Then, we have the following periodic table for
.
| | | ⋯ | | ⋯ | | |
| | | ⋯ | | ⋯ | | |
| | | ⋯ | | | | |
Since
, we then take all convergents
of
such that
, and thus,
. By
,
and Proposition 7(ii), we have:
for some
. By
, where
, we have:
Thus, . Hence, . □