Contextual Inferences, Nonlocality, and the Incompleteness of Quantum Mechanics
<p>Light-cone picture of the EPR–Bohm–Bell scheme. The photon pair is generated at the bottom of the middle cone, and is described by <math display="inline"><semantics> <mi>λ</mi> </semantics></math>. The measurement settings <span class="html-italic">x</span> and <span class="html-italic">y</span> are chosen by Alice and Bob in separated light cones. The earliest time for generating the results <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>a</mi> <mo>|</mo> <mi>x</mi> </mrow> </semantics></math> and <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>b</mi> <mo>|</mo> <mi>y</mi> </mrow> </semantics></math> are at the intersections of the light cones, and this is also when Alice’s probability <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>P</mi> <mo>(</mo> <mi>b</mi> <mo>|</mo> <mi>y</mi> <mi>λ</mi> <mo>,</mo> <mi>x</mi> <mi>a</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> </semantics></math> about Bob’s result, and Bob’s probability <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>P</mi> <mo>(</mo> <mi>a</mi> <mo>|</mo> <mi>x</mi> <mi>λ</mi> <mo>,</mo> <mi>y</mi> <mi>b</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> </semantics></math> about Alice’s result become available (dashed arrows). These probabilities result from a contextual inference, which respects relativistic causality and does not entail any action or influence between Alice and Bob. The resulting predictions can be effectively checked in the verification zone V in the common future of all light cones.</p> "> Figure A1
<p>Illustration of the complete set of commuting observables considered here. The operators <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>X</mi> <mo>,</mo> <mi>Y</mi> <mo>,</mo> <mi>Z</mi> </mrow> </semantics></math> correspond to the Pauli matrices <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <msub> <mi>σ</mi> <mi>x</mi> </msub> <mo>,</mo> <msub> <mi>σ</mi> <mi>y</mi> </msub> <mo>,</mo> <msub> <mi>σ</mi> <mi>z</mi> </msub> </mrow> </semantics></math>, and <span class="html-italic">I</span> to the identity. Three operators in a set are enough, but a fourth commuting one is added in each group. The possible results are indicated for the initial state <math display="inline"><semantics> <msub> <mi>ψ</mi> <mrow> <mi>i</mi> <mi>n</mi> </mrow> </msub> </semantics></math> (GHZ state), which is an eigenstate of the CSCO at the center. Note that the missing operators <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>X</mi> <mi>X</mi> <mi>Y</mi> </mrow> </semantics></math>, <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>X</mi> <mi>Y</mi> <mi>X</mi> </mrow> </semantics></math>, <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>Y</mi> <mi>Y</mi> <mi>X</mi> </mrow> </semantics></math>, and <math display="inline"><semantics> <mrow> <mi>Y</mi> <mi>Y</mi> <mi>Y</mi> </mrow> </semantics></math> all give random results in the state <math display="inline"><semantics> <msub> <mi>ψ</mi> <mrow> <mi>i</mi> <mi>n</mi> </mrow> </msub> </semantics></math>.</p> ">
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Probabilistic Framework
3. Enforcing Relativistic Causality
- probability of Alice obtaining result a for input x, and
- probability of Bob obtaining result b for input y, calculated by Alice who knows x and a;
- probability of Bob obtaining result b for input y, and
- probability of Alice obtaining result a for input x, calculated by Bob who knows y and b.
4. Contextual Inferences vs. Bell’s Hypotheses
5. Discussion
6. Conclusions
- In the above, we argue that is predictively incomplete, but not that QM is incomplete in the sense of being erroneous. There are many practical ways to complete it, by reintroducing the context either “by hand” (like in usual textbook QM) or in a more formal way using algebraic methods [17].
- The predictive incompleteness of is general, and not limited to entangled states. This is because the measurement context is required to find actual probabilities, or said otherwise, one cannot define a full consistent set of classical probabilities applicable to any result in any context. In the language of [29], provides mathematical q-probabilities without interpretation, whereas completed by the specification of the measurement context provides true probabilities for mutually exclusive events.
- In this article, we enforced (EL) at the beginning and explained how (PC) can be violated by a non-deterministic theory, without any conflict with RC. On the other hand, deterministic theories must agree with (PC), and therefore have to violate (EL) to be compatible with the observed violation of Bell’s inequalities; an example of such a theory is Bohmian mechanics. Generally speaking, if (EL) is rejected, more care must be taken in order to avoid an explicit violation of special relativity [30].
- Here, we considered the standard version of Bell’s theorem, but many other inequalities may be obtained in the general framework of “local realism”. It would be interesting to look whether the violation of such inequalities is generally due to a violation of (PC); this may be the topic for further work (see Appendix B for three-particle entanglement).
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A. Summary of the Main Arguments
- QM is a fundamentally probabilistic theory: this is a consequence of the non-commutation of observables.
- The “quantum state” (pure state or mixture ) is predictively incomplete, because by itself it does not provide a normalized probability distribution over a set of mutually exclusive events.
- From a physical point of view, or can be completed by specifying a measurement context, i.e. a macroscopic apparatus, in order to define a set of mutually exclusive events given by the apparatus outcomes.
- Once a context is given, or provides the relevant set of probabilities; this applies in any possible context, but only one at a time (predictive incompleteness).
- Nevertheless, QM allows measurements results to be predicted with certainty, either by repeating them in the same measurement context (this defines a modality), or by observing fully connected results betwen different contexts (this defines an equivalence classe of modalities, called an extravalence class).
- Associating (a mathematical object) to an extravalence class yields Born’s law from Gleason’s theorem.
- By construction, is predictively incomplete because it is associated with an extravalence class and not with a modality, and thus the context is missing.
Appendix B. Discussion of Three-Particle Entanglement
References
- Aspect, A. Closing the Door on Einstein and Bohr’s Quantum Debate. Physics 2015, 8, 123. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? Phys. Rev. 1935, 47, 777. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bohr, N. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete? Phys. Rev. 1935, 48, 696. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harrigan, N.; Spekkens, R. Einstein, Incompleteness, and the Epistemic View of Quantum States. Found. Phys. 2010, 40, 125–157. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Oldofredi, A.; López, C. On the Classification Between ψ-Ontic and ψ-Epistemic Ontological Models. Found. Phys. 2020, 50, 1315–1345. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Abramsky, S.; Brandenburger, A. The Sheaf-Theoretic Structure Of Non-Locality and Contextuality. N. J. Phys. 2011, 13, 113036. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cabello, A.; Severini, S.; Winter, A. Graph-Theoretic Approach to Quantum Correlations. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2014, 112, 040401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Acín, A.; Fritz, T.; Leverrier, A.; Sainz, A.B. A Combinatorial Approach to Nonlocality and Contextuality. Commun. Math. Phys. 2015, 334, 533–628. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dzhafarov, E.; Kujala, J.V. Probabilistic foundations of contextuality. Fort. Phys. 2016, 65, 1600040. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- D’Ariano, G.M.; Chiribella, G.; Perinotti, P. Quantum Theory from First Principles: An Informational Approach; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Okay, C.; Raussendorf, R. Homotopical approach to quantum contextuality. Quantum 2020, 4, 217. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jaynes, E.T. Clearing up Mysteries: The Original Goal. In Maximum Entropy and Bayesian Methods; Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1989; pp. 1–27. [Google Scholar]
- Jarrett, J.P. On the physical significance of the locality condition in the Bell arguments. Noûs 1984, 18, 569. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ballentine, L.E.; Jarrett, J.P. Bell’s theorem: Does quantum mechanics contradict relativity? Am. J. Phys. 1987, 55, 696. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Laloë, F. Do We Really Understand Quantum Mechanics? Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Peres, A. Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Grangier, P. Completing the quantum formalism in a contextually objective framework. Found. Phys. 2021, 51, 76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- ’t Hooft, G. Free Will in the Theory of Everything. arXiv 2017, arXiv:1709.02874. [Google Scholar]
- Bell, J.S. La Nouvelle Cuisine. In Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004; pp. 232–248. [Google Scholar]
- Clauser, J.F.; Horne, M.A. Experimental consequences of objective local theories. Phys. Rev. D 1974, 10, 526. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shimony, A. Events and processes in the quantum world. In Quantum Concepts in Space and Time; Penrose, R., Isham, C., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Grangier, P. Contextual objectivity: A realistic interpretation of quantum mechanics. Eur. J. Phys. 2002, 23, 331. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. Contexts, Systems and Modalities: A new ontology for quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 2016, 46, 121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. Violation of Bell’s inequalities in a quantum realistic framework. Int. J. Quantum Inform. 2016, 14, 1640002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. Extracontextuality and extravalence in quantum mechanics. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. A 2018, 376, 20170311. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. A generic model for quantum measurements. Entropy 2019, 21, 904. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. Deriving Born’s rule from an Inference to the Best Explanation. Found. Phys. 2020, 50, 1781–1793. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Farouki, N.; Grangier, P. The Einstein–Bohr debate: Finding a common ground of understanding? Found. Sci. 2021, 26, 97–101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Allahverdyana, A.E.; Balian, R.; Nieuwenhuizen, T.M. Understanding quantum measurement from the solution of dynamical models. Phys. Rep. 2013, 525, 1–166. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Norsen, T. Local Causality and Completeness: Bell vs. Jarrett. Found. Phys. 2009, 39, 273. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Grangier, P. Revisiting quantum mysteries. arXiv 2021, arXiv:2105.14448. [Google Scholar]
- Greenberger, D.M.; Horne, M.A.; Zeilinger, A. Bell’s Theorem, Quantum Theory and Conceptions of the Universe; Kafatos, M., Ed.; Kluwer Academic: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Pan, J.-W.; Bouwmeester, D.; Daniell, M.; Weinfurter, H.; Zeilinger, A. Experimental test of quantum nonlocality in three-photon Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger entanglement. Nature 2000, 403, 515. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Erven, C.; Meyer-Scott, E.; Fisher, K.; Lavoie, J.; Higgins, B.L.; Yan, Z.; Pugh, C.J.; Bourgoin, J.-P.; Prevedel, R.; Shalm, L.K.; et al. Experimental three-photon quantum nonlocality under strict locality conditions. Nat. Photonics 2014, 8, 292. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Mermin, N.D. Quantum mysteries revisited. Am. J. Phys. 1990, 5, 731. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mermin, N.D. Extreme quantum entanglement in a superposition of macroscopically distinct states. Phys. Rev. Lett. 1990, 65, 1838. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Grangier, P. Contextual Inferences, Nonlocality, and the Incompleteness of Quantum Mechanics. Entropy 2021, 23, 1660. https://doi.org/10.3390/e23121660
Grangier P. Contextual Inferences, Nonlocality, and the Incompleteness of Quantum Mechanics. Entropy. 2021; 23(12):1660. https://doi.org/10.3390/e23121660
Chicago/Turabian StyleGrangier, Philippe. 2021. "Contextual Inferences, Nonlocality, and the Incompleteness of Quantum Mechanics" Entropy 23, no. 12: 1660. https://doi.org/10.3390/e23121660
APA StyleGrangier, P. (2021). Contextual Inferences, Nonlocality, and the Incompleteness of Quantum Mechanics. Entropy, 23(12), 1660. https://doi.org/10.3390/e23121660