Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Herbert Butterfield: History, Providence, and Skeptical Politics
Herbert Butterfield: History, Providence, and Skeptical Politics
Herbert Butterfield: History, Providence, and Skeptical Politics
Ebook285 pages3 hours

Herbert Butterfield: History, Providence, and Skeptical Politics

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

"The most original historian of his generation." That is how the celebrated British academic Noel Annan described Herbert Butterfield (1900–1979), a profound and prolific writer who made important contributions as both a public and academic historian.

In this authoritative and accessible intellectual biography, Kenneth B. McIntyre explores the extraordinary range of Butterfield's work. He shows why the small book The Whig Interpretation of History (1931) achieved such large influence; Butterfield, he demonstrates, has profoundly shaped American and European historiography by highlighting the distortions that occur when historians interpret the past merely as steps along the way toward the glorious present.

But McIntyre delves much deeper, examining everything from Butterfield's lectures on history, historiography, and Christianity, to his warnings about the dangers of hubris in international affairs, to his essays on the origins of modern science, which basically created the modern discipline of the history of science. This latest volume in the acclaimed Library of Modern Thinkers series helps us understand a prescient and insightful thinker who challenged dominant currents in history, historiography, international relations, and politics.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateOct 3, 2023
ISBN9781684516766
Herbert Butterfield: History, Providence, and Skeptical Politics
Author

Kenneth B. McIntyre

Kenneth B. McIntyre is an assistant professor at Concordia University in Montreal, teaching political philosophy and the history of political thought. He is the author of The Limits of Political Theory: OakeshottÆs Philosophy of Civil Association and has written for a range of scholarly and popular publications.

Related to Herbert Butterfield

Related ebooks

Biography & Memoir For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for Herbert Butterfield

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Herbert Butterfield - Kenneth B. McIntyre

    Herbert Butterfield: History, Providence, and Skeptical Politics, by Kenneth B. McIntyre. The Library of Modern Thinkers.Herbert Butterfield: History, Providence, and Skeptical Politics, by Kenneth B. McIntyre. Regnery Gateway. Washington, D.C.

    CONTENTS

    Introduction

    1. The Autonomy of History

    2. The Historical Revolution and the Scientific Revolution

    3. Butterfield’s Politics: Skeptical Liberalism and International Relations

    Conclusion: Butterfield’s Legacy

    Acknowledgments

    Notes

    Bibliography

    You have reckoned that history ought to judge the past and to instruct the contemporary world as to the future. The present attempt does not yield to that high office. It will merely tell how it really was.

    —Ranke

    Use every man after his desert, and who shall ’scape whipping?

    —Shakespeare

    Introduction

    IN AN AGE OF SPECIALIZATION and secularization, Herbert Butterfield’s diverse accomplishments are as extraordinary for their resistance to these predominant cultural movements as for their insight and prescience. Butterfield achieved success as both a public intellectual and as an academic historian in a variety of fields ranging from historiography and international relations to the history of England in the eighteenth century and the history of the scientific revolution. He also maintained a sincere fidelity to the Augustinian Christianity of his upbringing.¹

    He was a committed and respected scholar whose influence over the development of modern historiography, the history of science, and the English School of international relations is widely acknowledged. His understanding of his faith informed the development of his ideas about the nature and limits of political activity at the domestic and international levels.

    While not a conventionally systematic thinker, Butterfield was a prolific and erudite writer with a penetrating intelligence and a shrewd grasp of many of the central intellectual and moral issues of his day. His essays are remarkable for their highly epigrammatic style and effortless accessibility, qualities which contributed to his reputation inside and outside of academia. He was also a notable contrarian, always questioning the conventional wisdom of the day.²

    Butterfield’s work is remarkable for its depth of insight and for its diversity and breadth.

    He is best remembered for his early historiographical essay The Whig Interpretation of History (1931), which made his name amongst academic historians and popularized the notion that the historical past is somehow distinctive or different from a merely practical account of the past. This notion that historical explanation entails a sympathetic understanding of the past in its particularity or independence from present concerns was also being given a philosophical elaboration by thinkers like R. G. Collingwood and Michael Oakeshott, but Butterfield translated the somewhat arcane language of the philosophers into a medium that has had a decisive influence on European and American historians ever since.

    His essays on the origins of modern historical explanation and on the origins of modern science basically created the modern disciplines of the history of historiography and the history of science. These investigations into the emergence of the historical and scientific consciousness profoundly influenced such contemporary thinkers as J. G. A. Pocock and Thomas Kuhn. Butterfield was one of the first contemporary thinkers to place the scientific revolution at the heart of Western modernity, and was also one of the first historians to recognize the radical novelty of modern historical experience. Isaiah Berlin traced this new way of conceiving the past in terms of its divergence from and irrelevance to the practical concerns of the present to Giambattista Vico, noting that the task of the historian [now] was not merely to establish facts and give causal explanations for them, but to examine what a situation meant to those involved in it, what their outlook was, by what rules they were guided, what ‘absolute presuppositions’ (as Collingwood called them) were entailed in what they (but not other societies, other cultures) said and did.³

    The revolution in historical consciousness brought about a new awareness of the foreignness of the past.

    In addition to his work as an academic historian, Butterfield made significant contributions to the field of international relations and his various essays on politics and the development of liberty in the modern world constitute a somewhat disparate but substantial understanding of political life. In these areas, it becomes obvious that Butterfield’s commitment to his Christian faith was not a merely factitious aspect of his life, but instead the central feature of his conception of political and moral life. Butterfield’s Augustinian emphasis on the ubiquity of sin and the importance of the individual personality led him to develop a religious version of the skeptical liberalism of his native England, and his vision of politics informed his historically sensitive conception of the international order. This skeptical liberalism provided the basis for a critique of ideological politics both domestically and internationally, and a condemnation of the dangers of hubristic or self-righteous crusading in international affairs. Indeed, Butterfield’s skeptical liberalism offers a compelling alternative to a contemporary political world defined primarily by its Manichean distinctions and its quasi-religious conflicts.

    Herbert Butterfield was born on October 7, 1900, in Yorkshire, England.

    He was the son of devout working-class Methodists. His father, who had once aspired to be a Methodist minister, left school early upon the death of Butterfield’s grandfather and worked at a local wool factory, eventually becoming chief clerk in the firm. From a young age, Butterfield entertained thoughts of becoming a minister himself, and in fact eventually became a lay minister in the Methodist church, preaching in his native Yorkshire and at Cambridge. He attended the local grammar school at Keighley before matriculating at Cambridge University as a scholarship student.

    At Cambridge, he was a student at Peterhouse College, which was notable for its strength in history. Sir Adolphus Ward, one of the editors of the first Cambridge Modern History, was the Master of Peterhouse at the time, and Harold Temperley, a noted diplomatic historian who became Butterfield’s intellectual mentor, was a fellow there when Butterfield matriculated. Butterfield graduated with a double first in history and won several academic prizes along the way. He was subsequently elected a Fellow of Peterhouse, and would remain affiliated with the college in some way for the rest of his life.

    His first work of academic history, The Peace Tactics of Napoleon, 1806–8, was published in 1928. It manifested the influence of Temperley and is a model of what Butterfield would subsequently call technical history. In that same year, he married Edith Joyce Crawshaw, with whom he would have three sons. Crawshaw was the daughter of a Methodist minister, and the sister of one of Butterfield’s friends. Her interests were more artistic than historical, though she did assist in proofreading his work and preparing it for publication. In 1931, The Whig Interpretation of History, the book that would become most closely associated with his name, was published to mixed reviews. Although Butterfield was still a very young man, he had written a defense of the autonomy of history which would become a central text in the historiography of the twentieth century.

    At the end of the decade and in the dark years preceding World War II, he wrote a short biography of Napoleon which was published in 1939 and a brief examination of the political and historical ideas of Machiavelli entitled The Statecraft of Machiavelli (1940). Both of these works contain a subtle message concerning the dangers of modern revolutionary politics. This message was more explicitly affirmed in The Englishman and His History (1944), in which Butterfield, while maintaining his critical stance toward Whig historians, offered a celebration of the Whig political tradition of ordered liberty. In 1944, Butterfield was named professor of modern history at Cambridge.

    In October 1949, in a burst of prolificness, Butterfield came out with three books: George III, Lord North, and the People, 1779–80; The Origins of Modern Science, 1300–1800; and Christianity and History. The first was Butterfield’s second and last major work of technical history and focused on a series of crises which challenged the traditional character of British politics in the eighteenth century and provided a glimpse of the kind of mass politics more closely associated with the French Revolution and the rise of nationalism in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The second was based upon lectures which Butterfield originally offered at Cambridge under the auspices of its Committee on the History of Science. The book made the significant claim, which has been widely accepted, that the scientific revolution, not the Renaissance or Reformation, should be considered the true beginning of the modern world. The book also made a substantial contribution to the creation of the history of science as a field of study. The third book, Christianity and History, was based upon lectures which Butterfield originally offered at Cambridge and which were broadcast by the BBC. Their tremendous popularity made Butterfield a public figure. In them, Butterfield elaborated a distinction between technical or academic history and prophetic history which would become central to his political work, while defending a specifically Christian conception of the human past and of the singular importance of human personality.

    In 1951, a collection of Butterfield’s essays entitled History and Human Relations was published and The Whig Interpretation of History was reissued. These works cemented Butterfield’s reputation as the preeminent historiographer of his day, while further burnishing his credentials as a Christian voice in public affairs. In 1953, Christianity, Diplomacy, and War, Butterfield’s first extended foray into international relations, was published. Butterfield offered a defense of Augustinian skepticism in international relations while making a critique of ideology and the self-righteous style of politics that ideology entails. The book attracted the attention and approbation of Reinhold Niebuhr and Hans Morgenthau, and eventually led to the creation of the British Committee on the Theory of International Relations (BCTIR), which Butterfield chaired.

    Butterfield was elected the master of Peterhouse College in 1955. In the same year, Man on His Past, his influential Wiles Lectures on the history of historiography, was published. In it, Butterfield made claims concerning the novelty and significance of the emergence of historical consciousness in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries which were similar to the ones he made about the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century. According to Butterfield, these two revolutions in consciousness are the primary intellectual achievements of the modern age. Like his earlier contribution to the history of science, Butterfield’s book played a central role in the development of the history of historiography in the twentieth century.

    In 1958, with funding from the Rockefeller Foundation and with the help of Martin Wight, Butterfield founded the BCTIR. The committee was the fons et origo of the English School of International Relations, which has emphasized the importance of the notion of international order while offering compelling critiques of the one-sidedness of traditional Hobbesian realism and revolutionary Kantian idealism in international relations. While chairman of the BCTIR, Butterfield wrote International Conflict in the Twentieth Century and coedited Diplomatic Investigations with Martin Wight. During this period, he also served as vice chancellor of Cambridge University, the highest administrative office in the university, from 1959 to 1961.

    Butterfield was named Regius Professor of History at Cambridge in 1963 and delivered the Gifford Lectures at Glasgow University in 1965 and 1966. The lectures would be posthumously published in 1981 as The Origins of History. In the lectures and the book, Butterfield examined the great variety of ways in which civilizations have conceived the past, while focusing on the specific interest in the past which developed in Western civilization as a result of the peculiar concatenation of Greek philosophy, Christian theology, and modern science. Butterfield was knighted in July 1968, and retired from the academy later that same year. He died on July 20, 1979, in Sawston, Cambridgeshire, where he had moved after his retirement.

    Despite his working-class background, Butterfield lived the life of an English don and reveled in the peculiar eccentricities associated with such a life. Maurice Cowling notes that he was modest and tolerant, was free of arrogance, and disliked the entrenched prescriptions of the progressive intellect. He felt a deep and irrational regard for rakes whom he much preferred to the ‘virtuous and stiff-necked.’

    He had a marked streak of contrarianism, and in spite of being a lifelong teetotaler otherwise, he took up drinking during a fellowship year at Princeton in order to protest against the foolishness of prohibition.

    He was also a constant smoker and was known to be somewhat careless of his appearance, at least until he began to hold administrative positions of some significance at Peterhouse and Cambridge. He was short of stature and had a slight build, but he was not an unattractive person. Cowling suggests that Butterfield combin[ed] a Shelleyesque beauty of feature with a great deal of hair and a certain tense volatility with a modestly attractive decisiveness of manner.

    He was proud of his background, but he was often self-conscious about the Yorkshire accent which he retained throughout his life.

    Butterfield was not only an extraordinarily prolific and successful historian and political thinker, but also an influential administrator during a time of tremendous upheaval at British universities. While his administrative talents were widely applauded, he was also noted as a man with a cynical streak who enjoyed academic politics in an almost unseemly way. Noel Annan, who describes Butterfield as the most original historian of his generation, also observes that nothing pleased Butterfield more than plotting: he enjoyed academic intrigue.

    Butterfield’s life, like so many lives in the modern age, was marked by a complexity that belies the facile reductionism of conventional biography. He combined an impish contrarianism and an almost puritanical devotion to academic history with a sincere and wholly admirable devotion to his family and to his faith.

    In this book, I offer an introduction to the work of Herbert Butterfield. Although the work is primarily expository, I will also offer a critical appraisal of the significance of Butterfield’s work. The first chapter is devoted to an analysis of Butterfield’s conception of the logic of historical explanation and his defense of the autonomy of history. The second chapter focuses on Butterfield’s pioneering work in the history of historiography and the history of science, and concludes with an examination of Butterfield’s debate with Lewis Namier concerning the nature of historical understanding. The third chapter deals with Butterfield’s skeptical liberalism and his understanding of international order. I conclude with a brief assessment of the significance of Butterfield’s work and its relevance to contemporary questions, both academic and practical.

    CHAPTER ONE

    THE AUTONOMY OF HISTORY

    HERBERT BUTTERFIELD CAME TO PUBLIC prominence as the writer of a short book on historiography entitled The Whig Interpretation of History. Like Christianity and History and History and Human Relations, his other works on historiography, The Whig Interpretation of History consists of an unsystematic and sometimes uneven series of essays about some of the difficulties associated with historical research and explanation. Despite its somewhat haphazard character, the book exhibits a subtle and intuitive grasp of the fundamental issues in the field, and manifests the insightful and epigrammatic style characteristic of Butterfield’s writings on every subject. All of his historiographical work is animated by a consistent defense of the autonomous character of historical investigation and explanation. Though his later works also explore the nature of an explicitly Christian interpretation of the past, Butterfield consistently maintains the clear distinction that he made initially in The Whig Interpretation of History between the kind of explanation proper to what he terms on different occasions technical, academic, or scientific history, and the practical or prophetic impulse which informs the Christian reading of past events. This distinction is the key to Butterfield’s significance as a historiographer. His signal achievements in his historiographical essays are his elucidation and confirmation of the importance of the autonomy of historical explanation and his clarification of the necessity of that autonomy to objective historical scholarship.¹

    The autonomy of historical explanation lies, on the one hand, in its emancipation from the domination of practical, political, or religious concerns, and, on the other, in its development of both unique methods of investigation and of a specific logic of explanation distinguishing itself from the logic and methods of the natural sciences. The lasting significance of his work can be seen in the work of contemporary intellectual historians like Quentin Skinner, J. G. A. Pocock, et al., who continue to posit the same methodological prescriptions, whether they attribute them to Butterfield or not.

    I.

    According to the conventional interpretation of Butterfield’s work, there is an unresolved tension between his insistence upon the disciplinary and logical autonomy of what he calls technical history and his commitment to a practical Christian interpretation of the past.²

    The tension manifests itself in two different ways. First, many note that Butterfield’s historical work often displays the weaknesses associated with what he calls the Whig interpretation of history. That is, he sometimes seems to read the past in terms of its contribution to a desired present state of affairs instead of conceiving the past in its independence from contemporary practical concerns. For instance, in The Englishman and His History, Butterfield writes that the past, like the spent part of a cinematograph film, is coiled up inside the present… [A]part from any action we may take in some present conjuncture, the world is changing, and history is moving forward on her own account; and we ourselves must reckon with this process and use it—must conceive of ourselves as cooperating with history,… lying in wait for opportunity.³

    One of Butterfield’s most prominent protégés, J. G. A. Pocock, has jocularly referred to this as Das Herbert Butterfield Problem.

    However, the mere appearance of inconsistency between his historical works and his historiographical essays does not necessarily undermine the validity of Butterfield’s account of technical history. After all, his defense of the autonomy of history rests on the internal coherence of its argument and its effectiveness as a description of the logic of historical practice, not on the pragmatic display of its effects or on the demonstration of his own perfect adherence to its methodological strictures.

    A more important manifestation of the tension emerges within the later historiographical essays. In Christianity and History and History and Human Relations, Butterfield continues to hold that technical or academic history is an autonomous and independent kind of explanation, but introduces his own Christian version of the past as an equally valid and ultimately more complete conception of the human past. The logic of the connection between technical history and Christian or providential history is never made completely clear by Butterfield, and thus many writers have concluded that the tension between the two conceptions of the past undermines the coherence of his historiographical work. C. T. McIntire, who has written an extraordinarily comprehensive and well-argued intellectual biography of the man, argues that the tension between Butterfield the historian, who posits a categorical distinction between technical history and the providential past, and Butterfield the Christian, who posits a world unified and reconciled by the Christian faith, cannot be adequately resolved.

    This reading of Butterfield, which reflects a conception of the modern world as marked by the fragmentation of human consciousness, echoes the claims of philosophers like R. G. Collingwood and H. G. Gadamer, who both suggest that the disintegration of human consciousness which is characteristic of the modern experience of the world is a theoretically incoherent and spiritually debilitating kind of experience which must be overcome by a kind of Hegelian sublation of differences.

    For Collingwood and Gadamer, this sublation would create a practical and philosophical unity which respects the inherent historicity of human beings.

    However, the fact that Butterfield never appears to be aware of the tension between technical history and Christian history suggests that he does not believe that the tension between them is real

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1