Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu
This art icle was downloaded by: [ Vrij e Universit eit Am st erdam ] On: 13 July 2012, At : 03: 53 Publisher: Rout ledge I nform a Lt d Regist ered in England and Wales Regist ered Num ber: 1072954 Regist ered office: Mort im er House, 37- 41 Mort im er St reet , London W1T 3JH, UK Sport, Ethics and Philosophy Publicat ion det ails, including inst ruct ions f or aut hors and subscript ion inf ormat ion: ht t p: / / www. t andf online. com/ loi/ rsep20 Disability or Extraordinary Talent—Francesco Lentini (Three Legs) Versus Oscar Pistorius (No Legs) Ivo van Hilvoorde & Laurens Landeweerd Version of record f irst published: 18 Jul 2008 To cite this article: Ivo van Hilvoorde & Laurens Landeweerd (2008): Disabilit y or Ext raordinary Talent —Francesco Lent ini (Three Legs) Versus Oscar Pist orius (No Legs), Sport , Et hics and Philosophy, 2: 2, 97-111 To link to this article: ht t p: / / dx. doi. org/ 10. 1080/ 17511320802221778 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTI CLE Full t erm s and condit ions of use: ht t p: / / www.t andfonline.com / page/ t erm s- andcondit ions This art icle m ay be used for research, t eaching, and privat e st udy purposes. Any subst ant ial or syst em at ic reproduct ion, redist ribut ion, reselling, loan, sub- licensing, syst em at ic supply, or dist ribut ion in any form t o anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warrant y express or im plied or m ake any represent at ion t hat t he cont ent s will be com plet e or accurat e or up t o dat e. The accuracy of any inst ruct ions, form ulae, and drug doses should be independent ly verified wit h prim ary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, act ions, claim s, proceedings, dem and, or cost s or dam ages what soever or howsoever caused arising direct ly or indirect ly in connect ion wit h or arising out of t he use of t his m at erial. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, Vol. 2, No. 2, August 2008 DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT— FRANCESCO LENTINI (THREE LEGS) VERSUS OSCAR PISTORIUS (NO LEGS) Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 Ivo van Hilvoorde and Laurens Landeweerd It seems fairly straightforward to describe what should and should not count as a disability into two separate and opposing categories. In this paper we will challenge this assumption and critically reflect on the narrow relations between the concepts of ‘talent’ and ‘disability’. We further relate such matters of terminology and classification to issues of justice in what is conceived of as disability sport. Do current systems of classification do justice to the performances of disabled athletes? Is the organisation of a just and fair competition similar for abled as it is for disabled sport? Two cases (of Francesco Lentini and Oscar Pistorius) will be explored to further illustrate the complexities of these questions, in particular when related to notions of normality and extraordinary performances. Resumen Parece un asunto bastante simple el describir lo que deberı́a y no deberı́a contar como discapacidad en dos categorı́as distintas y opuestas. En este artı́culo desafiaremos esta suposición y reflejaremos crı́ticamente sobre las estrechas relaciones que hay entre los conceptos de ‘talento’ y ‘incapacidad.’ Además conectamos tales asuntos de terminologı́a y clasificación con asuntos de justicia en lo que se entiende como deporte discapacitado. ¿Hacen justicia estas maneras actuales de clasificación a las actuaciones de los atletas minusválidos? ¿Es la organización de una competición justa parecida para el deporte con y sin discapacidad? Dos casos (el de Francesco Lentini y el de Oscar Pistorius) seran explorados para ilustrar mejor las complejidades de estas cuestiones, en particular cuando se las relaciona con nociones de normalidad y actuaciones extraordinarias. Zusammenfassung Die Unterteilung von Behinderung und Nicht-Behinderung in zwei getrennte gegensätzliche Kategorien erscheint etwas zu vereinfachend zu sein. In unserem Artikel wollen wir diese Unterteilung infrage stellen und kritische Reflexionen zur engen Verbindung der Begriffe ,Talent’ und ,Behinderung’ anbringen. Des Weiteren wollen wir derartige terminologische Aspekte sowie Probleme der Klassifikation mit Fragen nach Gerechtigkeit im sogenannten Behindertensport in Verbindung bringen. Ist die gegenwärtige Leitungsklassen-Einteilung behinderter Athleten gerecht? Ist die Organisation gerechter und fairer Wettkämpfe Nicht-Behinderter mit derjenigen ISSN 1751-1321 print/1751-133X online/08/020097–15 ª 2008 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/17511320802221778 98 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 für Behinderte vergleichbar? Zur Veranschaulichung der Komplexität dieser Fragen werden zwei Fallbeispiele (Francesco Lentini und Oscar Pistorius) herangezogen, insbesondere in Bezug auf Begriffe wie Normalität und besondere Leistung. KEYWORDS disability; super-ability; definition and ethics of (disability) sports; naturalness; artificiality; enhancement; prostheses; Lentini; Pistorius Introduction The highly talented and the disabled person seem, at first sight, to be living in completely different worlds. Gifted persons will be celebrated because of their culturally valued talents and may enjoy a lifetime of social advantages as a result. But instead of being praised for their deviation, a disabled person may need to adapt to a world that is primarily built around standards of normality and even experience a lifetime characterised by stigmatising and discrimination. Therefore, there seems to be a sharp contrast between the athlete as a cultural hero and icon and the disabled person that needs extra attention or care; the one incorporating the peak of normality, human functioning at its best, the other often representing the opposite. The concepts of ‘talent’ and ‘handicap’, however, bear certain family resemblances. Both concepts of dis-ability and super-ability are based upon deviations from standards of normality. Disabilities are seen as a dysfunctional deviations from normality. The division between the dysfunctional and the healthy is often built from a bio-statistical notion of normal functioning. Though a dysfunction can also be the result of an accident, these deviations are in many cases the result of genetic inheritance and mutations. In the literature there is an extended discussion on how to distinguish between impairment, disability and handicap, a classical categorisation (cf. Sherill 2004a; Ustun 2004). The semantic jungle that followed from this discussion still obstructs clear debates on disability rights and public duties. We will try to avoid touching upon this jungle by merely using the term disability as a generic term. Athletes with a disability are classified within the following disability categories (cf. Tweedy 2002; IPC 2006; Kioumourtzoglou and Politis 2004; Klenck and Gebke 2007; DePauw and Gavron 2005): . Wheelchair athletes; . Athletes with cerebral palsy; DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 . . . . Amputees; Athletes with total or partial loss of sight; Athletes with intellectual disability and learning difficulties; and ‘Les autres’ disabilities (a complex ‘all the rest category’) Both the concept of ‘sport’ and ‘disability’ have their own specific distinctions and internal differentiations, such that a combination of both gives rise to all sorts of complexities and new issues, in particular regarding definition and fairness. The distinction between different disabilities listed above is only relevant for disability sports. There is no medical categorisation of disabilities that fits smoothly and logically into the context of sport. What is considered a disability in ‘regular life’ may even become an advantage in the context of elite sports. In basketball, extreme height is considered to be an advantage rather than a disability, while possibly posing a disability, albeit slight, in daily life. A huge sumo wrestler may have problems travelling on a bus, but at the same time be celebrated as a Japanese sport hero. A genetic mutation that corresponds to extreme muscle growth can be classified in one case as a high-risk potential for disablement and in another as a precondition of being exceptionally talented. It appears that in many ways the scales on which one ranks human traits are not value-neutral, or are at least established from a very specific (albeit hidden) perspective. This poses the question whether one can neutrally or objectively define what should count as a disability (or impairment), what as a trait within a normal variance and what as a super-ability. Several authors have shed light on the philosophical dimensions of classification, categorisation, merit and justice related to disability sports (cf. Bowen 2002; Wheeler 2004; Pickering 2005; Jones and Howe 2005). Categorisation and classification are ongoing processes and discussions need to be continued, not least because our views on disabilities change and evolve, as does the technology to compensate for certain disabilities. From an egalitarian perspective one can strive for the neutralisation of luck and reward specific talents (cf. Bailey 2007). On the other hand, specific distinctions between (severity of) disabilities can be drawn in such a way that extreme efforts are awarded in order to compensate for a lack of talent. Categorisations within disability sports appear to be the site of an ‘ongoing struggle’ to find the right balance between a good competition based on differences in talent on the one hand and the demonstration of excellence within a group with relevant similar skills on the other. We will try to show that this tension eventually also bears relevance for the distinction between elite sports and disability sports. Defining Disability: Normative or Neutral The concept of disease and disability was heavily debated in the 1970s and 1980s by Christopher Boorse (1975, 1976, 1977) and H. Tristam Engelhardt and S.F. Spicker (1974). Boorse looked upon the difference between health and diseases as a natural given, basing his stance on a statistically derived definition of normal and abnormal function. Health was therefore defined as ‘the ability to perform all typical physiological functions with at least typical efficiency level’ (Boorse 1977, 542). Correspondingly, disease is any state that interferes with this normal functioning. In Boorse’s words: An organism is healthy at any moment in proportion as it is not diseased; and a disease is a type of internal state of the organism which (i) interferes with the performance of some 99 100 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 natural function—i.e., some species-typical contribution to survival and reproduction— characteristic of the organism’s age; and (ii) is not simply in the nature of the species, i.e., is either atypical of the species or, if typical, mainly due to environmental causes. (Boorse 1976, 62) This means that Boorse’s account of the concepts of health and disease is heavily dependent of an objective image of ‘nature’, ‘natural’ or ‘normal functioning’. Among others, Tristam Engelhardt criticises this naturalist approach to the conceptualisation of diseases. In his opinion, one cannot analyse concepts of health and disease solely on the basis of the biological nature of the organism and its functioning. The social context needs to be taken into account as well. In this normative approach diseases are normative constructions with a specific socio-cultural background, rather than natural givens within a bio-statistical framework. In the words of Toulmin, supporting Engelhardt’s view, The nature of health is, at one and the same time, a matter for empirical discovery and a matter of evaluative decision. We refine our sense of how the human body ought to work, and ought to be helped to work, in the course of and in the light of our empirical studies of how it does in fact work. (Toulmin 1975, 51) So, according to the normativists, what counts as a disability and what not is as much dependent on socio-cultural values and decisions as on medical standards. Essentially, within this perspective, the latter are even to be seen as a subcategory of the former. The discussion between the bio-statistical and the normative or contextual definition of diseases and disabilities has continued up to now. As has been put forward by Moser (2006, 374), ‘Being disabled is not something one is by definition, but something one becomes in relation to specific environments. Disability is enacted and ordered in situated and quite specific ways.’ People can become disabled by the environment or by specific (lack of) technologies. A person with an average intellectual ability may ‘become’ disabled in an environment with just highly gifted people. An elite athlete who chooses not to use performance-enhancing substances may become dis-abled in a context in which the use of doping is ‘normalised’. In these cases (and in many similar cases) one can argue that one is free to choose the ‘right’ environment in which specific qualities can be shown and compared to ‘relevant others’. The person that one wants to be cannot be detached from the financial rewards that are attached to specific practices, as well as the status and meanings that are intrinsically related to the community of superior athletic performances. The valuation of human performances cannot be effected irrespective of a social-cultural hierarchy, ranking specific talents and making differences between highly valued talents (e.g. the ability to throw a ball in a basket) and less valued talents (e.g. running on prostheses). New technologies such as prostheses apparently help to turn disabled people into ‘normal’ subjects. This may explain the urgent wish of Oscar Pistorius, an athlete who usually competes in races for disabled athletes, to become part of the ‘normal Olympic Games’. What may be considered ‘normalisation’ in the context of daily life is at least ambivalent in the context of elite sport. Running on prostheses may be defined as crucial for the specific talent that is tested in a competition against ‘relevant others’: athletes who have the ability to show a similar talent. The wish of a disabled person to become part of ‘normal’ elite sport may be framed as a way of ‘inclusion’ or ‘integration’, but this at the Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? same time reproduces new inequalities and asymmetries between performances of able and dis-abled bodied. If one is to enhance the traits needed to function optimally in society, one takes that society as a universal standard against which the functioning of people is measured, while one could also say that within a just society people should not be made to follow the dictations of a larger ideal. When one defines what counts as a disability in a normative rather than a descriptive fashion the notion of a disability also becomes political. In contemporary (Western) democracies, each citizen is presupposed to be self-reliant within a competitive capitalist environment. Therefore, society is set up to deal primarily with an idealised version of the ‘average person’ (Taylor and Mykitiuk 2001, 1). Anything that falls below this picture of the ideal citizen is treated as abnormal. In many respects, however, the ideal of the elite sportsman has all characteristics of abnormality as well. But in contrast to the disabled, the elite sportsman is not considered a political and medical burden. So on the one hand society invests quite willingly in the ‘abnormal’ super-abilities of the elite sportsman, while on the other it does this only reluctantly, and from a ethics of inclusion, with respect to the disabled. In the case of disabilities, one wants to eradicate abnormalities by equalising on the basis of ‘sameness’ (Taylor and Mykitiuk 2001, 1), while in the case of super-abilities we support abnormalities. This ‘selective investment in the abnormal’ and the admiration for the ‘genetically superior’ could be seen as a token of a society that cannot meet up with the criteria for justice (cf. Tännsjö 2000). On the other hand, sport is a competitive practice, whose internal logic consists of the display of an unequal distribution of abilities. These internal goods are considered worth striving for, for their own sake (cf. MacIntyre 1985; Brown 1990; McNamee 1995). Sport consists of an internal logic that may conflict with more societal ideals (for example concerning justice or equality). These internal goods cannot be brought in agreement with the ideal, for example, to create as many sport categories as possible with the aim of producing as many sport stars as possible. It may be that everyone has certain abilities and disabilities; we cannot however freely choose the practice in which our own specific abilities are admired by people around the world. Rawls and a Just Distribution of Disabilities In the 1970s, Rawls, among others, gave rise to a revival of liberal political philosophy. Next to his general influence on political and ethical philosophy, Rawls also had an extensive influence on bioethics and sport ethics. Rawls most important contribution to juridical and political philosophy was his publication in 1971 of a Theory of Justice. In a Theory of Justice, John Rawls set out to find a more rational basis for the contractualist tradition in political and ethical theory. He tried to find general principles of justice that would function as basic rules for justice in society. These principles would, as is typical for contractualism, be supported by a social agreement. However, Rawls combined this with a stronger notion of justice which he derived from Kantian philosophy, and with the utilitarian notion of costs and benefit calculus to find the best overall balance for individual and collective well-being or happiness. Rational agreement was to be the basis of this philosophical system. For Rawls, principles of justice are the principles that free and rational persons concerned to further their own interests would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the fundamental terms of their 101 102 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 association. These principles are to regulate all further agreements; they specify the kinds of social cooperation that can be entered into and the forms of government that can be established. (Rawls 1971, 11) So, in Rawlsian philosophy, the basic principles of justice should balance individual liberty with an equal distribution of liberty. This should be combined with a provision of the greatest benefit for the least advantaged. People should come to this agreement through rational reflection, unaware of their specific individual place, talents or background in society. This is what Rawls called ‘original position’. Rawls’s conception of an ‘original position’ forms the rationale behind these basic principles of justice. It stems from the contractarian tradition in political theory. The original position was usually posed as the beginning position from which the social contract was formulated, from within a ‘state of nature’. In Rawls’s work, this construction of an original position should be regarded as a hypothetical position rather than a true historical occurrence. It functions as a maxim rule; it is the basic position one should take to come to the principles for a just society. In Rawls’s original position, one is supposed to wear a ‘veil of ignorance’. With this construction, Rawls tried to find a tool that can balance freedom or liberty and equality and leave out any prejudices stemming from one’s class or one’s ethnic, linguistic, religious or cultural background. In Rawls’s vision, those who are at the same level of talent and ability, and have the same willingness to use them, should have the same prospects of success regardless of their initial place in the social system. Social class, gender or any other contingency should have no influence on the liberty individuals are to enjoy in the pursuance of his or her goals in life. Moreover, social and economic inequalities should be distributed in such a way that they can reasonably be expected to be advantageous to all those who are the worst off in the first place. Rawls aimed at a distributive justice to compensate for the differences in fortune that we come across. Justice is seen as being independent of luck and favouring more equal distribution. This position, although dominant in our current theoretical framework of justice, is on a par with the notions of both talent and disability. Our world is primarily designed for the average human being. People with a disability cannot partake in it as fully as they should according to the principles of distributive justice. By redesigning the world around us, however, we can make this world more accessible for the disabled. The question remains what obstacles can and should be taken away in order for the disabled to become part of other spheres of life. Making a building accessible is not the same thing as trying to become (a successful) part of one of the most competitive practices on earth. Following Rawls, we should adjust the person rather than the environment. Therefore, a defence of plurality is often not the outcome of a Rawlsian approach to justice. Our dominant understanding of elite sport cannot be brought in agreement with the right to become an elite athlete, similar to the right for example to receive good education. It may be difficult to justify the difference in admiration for the elite athlete and the disabled athlete just based upon concepts as ‘talent’ or ‘effort’. Some talents are more valued in a society than others in spite of a (changing) terminology, one that sometimes even seems to suggest that being disabled is the norm for each human being. DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 Adaptation of terminology The inclusion of people with disabilities within regular sport and physical education has become daily practice in many countries (cf. Doll-Tepper et al. 2001; Vanlandewijck and Chappel 1996; Block and Obrusnikova 2007). The aims of participation and inclusion have also influenced debates about terminology and disability sports. This issue of terminology and language is important when it comes to matters of categorisation, and also with regard to the distinction between elite sport and disability sport. How does this categorisation, between sport for the ‘normal’ and sport for the disabled, in itself contribute to our understanding of what is and what should be considered ‘ab-normal’? What equalities and what inequalities are considered justified in our society and in what way does the internal logic of sports challenges the understanding of justice in relation to matters of inclusion and exclusion? In able to deal with these questions we will have to go back to some of the debates on terminology and classification. In 1980, the World Health Organisation introduced the International Classification of Impairments, Disabilities and Handicaps (ICIDH). It was followed by years of dispute about the medical and social model of disabilities. This dispute finally resulted in the presentation of the International Classification of Functioning, Disability and Health (ICF) in 2001. Within this new model, disability is not regarded a characteristic (that is present all the time) but a state that may be present in certain environments or resulting from specific interactions with other people (cf. Ustun 2004). Following this new terminological proposal all people possess a multitude of abilities and disabilities. Sherill (2004b, 9) optimistically writes about this change of terminology: ‘The worldwide trend is on appreciating, embracing and celebrating individual differences as opposed to glorifying the norm, the normal, and normalisation as was done in the 1900s.’ Since everyone has disabilities and abilities, there is no need to make a rigid distinction between abled and dis-abled bodies. ‘Being disabled is the norm for humanity’ (Ustun 2004, 1). In this sense, the Paralympics is understood as ‘parallel Olympics’, not special nor separate or inferior. The change of terminology can not hide the huge difference in status attached to winning a medal as an able-bodied or a disabled athlete. This difference very clearly explains the ultimate wish for a disabled athlete to become part of the competition for elite athletes. With two cases we ask if certain limits to normalisation and inclusion may conflict with ‘a distribution of resources’. Having three legs or no legs does not, in and of itself, necessarily entail being disabled. In relation to sport it does however raise questions regarding which inequalities are ‘relevant inequalities’ based upon the internal logic of sport. It also presents us with an example of the reproduction of normality through sports. Although sport and the circus have very similar historical roots, elite sport in the twentieth century has differentiated from the early ‘freak shows’. Nowadays it celebrates the ultimate, but at the same time normalised, two-legged human abilities and performances. Even in elite sport ‘more’ is not necessarily ‘better’, as can be illustrated by the story of Franceso Lentini, the ‘three legged football player’. Lentini: Super- or Dis-abled? Francesco Lentini (1889–1966) was born in Sicily in Italy with three legs, and a rudimentary foot growing on one of his legs. As a child he was brought to a home for disabled children. Initially, Lentini experienced his impairment as a disability (mainly 103 104 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD because his third leg was six inches shorter than the two other legs). After being brought into this home of disabled children (with children who were deaf, blind or mute) he found out for himself that he was not disabled at all. Lentini writes about his childhood ‘transformation’: Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 I could appreciate the fact that I was possessed of all my faculties and senses. I could hear, talk, understand, appreciate and enjoy the beauties of life. I could read and they couldn’t. I could talk to my friends, but some of them couldn’t because they were dumb. I could hear and enjoy beautiful music, while some of them couldn’t because they were deaf. I had my mental faculties and began to look forward to my education, and some of them couldn’t because they were idiots. (Nickell 2005, 131–2) Lentini learned to use his ‘disability’ as an advantage. He entered the circus in the USA as a young child. One of his acts was playing soccer on a stage, which explains his show name: the ‘Three-Legged Football Player’. How fair it would have been if Lentini would have entered a regular soccer competition is purely hypothetical, since he was only acting in the circus, and his third leg would have given him a disadvantage over his opponents rather than an advantage. More interesting in this respect would be the case of swimming. Lentini talks about this advantage: No, my limb does not bother me in the least. I can get about just as well and with the same ease as any normal person—walk, run, jump; ride a bicycle, horse; ice and roller skate; and drive my own car. I can swim—one advantage I have over the other fellow when I swim is that I use the extra limb as a rudder.1 There is a clear difference between a performance in the circus and elite sport, and between the performances of able (two-legged) and disabled (three-legged) athletes. This difference can however not be inferred from a definition of ‘the normal’. Modern elite sport celebrates abnormalities in many shapes and appearances, varying from extremesized sumo wrestlers to extremely undersized gymnasts. What is considered a sport performance or a circus performance has to be primarily understood from the historical and cultural context. Yet comparing them does raise some interesting issues regarding the definition of being disabled, the ‘boundaries of normality’ and the manner in which modern, competitive sports may challenge some of the accepted categories and definitions. Having three legs may become a disability in a world where two legs presents the dominant norm, similar to Lentini’s observation: ‘If you lived in a world where everyone had one arm, how would you cope with two?’ In the case of Lentini, uniqueness is not a reason for admiration, just because of the deviation from the standard (as is the case in elite sport). Admiration and heroism is afforded on the basis of a multitude of factors including training, discipline, showing and mastering certain skills. Differences between elite sport as a global entertainment industry and the circus are related to conceptual differences between ‘admiration’ and ‘amazement’. One can be amazed by looking at ‘physical abnormalities’, but this amazement may turn into admiration when an ‘extraordinary feature’ is mastered and turns out to be an extraordinary sport talent. Without the prospect for the kind of heroism that is attached to modern elite sport, large deviations from the standards of being ‘normal’ may still end up in a circus. It is Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? interesting to see that, although many acts in the circus are the result of years of hard and vigorous training, these performances are still very much associated with the historical roots of the freak show, or any other public place for the ‘unlucky mutants’ exposing or trading upon their abnormalities. Elite sport and the circus have similar roots, based upon the celebration of extraordinary talent. European countries share a similar history in the knowledge and popularisation of physical culture, thanks to the circuses, the acrobats, the pioneering bodybuilders and other body artists who travelled through Europe. In the late eighteenth century, people already watched strongmen and other athletes performing at fairs, festivals and in all kinds of theatres. Long before the idea of training and building muscle mass became a ‘normalised’ kind of behaviour, people saw extraordinarily strong men (and children) primarily as ‘miracles of nature’. Until around 1850, it is hard to draw clear distinctions between sport, acrobatics and circus-like activities. Thanks to the globalisation of modern sport, many ‘mutants’ are nowadays cheered for their achievements. They set a norm for human performance and virtuosity to be strived for also by elite athletes in disability sports. The classical distinction between elite sports and the disabled athlete is blurring, as well as the distinction between the athlete as hero, excelling on the basis of what counts as ‘normal’, and a (former) ‘patient combating his limitations’, falling outside this normal variance. In this respect, modern disability sports have made much progress in terms of admiration and respect. Nowadays, some so-called ‘disabled’ performances sometimes even come close to those of elite athletes. It raises the question of what counts as normal in order to become part of the competition for ablebodied athletes. How much of a disablement can and should be compensated for in order to be (re)defined as a ‘normal athlete’? Oscar Pistorius: Super- or Disabled? South African Oscar Pistorius is known as ‘the fastest man on no legs’. He runs with artificial limbs and is world record holder in the 100, 200 and 400 metres. He runs that fast thanks partly to his carbon-fibre legs. He can even compete with elite athletes on ‘natural legs’. In fact, he did so in July 2007, when he ran a 400-metre race at the British Grand Prix. His participation in a regular competition is, however, surrounded by controversy. His artificial limbs (also called ‘cheetahs’) may give him extra advantages which, as some argue, makes the running competition unfair. Pistorius is not the first disabled person competing in an able-bodied event. In most historical cases there was no reason for concern about the justification of the participation of disabled athletes. In the 1904 St Louis Olympics, George Eyser won three gold medals in gymnastics while competing on a wooden leg. Neroli Fairhall, a paraplegic, competed in archery in the 1984 Olympics, and in 2000 blind runner Marla Runyan raced against ablebodied runners in the 1,500 metres athletics competition. Ajibola Adeoye (Nigeria) is an arm amputee who holds the Paralympic record in the men’s 100 metres (10.72 seconds). If his time would allow it, there is little reason why he couldn’t compete in the regular Olympics. The loss of one of his arms does affect his ability to run, but not in such a way that it causes concern about the fairness of the competition. These examples illustrate that unless their disadvantage is a certain disability people can still compete in regular competition. In these cases, no use is made of any prosthetic that influences the athletic performance, at least not in such a way that it raises concern about the fairness of the competition. 105 106 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 The case of Pistorius is rather special, because his disability may, with the help of his prostheses, turn out to be an unfair advantage. This is why the IAAF amended its competition rules in 2007, banning the use of ‘any technical device that incorporates springs, wheels or any other element that provides a user with an advantage over another athlete not using such a device’ (IAAF Rule 144.2). IAAF spokesman Nick Davies commented after the British Grand Prix, ‘We all wish him [Pistorius] well. The point here is what’s going to happen in ten years? What happens if it continues to evolve?’ In November 2007 the IAAF asked the Institute of Biomechanics and Orthopaedics (German Sport University, Cologne) for an independent biomechanical and physiological study. Early in 2008 the results were presented. Some of the main results, as presented on the IAAF site2 were that: . running with prosthetics needs less additional energy (up to 25 per cent) than running with natural limbs; . the amount of energy return of the prosthetic blade has never been reported for a human muscle-driven ankle joint in sprint running; . the returned energy from the prosthetic blade is close to three times higher than with the human ankle joint in maximum sprinting. Based on these findings, the study concluded that an athlete running with prosthetic blades has a clear mechanical advantage (more than 30 per cent) when compared to ‘someone’ not using the blades. According to Pistorius, however, other experts contradicted these findings. Not all of the relevant variables were taken into consideration. Pistorius and his coach responded to some of these arguments by claiming that his prosthetics confront him with other disadvantages, such as rain (which reduces his traction), crosswinds (which can blow the device sideways), and that some of his energy is more easily dispensed at the start of the race than the energy of other runners. The discussion and main arguments in this case were primarily focused on the empirical question of what is considered an athletic advantage. This debate cannot, however, be detached from the more conceptual question on the definition of running, and what could still be considered a norm for (human) running. The main question preceding any empirical research is of course: with whom is Pistorius compared, and based upon what arguments? Compared to the world record holder, any runner may be defined as ‘disadvantaged’. The fact that running with prosthetics needs less additional energy (up to 25 per cent) than running with natural limbs is in itself insufficient to keep Pistorius from competing in the Olympics. Based on the same arguments, sport authorities could have forbidden the introduction of klapskates in speed skating or the even the Fosbury flop in high jumping (cf. van Hilvoorde et al. 2007). There seems to be a fear that running on prosthetics might become faster that ‘normal’ running. It may conflict with our understanding of elite sport. Does it show the conservatism of sport and the public that wants to hold on to the familiar distinction between elite sport and disability sport? Enhancement and ‘Boosting’ in Disabled Sport In discussing the ethical issues that Paralympic sports are confronted with, Wheeler (2004) states that most ethical issues may be classified as ‘boosting’. Well-known in disability sports are physiological, pharmacological and intellectual boosting. In the Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? context of this paper the discussion on technical boosting is of great relevance. Similar to sport in general, there is an ongoing discussion on unfairness as a result of inequalities in (financing) new technology. Differences in the availability of new products (wheelchairs that are made of lighter material for example) and increasing inequalities between developing and industrialised countries highly affect the fairness of disability sports worldwide. Wheeler also mentions ‘osseointegrated prostheses’, a new technology that improves (enhances) the integration of the prostheses with the human part of the leg. This is a positive development for people who are hindered by their current prostheses, but it also creates new inequalities in the context of elite disabled sport. Special concern is also raised by the issue of ‘classification boosting’, which is unique to disability sports. Instances have been described where athletes misrepresent their functional abilities during the process of classification (Wheeler 2004, 4). The matter of defining dysfunctions is both complex and contentious, being susceptible to deceptive manipulation and fraud. Think for example of the misrepresentation or misclassification of persons with average or above average intellectual abilities as intellectually disabled. Not much is known about this phenomenon, but it raises reasons for concern about the (future) credibility of disability sports—not least because there do not seem to be easy measures to prevent this type of athletic fraud. The ‘pre-game process’ of classification influences possible outcomes of a contest to a considerable degree. Wheeler’s pledge for a code of ethics for disability sport could be a first step, but needs to be followed by measures of administrators to formalise observational criteria and investigate possibilities of manipulation. At the same time it raises the question of how objective the presentation of functional abilities can be. Every boundary that is drawn between certain types of disability creates some injustice (cf. Jones and Howe 2005). In every category there are the ‘lucky’ and ‘unlucky’ ones. In one category one could qualify as highly talented (Pistorius in the Paralympics for example), in the other just as an average athlete (Pistorius in the regular Olympics). This injustice is in many ways similar to the kind of injustice that is intrinsic to sport in general (cf. Loland 2002). Sport intrinsically differentiates between (in some respect arbitrary) differences in genetic makeup. Dysfunctions need to be recognised as similar/ dissimilar and, to an acceptable degree, responsible for the outcome of the sport. Athletic competitions are ideally set up in such a way that obvious differences in biological makeup do not determine the outcome at forehand. On the other hand, some people will always be naturally faster or stronger in ways that no training regimen can correct for. While recognising that Paralympics do not imply inferior performances, based upon a static and absolute distinction between able and disabled bodies, one can expect that these games are increasingly confronted with discussions about classification, credibility and also about unfair methods of ‘enhancement’. The optimist could say that the increase in sport-ethical concerns in the Paralympics (whether because of fraud or illegal enhancement) is a good sign, because it shows that the Paralympics are taken more and more seriously by both competitors and the audience. The more status is attached to winning medals, the more attention there is for possible fraud (such as classification boosting). This might, however, appear to be too optimistic. The struggle, for example, within professional cycling as a result of doping scandals is grounded in the fear of losing credibility within a sport that already enjoys a worldwide popularity. Disability sports start with a lack of popularity (and credibility) and have, in this sense, not much to lose. The Paralympics are not considered to be ‘truly’ interesting by the larger portion of the general 107 Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 108 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD public since disabled sportsmen (defined as an impaired deviance of normality) are not the best athletes in the world from the perspective of ‘normal sports’. In this respect, the urgent wish of Pistorius to compete within the 2008 Olympic Games paradoxically underlines the differences and reproduces the current order and hierarchy between able and disabled bodies. It would be as if Pistorius, being the best disabled runner, is promoted from an inferior division to the premier league of international sport. For most disabled athletes there is no reason (and no possibility) to aim for this kind of ranking and ‘promotion’. Pistorius’s ‘promotion’ may even contribute to a loss of credibility and appreciation of the performances of disability athletes. Some argue that athletic enhancement by means of an increase in the quality of prosthetics is similar to the use of doping. In terms of enhancement there is, however, more at stake within disability sport, more than just trying to become the best athlete within a specific category. Disability sports are about showing performances within categories of similar disabilities, without making those disabilities the central element of athletic prowess. Elite sport is about excellence within the boundaries of ‘self-chosen’ limitations; disability sports originated from limitations through fate. Elite sport symbolises the athlete as hero; it reproduces elitist ideals about the body (‘athletic’ and ‘beautiful’), about good sportsmanship and national pride. For many people in disability sport, the athlete is still a ‘patient combating their limitations’, instead of an elite athlete with specific talents or virtuosity. It is, however, a different matter if disabled elite athletes may in some cases be eligible to compete with able athletes. Arguments against the inclusion of three legs or prosthetic limbs may be focused too much and selective on visible differences between athletes. Take for example Floyd Landis, who injured his hip in 2003 and received a hip prosthesis in 2006. Why is Floyd Landis’s hip not regarded as an advantage or an (‘artificial hip’) enhancement, while his usage of testosterone was? What’s the difference between the internal prosthesis of Landis and the external ones of Pistorius? The advantages of a prosthesis in this case bear upon the relevant inequalities of the sport. Some actually claim this is also the case for running competitions between Ethiopians and Caucasians, and that therefore they should compete in separate categories. The question is whether Pistorius is playing the same game as his opponents. We argue that he is not because he is showing another and extra skill, namely handling his prosthesis in an extremely talented way. Prostheses may have a considerable influence on the outcome of the game. This, however is not an argument in itself that this competition should be excluded from the regular Olympic Games. Conclusion Problems with classification and categorisation in sport for the disabled confront us with the intrinsic inequalities and unfairness of any competitive practice that depends upon the classification of people based upon both equalities and (‘relevant’) inequalities. A three legged swimmer or a sprinter with prostheses who might become faster than the elite sprinters can be excluded from regular competition, not because of their inferiority but instead because a disability may appear to be a superior advantage. It is easy to point at the conservative elements within traditional sport, in order to explain the exclusion of Pistorius from the Olympic Games. There is, however, more at stake, from the perspective of the internal goods of the sport. In sport there is no purely rational logic in the definition Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? of rules, neither in classification nor categorisations, in order to make the competition as ‘fair’ as possible. Rules are always a combination and compromise of tradition and a sportethical ideal of ‘equality’ (the ‘level playing field’). People with three legs would allow for a separate competition when the third leg has a considerate influence on the outcome of the game. When discussing relations and remarkable differences in admiration between elite sport and disability sport, the traditional sport world is confronted with matters of inclusion and a fair distribution of resources and rewards for the achievements of all athletes. As we have seen in the case of Rawls’s philosophy of justice, however, these mechanisms of inclusion and fair distribution are often based upon a very narrow image of the average person, therefore again excluding the possibility of a pluralistic society. Sport is a social practice with an internal logic that does not always conform to these general principles of justice, specifically as we have come to embrace them now. It therefore proves to be a good case for further analyses of the distinction society draws between normal and disabled, between natural and dysfunctional. Sports are a well-defined form of cultivation of specific abnormalities, and what is traditionally understood as professional sportsmanship has socio-cultural roots in history. Abnormality is the common denominator for both. The direction of excellence can be framed socio-culturally, and from that perspective, there is not that much of a difference between Paralympics and Olympics. The genetically fortunate and unfortunate share the exceptional position on the scale of normality. And sometimes they meet, at the circus or in a sports arena. Many biological exceptions are the result of certain genetic mutations that may result in either a talent or disability. Depending on the time and context in which a ‘mutant’ is being nurtured, one could either end up in a freak show, at the circus or in a modern sport arena. NOTES 1. 2. See http://www.sideshowworld.com/blowoff-RFlentini.html, accessed 10 March 2008. Available at http://www.iaaf.org/news/Kind¼512/newsId¼42896.html, accessed 10 March 2008. REFERENCES BAILEY, R. 2007. Talent development and the luck problem. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 1 (3): 367–77. BLOCK, M.E. and I. OBRUSNIKOVA. 2007. Inclusion in physical education: A review of the literature from 1995–2005. Adapted Physical Activity Quarterly 24: 103–24. BOORSE, C. 1975. On the distinction between disease and illness. Philosophy and Public Affairs 5: 49–68. ———. 1976. What a theory of mental health should be. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 6 (1). ———. 1977. Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science 44. BOWEN, J. 2002. The Americans With Disabilities Act and its application to sport. Journal of The Philosophy of Sport XXIX: 66–74. BROWN, W.M. 1990. Practices and prudence. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport XVII: 71–84. BUCHANAN, A.B., D.W. BROCK , N. DANIELS and D. WIKLER. 2000. From Chance to Choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 109 110 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 DEPAUW, K.P. and S.J. GAVRON. 2005. Disability Sport, 2nd edn. Champaign, IL: Human Kinetics. DOLL-TEPPER, G., M. KRONER and W. SONNENSCHEIN. 2001. New Horizons in Sport for Athletes with a Disability. Aachen: Meyer & Meyer Sport. ENGELHARDT, H.T. and S.F. SPICKER, eds. 1974. Evaluation and Explanation in the Biomedical Sciences. Dordrecht: Netherlands: Reidel Publishing Company. IPC (2006) Athletics Classification Handbook. JONES, C. and P.D. HOWE. 2005. The conceptual boundaries of sport for the disabled: Classification and athletic performance. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 32: 133–46. KIOUMOURTZOGLOU, E. and K. POLITIS, eds. 2004. Paralympic Games From 1960 to 2004. Athens: Organising Committee for the Olympic Games. KLENCK, C. and K. GEBKE. 2007. Practical management: Common medical problems in disabled athletes. Clinical Journal of Sport Medicine 19 (1): 55–60. LINDSTROM, L.L. 1992. Integration of sport for athletes with disabilities into sport programmes for able-bodied athletes. Palaestra 8 (3): 25–59. LOLAND, S. 2002. Fair Play in Sport: A Moral Norm System. London and New York: Routledge. MACINTYRE, A. 1985. After Virtue. London: Duckworth. MCNAMEE, M. 1995. Sporting practices, institutions, and virtues: A critique and a restatement. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport XXII: 61–82. MOSER, I. 2006. Disability and the promises of technology: Technology, subjectivity and embodiment within an order of the normal. Information, Communication and Society 9 (3): 373–95. NICKELL, J. 2005. Secrets of the Sideshows. Lexington, KY: University Press of Kentucky. PICKERING, FRANCIS L. 2005. Competitive sports, disability, and problems of justice in sports. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 32: 127–32. RAWLS, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. SHERILL, C. 2004a. Adapted Physical Activity, Recreation, and Sport. Crossdisciplinary and Lifespan, 6th edn. New York: McGraw-Hill. ———. 2004b. The changing terminology of ‘‘ability’’ and ‘‘disability’’ in the sport context. In Paralympic Games From 1960 to 2004, edited by E. Kioumourtzoglou and K. Politis. Athens: Organising Committee for the Olympic Games. TÄNNSJÖ, T. 2000. Is our admiration for sports heroes fascistoid? In Values in Sport: Elitism, Nationalism, Gender Equality, and the Scientific Manufacture of Winners, edited by T. Tännsjö and C.M. Tamburrini. London and New York: E&FN Spon/Routledge. TAYLOR, K. and R. MYKITIUK. 2001. Genetics, normalcy and disability. ISUMA: Canadian Journal of Policy Research/Revue canadienne de recherche surles politiques 2 (3): 65–71. TOULMIN, S. 1975. Concepts of function and mechanism in medicine and medical science. In Evaluation and Explanation in the Biomedical Sciences, edited by H.T. Engelhardt and S.F. Spicker. Dordrecht: Netherlands: Reidel Publishing Company. TWEEDY, S.M. 2002. Taxonomic theory and the ICF: Foundation for the Unified Disability Athletics Classification. Adapted Physical Activity Quarterly 19: 221–37. USTUN, T.B. 2004. Celebrate individual differences. The ICF model of disability. In Paralympic Games From 1960 to 2004, edited by E. Kioumourtzoglou and K. Politis. Athens: Organising Committee for the Olympic Games. VAN HILVOORDE, I., R. VOS and G. DE WERT. 2007. Flopping, klapping and gene doping: Dichotomies between ‘natural’ and ‘artificial’ in elite sport. Social Studies of Science 37 (2): 173–200. DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? VANLANDEWIJCK, Y.C. and R. CHAPPEL. 1996. Integration and classification issues in competitive sport for athletes with disabilities. Sport Science Review 5: 65–88. WHEELER, G.D. 2004. Ethical aspects in sports participation. In Paralympic Games From 1960 to 2004, edited by E. Kioumourtzoglou and K. Politis. Athens: Organising Committee for the Olympic Games. Downloaded by [Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam] at 03:53 13 July 2012 Ivo van Hilvoorde, Faculty of Human Movement Science, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, The Netherlands. E-mail: I.vanHilvoorde@fbw.vu.nl Laurens Landeweerd, Faculty of Health and Science, University of Maastricht, The Netherlands. E-mail: l.landeweerd@tudelft.nl 111