Nothing Special   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Promoting fairness in sport through performance-enhancing substances: An argument for why sport referees ought to 'be on drugs' Promoting fairness in sport through performance-enhancing substances: An argument for why sport referees ought to 'be on drugs'

2020, Sports, Ethics and Philosophy

The debate on the use of performance-enhancing substances or methods to improve refereeing is underdeveloped in the sport philosophical literature. This contrast with the attention scholars have devoted to the use of such substances and methods for athletic purposes. However, when considered from the perspective of fairness, this differential treatment is problematic. Since one of the main concerns with performance-enhancing drugs is their detrimental effect on fairness, the use of performance-enhancing drugs and methods to improve refereeing, given their positive effects on fairness, should have more relevance in the literature. If anti-doping advocates aim to protect and promote fairness in sport, they should consider the possibility of using performance-enhancing drugs or methods to improve refereeing. In this article, we make an argument for this possibility and critically discuss some possible objections. We conclude that referees, under certain conditions, ought to use doping substances or methods.

Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association r Fo Journal: er Pe Promoting fairness in sport through performance-enhancing substances: An argument for why sport referees ought to ‘be on drugs’ Sports, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association Re Manuscript ID RSEP-2020-0006.R2 Manuscript Type: Original Article w vie Keywords: doping, fairness, refereeing, sports ethics, WADA ly On URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 1 of 17 1 Promoting fairness in sport through performance-enhancing substances: An argument for why sport referees ought to ‘be on drugs’ Abstract: The debate on the use of performance-enhancing substances or methods to improve refereeing is underdeveloped in the sport philosophical literature. This contrast with the attention r Fo scholars have devoted to the use of such substances and methods for athletic purposes. However, when considered from the perspective of fairness, this differential treatment is problematic. Since Pe one of the main concerns with performance-enhancing drugs is their detrimental effect on fairness, the use of performance-enhancing drugs and methods to improve refereeing, given their positive er effects on fairness, should have more relevance in the literature. If anti-doping advocates aim to Re protect and promote fairness in sport, they should consider the possibility of using performance- vie enhancing drugs or methods to improve refereeing. In this article, we make an argument for this possibility and critically discuss some possible objections. We conclude that referees, under certain w conditions, ought to use doping substances or methods. On Keywords: doping; ethics; fairness; fair play; refereeing; sports ethics. ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 1. Introduction Refereeing errors are commonplace in professional sport. These errors are not only an important source of frustration and harm for athletes and spectators, but they also, and more importantly, result in the unsatisfactory and unfair resolution of sport contests. Poor positioning, cognitive limitations, and lack of concentration are among the causes of such errors. In baseball, due to URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 2 cognitive limitations and fatigue, umpires miss roughly 10–15% of their pitch calls behind the plate (Kim and King 2014). In football, the most common causes of error are the failure to concentrate on the play (focusing on the ball and legs of the players) and lack of visibility due to poor positioning (Oudejans et al., 2002). For instance, Diego Maradona’s ‘hand of God’ goal during the quarter final match between Argentina and England at the 1986 FIFA World Cup in Mexico City was given because of referee Ali Bin Nasser’s and linesman Bogdan Dochev’s poor positioning on r Fo the field (Murray 2018). The reduction of refereeing errors to promote fairness is a priority for sport governing bodies. Pe Indeed, in the last two decades, many of them have implemented supportive technologies such as er Video Assistant Referee (VAR) and Hawk-Eye to help referees make better, and ultimately fairer, calls.1 Despite their proven positive impact on referees’ effectiveness, criticism of these Re technologies has mounted in some sports.2 For instance, in football, spectators and journalists have vie criticized the VAR system on the grounds that it negatively affects both the flow of the game and the referee’s authority (i.e., the human authority on the field) and undermines important human w elements such as verbal communication and fallibility (Holt 2019; Wilson 2018). Besides the use On of assistive technology to improve refereeing, sport governing bodies have also invested in training referees. For instance, after implementing the VAR, the Fédération Internationale de Football ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 2 of 17 Association (FIFA) launched a worldwide training program to instruct national football leagues and federations on the use of such supportive technology (FIFA, 2018). One potential solution to poor refereeing that remains unexplored is the use of drugs (e.g., EPO and Ritalin) or methods (e.g., blood doping) to improve referees’ performance. Using EPO and blood doping, for example, would allow referees to run longer distances and better position themselves on the field, whereas taking cognitive-enhancing drugs such as Ritalin would improve URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 3 of 17 3 their attention span and ability to concentrate and focus on specific aspects of the game. By reducing referees’ errors, the use of these substances would positively affect fairness, understood as compliance with the rules of sport.3 Despite these beneficial effects, the debate on the use of doping to improve refereeing is underdeveloped in the sport philosophical literature. The lack of attention to the use of doping substances and methods for refereeing purposes contrasts with the consideration scholars have given to the use of such substances and methods to r Fo enhance athletic performance.4 Yet, when considered from the perspective of fairness, this differential treatment is problematic. If allowing referees to take doping has a positive effect on Pe fairness, anti-doping advocates should give more attention to the use of performance-enhancing er drugs and methods to improve refereeing (Geeraets 2018). To put it differently, if sport-governing bodies aim to protect and promote fairness in sport, they should consider the possibility of using Re performance-enhancing drugs and methods to improve refereeing. vie In this article, we provide an argument for this possibility. To do so, we proceed as follows. In Section 2, we analyze the World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) policy concerning the use of w doping among referees. In this section, we show that whether WADA allows referees to use doping On is unclear. In Section 3, we present and clarify our argument. Subsequently, in Section 4, we consider possible objections to the argument. Section 5 summarizes our findings and provides a ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association conclusion. 2. WADA on the use of doping among referees No sport governing body tests referees for doping.5 However, this does not mean that WADA explicitly allows referees to dope. The WADA Code (2019), commonly known as ‘the Code’, does URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 4 not refer to referees or umpires. It is thus unclear whether the international governing body in charge of anti-doping allows doping for refereeing purposes. The Code can be interpreted either way, that is, as advocating either for or against using drugs to enhance referees’ abilities. Concerning athletes, the Code states: ‘… any Person who participates in sport under the authority of any Signatory, government, or other sports organization accepting the Code is an Athlete’ (WADA Code 2019, 135). If a relevant governing body does not regard referees as participants, then the Code allows r Fo referees to dope. In contrast, if the governing body takes referees to be participants, then the Code does not allow referees to dope. Pe WADA prohibits professionals other than athletes from doping. For instance, athletes’ support er personnel are not allowed to use doping substances. WADA defines ‘athlete support personnel’ as ‘Any coach, trainer, manager, agent, team staff, official, medical, paramedical personnel, parent or Re any other Person working with, treating or assisting an Athlete participating in or preparing for vie sports Competition.’ (WADA Code 2019, p. 136). If the term ‘official’ here encompasses referees, then the latter are not allowed to dope. However, it is unclear whether WADA’s intends this w meaning. WADA extensively uses the word ‘official’ to refer to doping control officials (WADA On Code 2019, 136), but these officials are not referees. Moreover, sport-governing bodies often regard physicians and managers as officials.6 WADA should clarify its position on what the Code means by ‘official’ and whether the term includes referees. ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 4 of 17 Despite its lack of clarity on whether referees are allowed to dope, we assume that WADA prohibits referees from doing so, as this fits its anti-doping position concerning athletes and other sport-related professionals. In what follows, we will argue not only that referees should be allowed to dope, but also that they ought to do it, provided that it is safe for them to do so. URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 5 of 17 5 3. Our argument Our argument proceeds in four steps, comprising three premises and a conclusion. We depart from the moral claim that one ought to prevent unfairness or promote fairness if doing so does not require significant sacrifices such as severe physical or social harm. Second, if performanceenhancing drugs improved refereeing (e.g., enabling referees to cover more ground and concentrate better), their use would produce a positive effect on fairness. Third, the use of doping r Fo substances and methods to improve refereeing, assuming the drugs and methods are safe and legal, requires minor sacrifices only. These three premises lead to the conclusion that sport referees ought Pe to use performance-enhancing drugs or methods. Differently put, the argument goes as follows: er Re Premise 1: A sport referee ought to prevent unfairness or promote fairness assuming no significant sacrifices are required. vie Premise 2: Using performance-enhancing drugs and methods improves referees’ abilities. w Premise 3: The use of such drugs and methods, assuming it is safe and legal, only requires minor sacrifices. On Conclusion: Sport referees ought to use performance-enhancing substances and methods. ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association Some aspects of the argument require clarification. Concerning premise 1, it is important to note that we are not claiming that WADA should penalize referees for refusing to dope. Our claim is that referees have the moral obligation to use doping if the substances lack adverse effects, enhance refereeing abilities, and are legal. If doping substances or methods result in any serious harm using them would require significant sacrifices, which would run counter to premises 1 and 3. That doping is often harmful is widely documented (Birzniece 2015). For instance, at times, URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 6 doping harms health, especially if not used under medical supervision. However, at other times, despite not being harmful to health (e.g., autologous blood doping, that is, the infusion of the subject’s own stored blood), doping might be detrimental to one’s income, prestige, and social position (Zhou 2016). For example, the use of doping might harm a doping user’s income or social status if the possession and purchase of doping substances and methods is illegal in the society in which the user lives. To be clear, we argue that referees ought to use doping if doing so is safe and legal. r Fo Regarding premise 2, as we established in Section 1, unfairness in sport has to do with uncalled Pe rule infractions. These infractions harm the interests of the athletes, referees, coaches, relatives, er spectators, and nations that should benefit from the rule infraction. Recall Maradona’s ‘hand of God’ goal. If the goal had been ruled out, England might have won the 1986 World Cup. The best Re referees are those who make the least number of unfair calls. If doping allows referees to err less vie often, referees who benefit from using doping would be better than those who do not. Let us now turn to some possible objections to the argument that we have presented in this section. w 4. Critical discussion ly On 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 6 of 17 One type of objection against our position draws on arguments against the use of doping to enhance athletes’ performance in the sport philosophy literature. The other type of objection is based on practical concerns. With regard to the former, first, it could be argued that enhancing referees’ abilities undermines the nature of both sport and refereeing. However, this objection does not hold. Sport performance enhancement is different from refereeing performance enhancement. Sports and refereeing are markedly different practices. The latter is an instrumental activity that aims to URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 7 of 17 7 enforce the rulebook of a specific sport – for the game to be possible, fair, and flow. A referee is successful by achieving the instrumental function of the practice, that is, by making calls that allow the game to keep going, be fair, and flow nicely. In contrast, the athletic performance is not evaluated solely in instrumental terms. As Bernard Suits argues (1988), a sport is a game of physical skills whereby individuals exercise physical abilities to achieve a goal by overcoming demanding situations or challenges. Sport, unlike r Fo refereeing, is not an instrumental activity. Rather, according to Suits, most individuals engage in sport for the sake of doing it, that is, to enjoy the process and experience of testing their physical Pe skills. The use of drugs to enhance performance can negatively affect the participants’ experience, er removing what is valuable in it. This is hardly the case with refereeing. Being an instrumental activity, referees should use any morally acceptable means that increase their efficiency, helping Re them to better achieve the goal of the practice. Drugs are to referees what hammers are for vie carpenters. Furthermore, contrary to the widespread idea that sport performance enhancement is detrimental to the game, refereeing performance enhancement can have a positive effect on the game. w On Second, doping can be harmful to health and, thereby, should be banned to protect its users. Thus, at least as a rule of thumb, nobody should be morally obliged, or even expected, to engage ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association in a harmful practice. However, this objection builds upon two contested assumptions, namely: (a) doping is always harmful and (b) practices that risk inflicting harm should be banned to protect people. Concerning (a), certain forms of doping (e.g., EPO and blood transfusion) are not generally harmful to health if used under medical supervision (see e.g. López 2011, Lundby et al. 2007, and Zhou 2016). This would certainly be the case with referees. If their use of doping were accepted as instrumental to refereeing, they would not need to hide their doping practices, as athletes do URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 8 because doping is banned. As for (b), banning a harmful practice in which adult, well-informed individuals voluntarily decide to engage (e.g., racing in Formula 1 or BASE jumping) is an unjustifiable autonomy-limiting intervention. Moreover, even those who endorse paternalistic interventions to prevent harm should accept our argument, as we only accept that referees should use drugs when it is safe for them to do it. Third, the acceptance of refereeing doping could create a coercive environment that r Fo undermines the referees’ autonomy.7 If doping is not only allowed, but also morally required, referees, especially those who refuse to use artificial means to enhance their performance, could Pe feel coerced to dope. To respond to this objection, the meaning of ‘coercion’ must be clarified. er Not all situations where somebody engages with another person through compulsion or brute force (e.g., a sport official force-feeds a referee with Ritalin) are coercive8. This is not how we Re understand coercion. If that were the case, then it would be morally wrong to allow the use of vie doping among referees, for they would be coerced into doping, which would violate their autonomy. Instead, we rely on Nozick’s (1969) view of coercion.9 Briefly, in this view a person A w (the coercer) coerces another person B (the coercee) into doing x only if the following three conditions are met: 2. A communicates a threat to B. ly 1. A aims to get B to do x. On 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 8 of 17 3. A’s threat indicates that if B fails to do x, A will bring about some consequences that would make not x-ing less desirable for B than x-ing. To illustrate this understanding of coercion, consider a sport director saying to a referee, ‘If you do not take these cognitive enhancers, my friend, you will be sacked.’ In this case, all three conditions are met: URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 9 of 17 9 1. The sport director aims to get the referee to take drugs. 2. The sport director verbally communicates the threat that the referee will face if he or she fails to meet the sport director’s offer. 3. Refusing to take the drug would get the referee fired, which makes doping more desirable. With this understanding of coercion in mind, coercion would not always occur if WADA lifted the ban on doping for referees. First, it is unlikely that the acceptance of doping would inevitably r Fo coerce referees to use doping. By allowing referees to dope, WADA may not necessarily have the aim of getting referees to do so. By analogy, a state that legalizes substances such as alcohol or Pe tobacco does not intend people to consume such substances. The reasons for legalizing these er substances are multiple – e.g., to combat a criminal black market on alcohol and tobacco or to ensure that the state is less paternalistic. The same reasoning can be applied to lifting the ban on Re doping for referees. Thus, the first condition of coercion is not met, as WADA would probably not vie intend to make referees do something specific if they explicitly made it clear that referees are allowed to dope. Moreover, permitting referees to use doping may not be communicating, in any w way, a claim or threat to anyone. Therefore, the second condition is not met either. In addition, if On the first and second conditions are not met, neither is the third. Therefore, if the Nozick-inspired version of coercion is correct, the objection based on coercion against our argument does not hold ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association water. By allowing doping for referees, WADA would not necessarily be acting in a coercive way. Of course, a sport governing body may coerce referees to use doping under the threat of firing or punishing them. However, this would hardly be the purpose of lifting the ban on doping for referees. Nor is it clear that coercion would occur if the alleged coercers are peers collectively imposing social pressure on an individual to dope. Social pressure can be defined in many ways we do not have space here to specify them all. If ‘social pressure’ means merely that a person URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 10 comes under pressure to use doping substances because he or she knows or believes that his or her peers are using them (so there is no explicit request from peers to dope),10 then none of the three conditions for coercion are met. Furthermore, social pressure is not always morally problematic. In elite sport, for example, social pressure is often inherent to the game (see e.g. Allen 2003). And while peer pressure may increase the probability of negative ramifications, e.g. eating disorders (Mallin 2007), peer pressure may also increase the probability of positive outcomes, e.g. r Fo confidence, connection, compassion and caring (Fraser-Thomas et al. 2005). So, it seems to be an open question whether referees will experience a negative social pressure to use performance Pe enhancing drugs or methods given it was allowed. er Regarding practical objections to our argument, some might claim that current referees are good enough and fallible, and thereby we should not expect perfection from them. Certainly, Re whether they use doping or not, humans are, and will always be, fallible. However, even though vie referees are often subject to strict training and selection processes, they can always improve. Indeed, sport governing bodies invest big sums of money to improve refereeing by training referees w and developing supportive technology such as VAR and Hawk-Eye technology (FIFA 2016; On UEFA 2019). Technology and training can certainly help improve refereeing, but pointing out that this is the case fails to raise an objection to our argument. As we stated above, despite their training, ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 10 of 17 baseball umpires still miss 10–15% of calls. Furthermore, performance-enhancing drugs and methods might also help technicians manipulating supportive technology to be more effective in helping referees make better calls. Another practical problem would be that doping is expensive. Thus, given the economic differences among national sport federations, the use of doping to enhance refereeing would widen differences in refereeing quality among countries, which would have a detrimental effect on URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 11 of 17 11 fairness. However, this problem can be resolved if sport governing bodies subsidized access to performance-enhancing drugs for referees, just like the Association of Tennis Professionals (ATP) covers the cost of Hawk-Eye. One could further argue that allowing referees to dope would open the gates to broader acceptance and use of doping for athletic purposes. Promoting the use of performance-enhancing substances and methods among referees would in this case, function as a Trojan horse within r Fo today’s sport community, where agreement on the need to control and reduce the use of doping seems to be lacking. We take this to be a legitimate concern. However, as we established above, Pe the goals and nature of refereeing and sport are different. Thus, accepting the use of drugs in one er of the practices should not lead to acceptance in the other. Indeed, referees and athletes understand themselves as performing different and, in some cases opposing, jobs and functions (e.g., both Re perceive each other as enemies to deceive, manipulate, or discipline). Moreover, as is already the vie case, social distance between referees and athletes is required. This is not only to prevent their relationship from affecting referees’ judgment, but also, if doping for refereeing purposes were to w be allowed, to prevent athletes from having access to the drugs referees use. On Another counterargument one could make is that refereeing errors are evenly distributed. Thus, refereeing errors do not hinder sport fairness. Sometimes refereeing errors are to the ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association detriment of one side; at other times, referees make poor calls that benefit the other side. Moreover, if this is the case, there is no problem with fairness and referees erring. Of course, it would be good if referees’ errors were evenly distributed, but this is not the case. Did the referees make up for their poor call against England in the 1986 World Cup? As far as we know, they did not, and there is no guarantee that errors are evenly distributed. As empirical research demonstrates (Morgulev URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 12 et al., 2018), referees are biased to make calls that benefit home or powerful teams (e.g., favor the home team if the atmosphere is loud) and specific types of athletes. Finally, one could argue that the social perception of allowing referees to use doping would be very negative. This is, of course, an empirical question. Some spectators or sponsors might not have a problem with refereeing doping, and they might even support it if it increased fairness in sport. So, before introducing “a drug for referee policy,” it might be worthwhile to educate and r Fo inform the public on why this a good idea for the world of sports. er 5. Conclusion Pe When the ethics of doping is being discussed in the scholarly literature and sporting world, the Re focus has always been on athletes. This is, of course, an important focus, but it has made us blind vie to consider the ethics of using doping to enhance referees’ performance. For instance, as we have shown in this article, even WADA is unclear on whether referees are allowed to use doping. To w fill this gap in the ethics of doping literature and spur discussion on the topic, in this article, we On have made a case for the view that referees ought to use doping if it is safe and effective. And the argument for this is that, by using doping, referees can promote a core value in sport, namely: ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 12 of 17 fairness. Finally, we have presented and critically discussed possible objections to our argument and responded to them. So if there are no further and plausible objections against our argument, we conclude that referees, under certain conditions, ought to dope. URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 13 of 17 13 Notes 1 See e.g. Collins and Evans (2008) for a description of some of the technological details of how Hawk-Eye technology works. 2 Collins (2010), for example, has argued that it is not made clear to the public that the use of Hawk-Eye is not 100% reliable. 3 See e.g. Loland (2002). 4 One exception to this – though it is not a text in an academic journal – is a short blog contribution by Anders Sandberg http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2012/05/the-dignity-of-thereferee/. However, while Sandberg only discusses whether there should be a ban on referees using doping, and concludes that this should not be done, we argue that referees should be allowed to use doping and further argue that referees ought to use doping in order to increase fair play in the sport arena. 5 Scientific evidence on the frequency and prevalence of testing referees for doping use is lacking – UEFA, for example, said in 2013 that it will not test referees in 2013 and 2014 http://www.dutchreferee.com/no-blood-tests-for-referees-in-20132014-by-uefa/. Testing of referees is not done very often – and when it is, it can be a front-page story https://www.thesun.co.uk/sport/9425924/boxing-referee-judges-drug-tested-wbc/. r Fo er Pe 6 Re For instance, the International Handball Federation (IHF) employs the word ‘official’ for nonplaying team members (not referees) – e.g. the responsible team official is the only one allowed to contact the referee. See page 15 in the IHF Regulations: https://www.ihf.info/sites/default/files/2019-07/New-Rules%20of%20the%20Game_GB.pdf 7 See e.g. Murray (1983) or Holowchak (2000) for this type of worry. See Veber (2014) for a critical discussion of this view. 8 See Anderson (2013) for a more detailed account of this understanding of ‘coercion’. Dubljevic (2013) calls it ‘total coercion’. 9 We also draw here on Veber’s (2014) criticism of arguments from coercion against the use of doping in sport. 10 This specification is identical to the characterization of ‘peer pressure’ given by Fitz et al. (2013, p. 5). w vie ly On 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 14 References ANDERSON, S. (2017) Coercion" In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/coercion/. BIRZNIECE, V. 2015. Doping in sport: Effects, harm and misconceptions. Internal Medicine Journal 45(3): 239–48. r Fo COLLINS, H. 2010. The philosophy of umpiring and the introduction of decision-aid technology. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 37(2): 135–46. Pe COLLINS, H. and R. EVANS. 2008. You cannot be serious! Public understanding of technology er with special reference to ‘Hawk-Eye’. Public Understanding of Science 17: 283–308. Re DELONG, J.E. 2017. Neuropsychology behind the plate. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 11(3): vie 385–95. DUBLJEVIC V. (2013) Cognitive Enhancement, Rational Choice and Justification. Neuroethics, On vol.6, 179-187. w FIFA. 2016. First VAR training centre at the home of FIFA. FIFA.com, August 2. Available at ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 14 of 17 https://football-technology.fifa.com/en/media-tiles/first-var-training-centre-at-the-home-of-fifa/ (accessed 29 January 2020. ) ———. 2018. First FIFA VAR course for Member Associations held. FIFA.com, October 26. Available at https://www.fifa.com/about-fifa/who-we-are/news/first-fifa-var-course-for-memberassociations-held (accessed 29 January 2020). URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 15 of 17 15 FRASER-THOMAS, J.L. ET AL. (2005) Youth sport programs: an avenue to foster positive youth development. Physical Education & Sport Pedagogy, 10(1), 19-40. GEERAETS, V. 2018. Ideology, doping and the spirit of sport. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 12(3): 255–71. DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2017.1351483 HOLOWCHAK A. (2000). “Aretism” and Pharmacological Ergogenic Aids in Sport: Taking a Shot r Fo at the Use of Steroids. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 27 (1): 35-50. A HOLT, O. 2019. The shambles of VAR has turned English football into a laughing stock... it is Pe not fit for purpose. MailOnline, November 9. Available at er https://www.dailymail.co.uk/sport/football/article-7668523/OLIVER-HOLT-shambles-VARturned-English-football-laughing-stock.html (accessed 29 January 2020.) Re KIM, J.W. and B.G. KING. 2014. Seeing stars: Matthew effects and status bias in major league vie baseball umpiring. Management Science 60 (11): 2619–44, cit. in DELONG (2017). w LOLAND, S. 2002. Fair play in sport. London: Routledge. On LÓPEZ, B. 2001. The invention of a ‘drug of mass destruction’: Deconstructing the EPO myth. Sport in History 31(1): 84–109. ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association LUNDY et al. (2007). Erythropoietin treatment elevates haemoglobin concentration by increasing red cell volume and depressing plasma volume. Journal of Physiology 578(1): 309. MILLAN. J.M. (2007) Social Pressure and Body Image as Contributors to Eating Habits among Collegiate Women Athletes. Dissertation, University of Akron. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/656e/f7496fbbab8b53240d9ef89edd0ba7302daf.pdf URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association 16 MORGULEV, E., AZAR, O. H., LIDOR, R., SABAG, E., & BAR-ELI, M. (2018). Searching for Judgment Biases Among Elite Basketball Referees. Frontiers in psychology, 9, 2637. MURRAY, T.H. (1983). The Coercive Power of Drugs in Sports. Hastings Center Report, 13 (4): 24-30. MURRAY, S. (2018). World Cup moments: You’ve got to hand it to Diego. The Irish Times, May r Fo 30. Available at https://www.irishtimes.com/sport/soccer/international/world-cup-moments-youve-got-to-hand-it-to-diego-1.3479140 (accessed 29 January 2020.) Pe NOZICK, R. (1969) Coercion. In Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel, eds. Morgenbesser, Suppes, and White, 440–472. New York: St. Martin’s Press. er OUDEJANS, R. R., VERHEIJEN, R., BAKKER, F. C., GERRITS, J. C., STEINBRÜCKNER, M., & BEEK, P. J. (2000). Errors in judging ‘offside’ in football. Nature, 404(6773), 33-33. vie Re SUITS, B. 1988. Tricky triad: Games, play, and sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 15(1):1– w 9. On UEFA. 2019. UEFA VAR training in full swing. UEFA.com, April 17. Available at https://www.uefa.com/insideuefa/protecting-the-game/refereeing/news/newsid=2600177.html (accessed 29 January 2020.) ly 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 16 of 17 VEBER, M. (2014). The Coercion Argument Against Performance-Enhancing Drugs. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 41 (2): 267-277. WILSON, P. 2018. VAR is another slap in the face for the long-suffering paying spectator. The Guardian, March 18. Available at https://www.theguardian.com/football/blog/2018/mar/04/varslap-in-face-paying-spectator-referees (accessed 29 January 2020.) URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk Page 17 of 17 17 ZHOU, J. 2016. A review of the application of autologous blood transfusion. Brazilian Journal of Medical and Biological Research 49(9): e5493. r Fo er Pe w vie Re ly On 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Sport, Ethics & Philosophy: Journal of the British Philosophy of Sport Association URL: http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/rsep Email: m.j.mcnamee@swansea.ac.uk