Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-04T12:21:13.312Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What kinds of things are psychiatric disorders?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2010

K. S. Kendler*
Affiliation:
Virginia Institute for Psychiatric and Behavioral Genetics, Department of Psychiatry and Department of Human and Molecular Genetics, Virginia Commonwealth University, Richmond, VA, USA
P. Zachar
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Auburn University, Montgomery, AL, USA
C. Craver
Affiliation:
Philosophy-Neuroscience-Psychology Program, Washington University in St Louis, St Louis, MO, USA
*
*Address for correspondence: K. S. Kendler, M.D., Virginia Institute for Psychiatric and Behavioral Genetics, Virginia Commonwealth University Medical School, PO Box 980126, Richmond, VA 23298-0126, USA. (Email: kendler@hsc.vcu.edu)

Abstract

This essay explores four answers to the question ‘What kinds of things are psychiatric disorders?’ Essentialist kinds are classes whose members share an essence from which their defining features arise. Although elegant and appropriate for some physical (e.g. atomic elements) and medical (e.g. Mendelian disorders) phenomena, this model is inappropriate for psychiatric disorders, which are multi-factorial and ‘fuzzy’. Socially constructed kinds are classes whose members are defined by the cultural context in which they arise. This model excludes the importance of shared physiological mechanisms by which the same disorder could be identified across different cultures. Advocates of practical kinds put off metaphysical questions about ‘reality’ and focus on defining classes that are useful. Practical kinds models for psychiatric disorders, implicit in the DSM nosologies, do not require that diagnoses be grounded in shared causal processes. If psychiatry seeks to tie disorders to etiology and underlying mechanisms, a model first proposed for biological species, mechanistic property cluster (MPC) kinds, can provide a useful framework. MPC kinds are defined not in terms of essences but in terms of complex, mutually reinforcing networks of causal mechanisms. We argue that psychiatric disorders are objectively grounded features of the causal structure of the mind/brain. MPC kinds are fuzzy sets defined by mechanisms at multiple levels that act and interact to produce the key features of the kind. Like species, psychiatric disorders are populations with central paradigmatic and more marginal members. The MPC view is the best current answer to ‘What kinds of things are psychiatric disorders?’

Type
Original Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beck, AT, Alford, BA (2008). Depression: Causes and Treatment, 2nd edn. University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia, PA.Google Scholar
Borsboom, D (2008). Psychometric perspectives on diagnostic systems. Journal of Clinical Psychology 64, 10891108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boyd, R (1991). Realism, antifoundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies 61, 127148.Google Scholar
Boyd, R (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays (ed. Wilson, R. A.), pp. 141185. A Bradford Book/MIT Press: Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, KC (2003). The Rise of Causal Concepts of Disease: Case Histories. Ashgate Publishing Company: Burlington, VT.Google Scholar
Cooper, R (2005). Classifying Madness. Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands.Google Scholar
Craver, CF (2007). Explaining the Brain. Clarendon Press: Oxford.Google Scholar
Dewey, J (1925). Experience and Nature (1925/1958). Dover: New York, NY.Google Scholar
Evans, AS (1993). Causation and Disease: A Chronological Journey. Plenum Publishing Corporation/Plenum Medical Book Company: New York, NY.Google Scholar
Fine, A (1984). The natural ontological attitude. In Scientific Realism (ed. Leplin, J.), pp. 83107. University of California Press: Berkeley, CA.Google Scholar
Haack, S (2003). Defending Science – Within Reason: Between Scientism and Cynicism. Prometheus Books: Amherst, NY.Google Scholar
International Schizophrenia Consortium (2009). Common polygenic variation contributes to risk of schizophrenia and bipolar disorder. Nature 460, 748752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jablensky, A, Sartorius, N, Ernberg, G, Anker, M, Korten, A, Cooper, JE, Day, R, Bertelsen, A (1992). Schizophrenia: manifestations, incidence and course in different cultures. A World Health Organization ten-country study. Psychological Medicine Monograph Supplement 20, 197.Google Scholar
James, W (1907). Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth (1907, 1909/1975). Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Kendler, KS (1983). Overview: a current perspective on twin studies of schizophrenia. American Journal of Psychiatry 140, 14131425.Google ScholarPubMed
Kendler, KS (2005). ‘A gene for …’: the nature of gene action in psychiatric disorders. American Journal of Psychiatry 162, 12431252.Google Scholar
Kendler, KS (2008). Explanatory models for psychiatric illness. American Journal of Psychiatry 165, 695702.Google Scholar
Kendler, KS (2009). An historical framework for psychiatric nosology. Psychological Medicine 39, 19351941.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, KS, Baker, JH (2007). Genetic influences on measures of the environment: a systematic review. Psychological Medicine 37, 615626.Google Scholar
Kendler, KS, Gatz, M, Gardner, C, Pedersen, N (2006). A Swedish national twin study of lifetime major depression. American Journal of Psychiatry 163, 109114.Google Scholar
Koob, G, Kreek, MJ (2007). Stress, dysregulation of drug reward pathways, and the transition to drug dependence. American Journal of Psychiatry 164, 11491159.Google Scholar
Koob, GF (2009). Neurobiological substrates for the dark side of compulsivity in addiction. Neuropharmacology 56 (Suppl. 1), 1831.Google Scholar
Meehl, PE (1986). Diagnostic taxa as open concepts: metatheoretical and statistical questions about reliability and construct validity in the grand strategy of nosological revision. In Contemporary Directions in Psychopathology (ed. Millon, T. and Klerman, G.), pp. 215231. Guilford Press: New York, NY.Google Scholar
Murphy, D (2006). Psychiatry in the Scientific Image (Philosophical Psychopathology). MIT Press: Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Russo, SJ, Mazei-Robison, MS, Ables, JL, Nestler, EJ (2009). Neurotrophic factors and structural plasticity in addiction. Neuropharmacology 56 (Suppl. 1), 7382.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sass, H (2007). The German Anthology of Psychiatric Texts. World Psychiatric Association: Chene-Bourg, Switzerland.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, KF (1993). Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine. The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL.Google Scholar
Shi, J, Levinson, DF, Duan, J, Sanders, AR, Zheng, Y, Pe'er, I, Dudbridge, F, Holmans, PA, Whittemore, AS, Mowry, BJ, Olincy, A, Amin, F, Cloninger, CR, Silverman, JM, Buccola, NG, Byerley, WF, Black, DW, Crowe, RR, Oksenberg, JR, Mirel, DB, Kendler, KS, Freedman, R, Gejman, PV (2009). Common variants on chromosome 6p22.1 are associated with schizophrenia. Nature 460, 753757.Google Scholar
Sullivan, PF, Neale, MC, Kendler, KS (2000). Genetic epidemiology of major depression: review and meta-analysis. American Journal of Psychiatry 157, 15521562.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, BC (1976). To save the phenomena. Journal of Philosophy 73, 623632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, RA, Barker, MJ, Brigandt, I (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics 35, 189215.Google Scholar
Woodward, J (2003). Making Things Happen. Oxford University Press: New York.Google Scholar
Zachar, P (2000). Folk taxonomies should not have essences either. Philosophy, Psychology and Psychiatry 7, 191194.Google Scholar
Zachar, P (2003). The practical kinds model as a pragmatist theory of classification. Philosophy, Psychology and Psychiatry 9, 219227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zachar, P (2008). Real kinds, but no true taxonomy: an essay in psychiatric systematics. In Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry: Explanation, Phenomenology and Nosology (ed. Kendler, K. S. and Parnas, J.), pp. 327355. Johns Hopkins University Press: Baltimore, MD.Google Scholar
Zachar, P, Kendler, KS (2007). Psychiatric disorders: a conceptual taxonomy. American Journal of Psychiatry 164, 557565.Google Scholar